conjuredSean Cubitt, The Cinema Effect [OCR PDF, 10.9 MB]170,862 Words:
The Cinema Effect
The Cinema Effect
Sean Cubitt
The MIT Press Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England
© 2004 Massachusetts Institute of Technology
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form or by any
electronic or mechanical means (including photocopying, recording, or infor-
mation storage and retrieval) without permission in writing from the publisher.
This book was set in Janson and Rotis Semi Sans by Graphic Compostion, Inc.,
and was printed and bound in the United States of America.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Cubitt, Sean.
The cinema effect / Sean Cubitt.
p. cm.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 0-262-03312-7 (hc. : alk paper)
1. Motion pictures—Philosophy. 2. Cinematography—Special effects. I. Title.
PN1995.C77 2004
791.43—dc21 2003046405
10987654321
For Terry, Orlando, Eliza, and Sue
Acknowledgments viii
1. Entrée: The Object of Film and the Film Object 1
Part I: Pioneer Cinema 13
2. Temporal Film: The Pixel 14
3. Magical Film: The Cut 42
4. Graphical Film: The Vector 70
Part II: Normative Cinema 99
5. Total Film: Music 100
6. Realist Film: Sound 130
7. Classical Film: Dialogue 160
Part III: Post Cinema 189
8. Neoclassical Film 190
9. Neobaroque Film 217
10. Technological Film 245
11. Oneiric Film 273
12. Revisionary Film 300
13. Cosmopolitan Film 331
14. Outrée: Mediation and Media Formation 359
Filmography 367
Notes 383
References 399
Index 445
Contents
Acknowledgments
This book was commenced during and could not have been achieved with-
out a research fellowship in the School of Television and Imaging at Dun-
can of Jordanstone College of Art and Design at the University of Dundee
in the first months of 2000. My thanks especially to Steve Partridge for
inviting me, and to Jo Coull, Peter Estgate, Mike Stubbs, Simon Yuill, and
the staff of the Visual Research Centre at Dundee Contemporary Arts. To
my friends and colleagues at Liverpool John Moores University especial
thanks, most of all to Warren Buckland, Trevor Long, Nickianne Moody,
Tom Moylan, Yiannis Tzioumakis, Lydia Papadimitriou, and Corin Willis.
Moving to Aotearoa, New Zealand, in the middle of the project was greatly
eased, and the creative thinking that has gone into it subsequently has been
immensely enriched, by my colleagues in screen and media at the Univer-
sity of Waikato: Ann Hardy, Craig Hight, Stan Jones, Anne Kennedy, Geoff
Lealand, Suzette Major, Mark McGeady, Maree Mills, Alistair Swale, and
Bevin Yeatman. I also owe much to conversation, that most delightfully end-
less of all human activities, with John Armitage, Jonathan Beller, Eddie
Berg, Michael Bérubé, Sue Clayton, Tom Conley, David Connearn, Ed-
mond Couchot, Rachel Dwyer, Stuart Evans, Mike Featherstone, Jane
Graves, John Grech, Susan Hiller, Steven G. Jones, Thierry Jutel, Eduardo
Kac, Douglas Kahn, Ryszard Kluszinski, Jim Lastra, Geert Lovink, Tara
Macpherson, Janine Marchessault, Laura U. Marks, Margaret Morse, Tim
Murray, Steve Neale, Bethany Ogden, Daniel Reeves, Katarina Sarakakis,
Zia Sardar, Brian Shoesmith, Yvonne Spielmann, Kaspar Straecke, Mike
Stubbs, Petr Szepanik, Tan See Kam, Patti Zimmerman, and many more. A
draft of part of chapter 2 was published in Wide Angle21(1), and of chapter
11 in Aliens R Us: The Other in Science Fiction Cinema, edited by Ziauddin
Sardar and Sean Cubitt, Pluto Press, 2001. Early versions of various parts
of the text were presented the University of Illinois Urbana–Champaign;
the Society for Cinema Studies conference, Chicago; the University of
Dundee; the Cultural Studies Association of Australia at the University
ofTasmania, Hobart; the University of Volos, Greece; the National Film
Archive, Wellington; Roskilde University, Denmark; the University of
Toronto; the Association of Art Historians Body and Soulconference, Edin-
burgh University; the School of the Art Institute of Chicago; the Water-
shed, Bristol; Sheffield Hallam University; the Institute for Popular Music
at the University of Liverpool; the Screen Studies Conference, University
of Glasgow; Oxford University Computing in the Humanities Centre; the
Centre for Contemporary Art, Warsaw; Trinity College, Cambridge; Uni-
versity of Technology Sydney; Gasteig, Munich; the Royal College of Art,
London; the Centro Nacional de Arte Moderna Reina Sofia, Madrid; the
Centre for Contemporary Art and the Academy of Fine Art, Prague; and the
Central St Martins School of Art, London. An especial debt of gratitude to
the Centre for Audiovisual Studies at the Masaryk University of Brno,
Czech Republic for the opportunity to review the theses contained here
with them, and to the British Council for their support of that visit.
The manuscript was completed with the aid of research grants from
theFaculty of Arts and Social Sciences at the University of Waikato. Spe-
cial thanks for images are due to Donald Crafton, Vinu Vinod Chopra,
Katherine Oakes of the BFI Stills Library, and the New Zealand Film
Commission.Patrick Ciano, Chrys Fox, Judy Feldmann, Doug Sery, and
my anonymous reviewers at the MIT Press made production a lively and
challenging process.
A
ck
n
ow
le
d
gm
en
ts
|
| ix |
In some sense all cinema is a special effect.
—Christian Metz
I want to know what cinema does. If it causes no effect, however ornery or
belated, cinema doesn’t do anything, and there is left only the question of
what it is or, more exactly, what it fails to be. Cinema does something, and
what it does matters. Cinema’s first effect is to exist. Yet like everything else
it has trouble existing, and the effects it produces—images and sounds, di-
mensions, durations, sensations, understandings, and thoughts—all share
aquizzical and oblique relation to reality. Certainly you could measure
physiological dilations and palpitations to ascertain the reality of a film’s
emotional clout. But there is something fictive, something uncanny, or
something that, however marginally, fails the reality test in even the most
engrossing films, and perhaps in them most of all. Studying special effects
has led me to an odd little problem that has turned out, over the years we
have spent together, to be fascinating and revealing companion: the prob-
lem of the object of cinema.
Like most of my generation I went to school with Western Marxism
and psychoanalytic semiotics, and their overriding concern with subjectiv-
ity. The greatest film analysts outside that tradition have grappled with the
phenomenology of cinema. Bazin (1967, 1971) and Deleuze (1986, 1989),
revisited in recent years by Sobchack (1992), Bukatman (1994, 1998, 2000),
and Marks (2000), address sensation and what we do with it. Between sub-
ject and sensation lies the puzzling and enticing question of the object.
Somewhere in the action of perceiving, the endlessness of sensation is or-
dered into a unity that can be recognized as an object, and in that same act,
1
ENTRÉE: THE OBJECT OF FILM
AND THE FILM OBJECT
| |
the subject comes to be as the perceiver of the object. Simple, if mysterious,
this process, which lies among other things at the heart of the sociocultural
process of “othering,” has become utterly central to the mediated world we
live in.
I take it as a premise that communication is the fundamental activity of
human beings, that socialization, sexuality, trade, labor, power, and status
are all modes of communication, and that in our period the dominant
medium of communication is no longer face-to-face interaction but the
commodity. To ask the question about the object in our day is to ask about
the mysterious entity it has become, and to inquire into the changing nature
of the commodity form that came into being with capitalism and whose per-
mutations in and of the communicative herald, I believe, its eventual col-
lapse. The historical study of the object of film is then also a study of the
evolution of the commodity form. Drawing inspiration from Marx’s found-
ing insight into commodity fetishism, this book speaks to the materiality of
mediation, the object status of the media through which, so often, we en-
gage with our objects, as cinematographers, critics, and audiences.
Between sensuous inhabiting of the world and the elaborations of
meaning, there is the necessary stage in which the world is “othered,” “ob-
jected,” its flux categorized into identifiable objects thrown apart from any
consciousness of them. Marx adds the vital thought that this process has a
history. People have not always and everywhere made or exchanged objects
in the same way. In the hundred years or so since the invention of moving
pictures, that exchange has occurred more and more in the form of media
whose microhistory is also a microhistory of the commodity, from industrial
use value through the society of the spectacle (Debord 1977), to the virtual
objects of data exchange. Of all media, the popular cinema can claim to
reflect “the social characteristics of [people]’s own labour as objective char-
acteristics of labour themselves” (Marx 1976: 164–165). Labor is a com-
modity, a thing that can be exchanged. It is a mediation, a material form in
which communication goes on between people. Labor, cinema, and com-
modities are media, each of them proper to a particular epoch of history.
Communication is fundamentally human, but therefore also fundamentally
historical. To investigate a medium is to analyze and synthesize the histor-
ical nature of the material mediations that characterize a period in time.
Film is uniquely situated to reveal the inner workings of the commodity,
| 2 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
|
since it was for most of the last century the most popular, as it is now still the
most strategic medium. Cinema has art’s capability for analyzing its own be-
ing without, among the films addressed here, the embarrassment of having
undermined it.
Guiding the inquiry into the cinematic object has been the cryptic but
inspiring conception of firstness, secondness and thirdness developed by
C.S. Peirce. Peirce himself noted the symmetry of his triad with Hegel’s
being, essence, and notion (Hegel 1975: 5–6), and with Kant’s categories.
These concepts are especially fascinating because they are relational (Peirce
1958: 383): they concern, for the purposes of this writing, the relations be-
tween sensation, cognition, and comprehension. Think, for example, of a
football game. In the first instance there is only grass, air, milling figures. In
the second there are the structures defining the action: the goals, the bleach-
ers, and the touchline—and the apperception that identifies all this as “the
game.” Third is appreciating the significance of the running—the strategic
pass, the lightning dart, the feint, the skill and grace of a game well played.
I use the terms pixel,cut,and vectorhere, both to anchor the discussion in the
material of film, and to shape the whole as a retrospective historiography of
images in motion from the standpoint of the digital era, written for a digi-
tal audience.
Karl Brown gives a sense of the Wordsworthian delirium of the early
period. Griffith explains what he wants for a shot in Broken Blossoms:
“I want a river... a misty... misty river...” His long, sensitive hands were
molding the picture that he was seeing with his inner eye. “A river of dreams...
the Thames as Whistler or perhaps Turner might have painted it, only it must
be a real river, do you understand? A real river, flowing, endlessly flowing, car-
rying destiny, the never-ending destiny of life on its tide. I must see that flow,
that silent flow of time and fortune, with all the mystery of unknowable future
there to be seen and yet not to be seen...” The vision vanished, and with it the
poetic spell. He asked, in his sharp, penetrating, directorial voice, “Do you
know what I mean?” (Brown 1973: 216–217)
Brown describes the trough used for the river, the flash powder dropped
into give it sheen, the electric fan, the lead weights wired to the flat cut-
out luggers to keep them upright in the breeze. He adds artisanal pride
| 3 |
Th
e
O
b
je
c
t
o
f
F
i
lm
a
n
d
t
h
e
F
i
lm
O
b
je
c
t
|
in inventing the techniques of miniature set photography to the already
doubled demands the director makes of him, to be at once realistic and mes-
merizing. Such triple consciousness informs the digital viewer, alert to the
mechanisms of illusion, delighted by their effectivity, and entranced by their
developments. This book contends that the same triangulation shapes the
cinematic object.
States of schizophrenia are native to film’s present-absence, its not-
quite-existence, its fictionalization of truth and its verification of illusion.
For Kant, “This fundamental principle of the necessary unity of appercep-
tion is indeed an identical, and therefore analytical proposition; but it never-
theless explains the necessity for a synthesis of the manifold given in an
intuition, without which the identity of self-consciousness would be incog-
itable” (Kant 1890: 83). Now, self-consciousness is indeed “cogitable,” but
is it necessary? The axiom that communication is human may lead to indi-
vidual human communicators, but it need not, since selfhood is a derivative
of communication, a special effect of a particular historical mode of com-
munication. Since self-consciousness is no longer a given but an effect, syn-
thesizing the myriad sensations that crowd upon us into recognizable
identities is also in question. I am thus never sure whether what I perceive is
raw phenomenality, abstract identity, or synthetic truth. To that extent this
work deals also with the sense of self as that arises in the division of object
from subject in the relationships with light particles in time, the horizon of
the screen, or cinema’s represented worlds. These relationships are un-
stable, I argue. For this reason, it is important to distrust the normative
thrust of statements like this:
This... compromise between deep space and selective focus typifies main-
stream style today. The eclecticism introduced at the end of the 1960s and
canonised in such films as Jaws and The Godfatherseems to have become the
dominant tendency of popular filmmaking around the world. Long lenses for
picturesque landscapes, for traffic and urban crowds, for stunts, for chases, for
point-of-view shots of distant events, for inserted close-ups of hands and other
details; wide-angle lenses for interior dialogue scenes, staged in moderate depth
and often with racking focus; camera movements that plunge into crowds and
arc around central elements to establish depth; everything held together by
rapid cutting—if there is a current professional norm of 35mm commercial film
style around the world, this synthesis is probably it. (Bordwell 1997: 259–260)
| 4 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
|
Bordwell’s strategy here is to establish as normative the practices of the
North American film industry, and to derive all other filmic styles from that
norm (in the pages that follow, for example, he describes the film style of
Angelopoulos as “dedramatizing,” as if the dramatic were the norm from
which Angelopoulos’ films are an aberration), thus leaving space neither for
film styles independent of the North American industry nor for dialectical
currents within the normative style itself. The historian must be alert to dif-
ference as much as to similarity, and the materialist historian has also the
ethical duty to watch out for contradiction and alternatives. Aumont and his
colleagues note that “film analysis must be very detailed in order to be fruit-
ful or even accurate” (Aumont et al. 1992: 77). Normative criticism may be
a necessary phase in the establishment of film studies as a university disci-
pline, but its priority of the model over the actual is only an example of how
to construct a filmic object. Our task here is to take Aumont’s suggestion,
and to work at a moment prior to the constitution of either the model or the
represented as a given. We have to start, then, not with things but with re-
lationships and especially with change.
The moving image moves. But where does that movement come from?
For a certain approach in art history, an image is a discrete, whole entity. To
move from one image to another is already an immense wrench: even the
analysis of a diptych is wildly complex. What then is it to speak of “a” mov-
ing image, constructed from thousands of constituent images? In what sense
is it animage? Cinematic movement is a fundamental challenge to the con-
cept of wholeness and integrity, its becoming a test of the primacy of exis-
tence. In particular, it raises the question of temporality: when is the object
of cinema? When, indeed, is the moving image?
For although it is the most ancient of all the arts, the moving image is
also the most modern. Its relation to the commodity fetish becomes only
more apparent in the mysteries of its origins. Before it was technological,
before history began, there were firelight and shadows, gestures of the
shaman, strides of the dancer, puppetry of hand-shadows cast on the walls
at the rough dawn of consciousness. In these oldest arts, the immediate
world became image, an altar, for a god or a throng of gods to inhabit. Of
those millennia of tragedy, sacrifice, and dream, not a shred remains. His-
tory begins with recording, the records that start with the preparation of
spaces for bodies and light. Pigment stains adapting the accidents of geol-
ogy, carved modification of rockfaces, the petroglyphs of the Cave of the
| 5 |
Th
e
O
b
je
c
t
o
f
F
i
lm
a
n
d
t
h
e
F
i
lm
O
b
je
c
t
|
Bison inscribe before the event what would remain long after it. More frag-
ile and corruptible than even rock paintings, we no longer or scarcely pos-
sess wooden artifacts of the Stone Age, but looking at the stone figurines of
the Cyclades, we can catch hints of a coeval culture of carved dolls passed
hand-to-hand among the tribe, a precursor of the more intimate and seden-
tary arts of television. Film, however, begins in the public scale of torchlight
processions through Altamira, the play of sunlight, moonlight, and dappling
cloud on the stained glass windows of medieval Europe, the fireworks and
waterworks of the Baroque (rendered cinematic in Anger’s Eaux d’artifice)—
one more reason to be delighted that the Lumière brothers should be named
for light.
In the painted caves of Lascaux, the temporary community of ritual at-
tains continuity through repeated returns to the same marked space. Their
time is no longer only the experience of the moment but an ordering of
action. This ancient ordering is the founding principle of all those arts
that devolve on the movement of bodies through illustrated space. Disney
World mimics the passage through the sculpted cave in times set aside
from the ordinary. In a more banal vein, the same itinerary through illu-
minated places marks the traverse of airports, the guided meander through
supermarket aisles. From monumental statuary and triumphal arches (War-
ner 1985) to Benjamin’s arcades (Buck-Morss 1989) and the protocinema
ofrailway travel (Schivelbusch 1980), the stillness of the image and the mo-
tion of the body become characteristic forms of modernity. The comple-
mentary form, movement of the image and stillness of the body, begins,
ifwe are to believe Boal (1974), in the Greek drama with the distinction be-
tween performer and spectator. The protocinemas of the masque, the melo-
drama, and the magic lantern add the spectacle of technique. Cinema and
itsassociated media merely industrialize the stasis of the audience in the
movement of the image. Perhaps one day, perhaps soon, there will be an art
of moving bodies and moving images. Perhaps, as Virilio (1994) argues, we
are moving instead toward a world of static bodies and stationary images.
The magic of cinema, cinema as special effect, arises from this intertwin-
ingof relations of movement, scale, distance, and repetition, from this an-
cient history of time. But there is also the modernity of cinema to consider,
the specificities of time in the age of capital and of globalization.
Image and transport technologies, revolutionized in the nineteenth
century, instigated new relationships with time as fundamental as those be-
| 6 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
|
gun in the transition from prehistory to recorded time (Kern 1983). Both
Paul Virilio (1989) and Friedrich Kittler (1999) suggest that cinema must be
located in the twinning of media and military technologies. As Siegfried
Zielinski argues, however, reiterating the assertion made earlier by Lewis
Mumford (1934: 12–18), nineteenth-century military and media technol-
ogies both depended for their mechanization and automation on the logi-
cally and chronologically prior development of the clock (Zielinski 1999:
72–74). The new armaments and logistics of the Maxim gun and the tank,
like the new network of rail and telegraph, like the structured time of the
shutter, derive both technologically and conceptually from the mechanized
measurement of time. Without the mass-scale precision engineering re-
quired by the popularization of watches and clocks in the 1870s, the ma-
chine gun, the railway schedule, the production line, the cash register, and
the cinematograph are not thinkable. The splitting of human action into
mechanically discrete movements, the atomization of economic and bu-
reaucratic flows into distinct and quasi-autonomous, even meaningless key-
strokes on the adding machine and typewriter, the Taylorization of work at
Ford’s River Rouge plant all spring from the same imagining of time as a dis-
crete series of steps. And yet, although the cinema has the discretion of a
chronometer, it also struggles with other temporalities, some coming into
being, some fading from their old hegemony. However important the addi-
tion of the second hand to mass-produced watches, it alone cannot account
for the opening up of microscopic, infinitessimal times, or the mise-en-
abymeof the commodity fetish as it spiraled into spectacle. The proletari-
anization of chronometric time and its extension from the workplace to the
world of pleasures and reproduction brings it into a dialectical realm of con-
tradictions and disputations. Reform movements in the last decades of the
nineteenth century shortened the working week across Europe and North
America, producing the new phenomenon of surplus time, a time that now
fell to the emergent entertainment industries to commodify. Indeed, by the
late 1920s it would become apparent that the time of consumption was as
vital to economic growth as the time of production.
The first part of the book looks at this first period, focusing on France
in the decade after 1895. I propose here three elementary aspects of the
moving image corresponding to Peirce’s categories and derived from the
mathematical foundations of digital media. I want to supplant the meta-
phors of film as language pursued by Metz (especially 1974a, b) and film as
| 7 |
Th
e
O
b
je
c
t
o
f
F
i
lm
a
n
d
t
h
e
F
i
lm
O
b
je
c
t
|
psychology pursued by Bordwell (1985, 1989), with a more digital analysis
of the mathematical bases of motion. This choice of terminology comes with
an admission that like all histories this is a retrospective. Because cinema so
clearly traces a history from mechanical to digital time, I have tried to indi-
cate that the shifting temporalities of the commodity film have neither
ceased to change nor mutated into something utterly different in the digital
era. In the work of the Lumières, Méliès, and Cohl, it is possible to descry
the distinctive qualities of cinema as an autonomous medium. That auton-
omy would survive scarcely a handful of years, perhaps even less. Within
months of its invention, film had become a commodity, and its unique on-
tology embarked on its long dialectical relation with the larger world.
The second part leaps over the rich innovations of the first thirty years
of the twentieth century to engage with the sound cinemas of the 1930s.
Once the technical difficulties associated with the innovation of synchro-
nized sound were resolved around 1929 (Crafton 1997; Gomery 1980), the
cinemas of the 1930s began to move swiftly through experiments to secure
stable modes of operation. As Terry Smith puts it, “The urges to disorder
and totality of the competing modernities of the 1920s, dreams/projections
then, seek generalization, institutionalization in the mid-1930s. They seek
to control the social gaze—in short, to govern” (Smith 1993: 161). Mack
Sennett’s life at Keystone (Sennett 1967) and Griffith’s actresses’ at Bio-
graph (Gish 1969; Griffith 1969; Pickford 1955) seem full of joyful inven-
tiveness. In Ben Hecht’s sour account of the classical studio era (Hecht
1954), governance has triumphed in the stabilization of new cinematic
norms. Control over patents, cartelization of research and development,
market domination of supplies to the film industry (e.g., in film stock and
lights; Winston 1996: 39–57; Bordwell 1985: 294–297), and the increasing
role of the banks in film financing (Wasko 1986) all supported a growing
monopolization of the photomechanical and nascent electronic media
(Mitchell 1979a, b). A parallel monopolization occurred in 1934 in the
tyranny of social realism, when both Hitler and Stalin embraced it as the art
of the state (Hitler 1968; Zhdanov 1992).
The third part moves to the postwar period. Slow motion, freeze-
frame, steadicam, bullet-time: across three decades, cinema moves toward a
spatialization of time. This process is refracted through other dialectics as
well: order and entropy, local and global, analog and digital. Dadoun’s de-
| 8 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
|
scription of Hollywood in the 1930s is premature: it was in the postwar pe-
riod that “While being subjected more completely than anything else to the
constraints, the rules and ideas of the economic system, the cinema projects
the delusion of being an autonomous world, above reality, concerned only
with the higher pursuit of image-making” (Dadoun 1989: 46). The 1940s
are the hinge on which all arguments concerning the power to depict must
pause. The Holocaust was not the largest genocide undertaken by the Eu-
ropean empires, nor the most complete. It names more than the deaths of
the Poles, Romanies, homosexuals, Communists, and Jews: it names also, in
ways we are still learning to articulate, the massacres of slavery, the ethno-
cides in Tierra del Fuego, Tasmania, and Newfoundland, the slaughter of
the Aborigines, the destruction of the First Americans and on and on and
on. No attempt to write historically, not one written by a European, can be
taken seriously unless it confronts this vacuum into which the dream of ra-
tional Enlightenment descended.
Far from making reference impossible, the camps made it essential, the
metaphysical task of cinema, for a period that is only now coming to an end.
This is one reason the realist and total cinemas sometimes appear confused
in works like Imitation of Life.The demand that we weep is not negotiable,
when Mahalia Jackson sings. To some extent we are impelled to empathize
with a world that only ever knows too late how great we were (Neale 1986),
so that the film invites us to live a posthumous fantasy. Imitationis not itself
a fascist film, but it is a film that reveals fascism through fascism’s aestheti-
cization of politics. The totalitarianism of Eisenhower-era North America
is not just depicted in the enclosed deep-staging; it is voiced as loss in the
language of Riefenstahl, applied now to living rooms and kitchens that look
like the direct heirs of Albert Speer’s architecture of light. The cinema itself
became more than an alibi: it was the allegorical building where dreams and
aspirations went to die.
The postwar world began to pose in new ways another Kantian aes-
thetic, the division of the beautiful from the sublime. Beauty is, in The Cri-
tique of Judgment, a common thing, shared and social. Beauty is ephemeral,
a property of things that change, mature, are lost: a lover, a landscape, a work
of art. Beauty is our highest expression of what it is to be mortal. It speaks
of history, it speaks of the future, and therefore it speaks ethically. The sub-
lime, at the opposite pole, speaks of a life unbounded by the horizon of
| 9 |
Th
e
O
b
je
c
t
o
f
F
i
lm
a
n
d
t
h
e
F
i
lm
O
b
je
c
t
|
death, perhaps without the stain of birth: the timeless time of the universal.
The sublime endures outside history, and its permanence is a presence that
overwhelms the everyday contingencies of history. As absolute and unques-
tionable presence, the sublime exceeds and stands aside from the world. The
opposite of beauty, which, in its becoming, perpetually confronts the world
with its ephemerality, sublimity antedates sociality. Sublimity hails us as
unique: it is an elitism. Beauty hails us as common: its roots are democratic.
The confrontation of beauty and sublimity is an ethical issue: media democ-
racy or media elitism. Beauty confronts ugliness: sickness, squalor, brutal-
ity, things that can be changed. The sublime stares into the unchanging maw
of evil. The sublime addresses us phatically: like a demanding child, it posits
the interlocutor, the individual in the audience, as its other. The individual
it hails is intensely personalized and thus abstracted from the social world,
but also lifted out of language and thus without a name. Beauty calls to us
across what is shared; to empathy, to sympathy, to common taste, common
sense, and common knowledge. Its ephemerality addresses itself to the com-
mon fate, embracing forgetting as the necessary partner of becoming. Beauty
is communicative, then, while the sublime is the voice of the incommuni-
cable, the supernatural, the secret knowledge of the anonymous elect, even
though that elect is made up of every audience member who has ever suc-
cumbed to the lure of totality in the late Eisenstein or his heirs.
At issue here is the status of the audience and of “media effects.” The
common editorial and legal line that blames the media is based on the prem-
ise that there is an individual prior to mediation on which the media oper-
ate. Yet neither societies nor individuals are conceivable without language,
that is, without mediation. The opposite case, now general in cultural stud-
ies, privileges the subject over the object, presuming that there is a fully
formed personality on whom the latest media message impinges only tan-
gentially and late. But the problematic of the cinematic object demands that
we countenance the mutuality of their construction: that audiences consti-
tute the media that constitute them in a dialectical antagonism of mutual
creation, mutual annihilation, and that this is entirely true to the shifting na-
ture of the commodity relation in which it is no longer producers’ labor but
consumers’ attention that is bought and sold.
The sublime in this perspective is entirely comprehensible as a function
of the commodity form as it strives to colonize what little is left of the world
| 10 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
|
to commodify. The sublime and innocent effect, incongruously and uncon-
sciously evoked in Lyotard’s (1978) essay “Acinema” in the figure of the child
playing with matches, belongs to an order of time from which narration, de-
pendent on time’s passing and its loss, is debarred. It is the time of the fetish.
The cinematic sublime constructs an apparatus for the imitation of death,
that zero degree of speech, and so becomes an object of awe, an event that
contradicts its own existence. That is the source of the sacramental inno-
cence of cinema: the pretence of a timeless and universal order of commu-
nication bordering our own structures as supernatural and universal, the
commodity form of communication in our time.
The spectacle was only ever one of the possible worlds that might have
emerged from the investigation of time in film. From the earliest films,
The illusion of motion, with its consequent sensations of temporal flow and spa-
tial volume, provided enough innovation for spectators already familiar with a
range of spectacular visual novelties. If cinema’s blend of spatiotemporal so-
lidity and metamorphic fluidity was largely assigned to the representation of
narrative, these effect[s] of the medium nevertheless remained central to the
experience. Special effects redirect the spectator to the visual (and auditory and
even kinaesthetic) conditions of the cinema, and thus bring the principles of
perception to the foreground of consciousness. (Bukatman 1998: 79)
Distinctions between realism and illusion make no sense in an epoch when
it was neither the illusion of life nor the illusion of illusion that fascinated
but rather the spectacle of their making. The fascination of these experi-
ments on the raw material of time is not the collusion of cinema in the hege-
mony of commodity capitalism and emergent consumerism, but the fact
that the new device took on at once an anima of its own, aspiring to “more
and better freedom” (Bauman 1999: 1) than the freedom of free trade.
The evolving combinatorics of cinematic time’s elementary dimensions
begin to alter the dimensions themselves, providing insight not only into
how the cinema has been, but into what it may become. The task of theory
today is no longer negative. The job of media theory is to enable: to extract
from what is and how things are done ideas concerning what remains un-
done and new ways of doing it. As the poet Hopkins put it in a letter to
Robert Bridges, “The effect of studying masterpieces is to make me admire
| 11 |
Th
e
O
b
je
c
t
o
f
F
i
lm
a
n
d
t
h
e
F
i
lm
O
b
je
c
t
|
and do otherwise” (Hopkins 1953: 210). Discovering the temporalities of
film is as close as we get to understanding the why and wherefore of com-
modity fetishism as it has developed over the last hundred years. It is the ar-
gument of this book that we must look into this secret and bizarre space of
the commodity to understand the terms under which mediation functions
in our epoch, and therefore to understand the conditions under which we
can make the future otherwise than the past or the present.
| 12 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
|
| Part I |
Pioneer Cinema
Leaving the Factory: A Myth of Origin
For the Uncreated is that whose beginning does not exist; and Noth-
ing, we say, is that whose beginning does not pre-exist. Nothing con-
tains all things.
—Otto von Guerricke1
Picturing Leisure
The first and most special of all effects is the depiction of motion, an event
as dizzying as the invention of perspective in the Quattrocento. What hap-
pens when the still photograph begins to move? On the morning after the
first public projections, La Poste’s review of December 30, 1895, invited its
readers to “Imagine a screen, placed at the end of a room as large as one can
wish. This screen is visible to a crowd. On the screen appears a photographic
projection. So far, nothing new. But, suddenly, the image, lifesize or re-
duced, is animated and springs to life” (Ministère des affaires étrangères
1996: np). From this description, it sounds as if viewers saw (whether or not
the Lumières engineered) a still projection that suddenly came alive, in a
moment of amazement. The novelist Maxim Gorky would note the same
thing the following summer:
When the lights go out in the room in which Lumière’s invention is shown,
there suddenly appears a large grey picture, “A Street in Paris”—shadows of a
bad engraving. As you gaze at it, you see carriages, buildings and people in var-
ious poses, all frozen into immobility. All this in grey, and the sky above is also
grey—you anticipate nothing new in this all too familiar scene, for you have
2
TEMPORAL FILM: THE PIXEL
| |
| 15 |
Te
m
p
o
ra
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
P
ix
e
l
|
seen pictures of Paris streets more than once. But suddenly a strange flicker
passes through the screen and the picture springs to life. (Gorky 1950: 407)
The projection of still photographs had been a staple of the magic
lantern long enough to be banal. The Lumières and their itinerant projec-
tionists used the familiarity of slide projection to lull their audience into
comfortable inattention, before zapping them with the new apparatus, to re-
actions of wonder and amazement that we can only imagine. This chapter
analyzes the moment of movement as the miraculous first effect of cinema,
the instigating moment of cinema as special effect.
According to the editors of the Lumières’ letters, the first public screen-
ing at the Salon Indien “was probably like a cocktail party” (Lumière and
Lumière 1995: 94). Shown in the festive period between Christmas and New
Year, with twenty sessions a day between 10:00 A.M.and 1:30 P.M.,the cine-
matograph attracted a crowd of flâneurs from the Boulevards. Clément
Maurice recalled, “What I remember as being typical was some passer-by
sticking his head round the door, wanting to know what on earth the words
Cinématograph Lumière could possibly mean. Those who took the plunge
and entered soon reappeared looking astonished. They’d come back quickly
with a few friends they’d managed to find on the boulevard” (ibid.).
This little description tells us that the cinematograph instantly took its
place as a distraction for the strolling crowds, that it participated from the
start in what Tom Gunning (1989) identifies as “an aesthetic of astonish-
ment,” but also that the subjectivity it promoted was not only flexible and
mobile but also significantly social. The dynamism of the cinematograph as
event, rather than narrative, induces its spectators not to anchor themselves
as the narrated objects of a screen performance, but to mobilize themselves
as hectic and excited participants in an event that leads them not to con-
templation but to sharing. It is a brief moment of innocence before the reg-
ulation of cinema into an industrial formation, an Eden from which the
stories of good and evil would soon eject it. But it is vital to an understand-
ing of cinema’s utopian capabilities that we acknowledge how, in this form-
ative instant, it was able to activate rather than absorb its audiences.
Between 1894 when the first filmstrips were exposed and 1896 when
Gorky witnessed it, the Lumière cinematograph was anchored not in liter-
ary or popular genres of the novel and theater but in the crowd. Social,
public, and active, the event of cinema articulated the modernization of
urban experience. On the one hand, this belongs to the expansion of com-
modity capitalism into the sphere of leisure, a market the cinematograph
screenings on the Boulevard des Capucines during the holiday season were
designed to exploit. But on the other hand, there is also a relation, technical
but also thematic, to utopian innovations in concepts of perception. The
Lumières’ first film is exemplary in this respect. Familiarity has worn away
the strange choice of subject matter: workers, in the first instance, and work-
ers not working, or arriving for work, but leaving the brothers’ factory and
setting off for their own, unregulated pastimes. The theme of the first movie
is the crowd at leisure. Whether or not, as seems possible, the camera was
concealed during the making of both versions (accounts of the March screen-
ing refer to a horse-drawn diligence; both La Posteand Le Radical mention
voitures;current prints show neither), the remarkable modesty of the shot is
apparent. No one hams to camera as in other Lumière films, even though
there are some gestures and movements that suggest that some of the em-
ployees are aware of being visible, not to the camera but to one another. The
informality of the scene, however arrived at, is an unstaged event, a moment
of liberation (from work) in a framing characterized by liberation from for-
mal pictorial composition and formal theatrical staging, and from the uni-
fying and artificially coherent vision of academic painting and commercial
melodrama. Inured to endless closed-circuit TV, we have lost the astonish-
ment that ought to greet this mode of picturing and this choice of material:
why would the first film ever made picture workers leavinga factory?
Although it seems to us so ordinary as to be invisible, the picturing of
factory workers at leisure was the result of almost fifty years of struggle to
legitimate images of daily life. Linda Nochlin notes how the politically rev-
| 16 |
C
h
ap
te
r
2
|
olutionary Pissarro was committed to the unsentimental demands of mod-
ernity, communicated in the “direct, vivid, matter of fact” way in which he
depicts the railway in Lordship Lane Station, Upper Norwood(1871), when
compared with the flamboyant romanticism of Turner’s or Monet’s treat-
ments of similar subjects (Nochlin 1991: 64). Baudelaire asserted the hero-
ism of modern life in 1846 (Blake and Frascina 1993: 81–82), but twenty
years later, in 1868, the painter Boudin, a teacher of Monet’s, still had to de-
fend his decision to paint middle-class people in everyday dress:
The peasants have their painters of predilection... and this is good: these men
carry on sincere and serious work, they partake of the work of the Creator and
help Him make Himself manifest in a manner fruitful for man. This is good; but
between ourselves these middle-class men and women, walking on the pier
toward the setting sun, have they no right to be fixed on canvas, to be brought to
light? (Boudin, quoted in Nochlin 1966a: 83–84)
The painting of contemporary peasant life had itself developed only
slowly as a respectable subject for art. Initially only Italian peasants were
permissible subjects. Between the Paris Universal Expositions of 1855 and
1867, the veil of the exotic was dropped and it became possible to exhibit
scenes of rural life in France (Brettell and Brettell 1983). Boudin’s complaint
was that if the peasantry were suitable subjects, why not the bourgeoisie?
The answer was, in part, that the peasantry could be represented as natural:
naturally poor, of course, but also naturally in harmony with the seasons and
with God. For artists like Boudin and the Impressionists, the introduction
of industrial buildings, fashionable clothing, and the urban poor into the
landscape, or the emergence of the cityscape as a motif, made way for a dif-
ferent kind of harmony, one that no longer had a place for the premodern
pieties of agrarian Catholicism. Pissarro would make a specialty of depic-
tions of peasant life, again focused on moments of idleness snatched from
the demands of an emergent capitalist agriculture. But even the Impres-
sionists had trouble depicting the working class: Caillebotte’s sinewy, sweat-
ing floor-scrapers laboriously lifting layers of varnish is a rare example. Even
in the 1890s, it is startling to see the Lumières make the choice to debut
their new device with an image of the industrial proletariat.
The Sortie des usines (figure 2.1) is usually dated 1895, but Louis Lu-
mière himself reported shooting it during August of 1894. Since the workers
| 17 |
Te
m
p
o
ra
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
P
ix
e
l
|
are clearly wearing summer clothes, and the strong noon sunlight of high
summer beams down casting only a short shadow from the tree under which
the camera has been placed, we can presume a summer shoot. The film was
first shown on March 22, 1895 (though Davanne’s letter of March 26 seems
to suggest a prior projection in Lyon [Lumière and Lumière 1995: 16]): there
seems little reason to doubt Lumière’s word. Other scenes taken between
then and midsummer 1896 include a family scene, street scenes, views of
work in progress (The Demolition of a Wall), transport scenes, landscapes
andseascapes associated with family holidays, and formal occasions (see
Rittaud-Hutinet 1990 for a complete listing). Only the Arroseur arrosé, a
brief tableau of a naughty child standing on a hosepipe and being spanked
by the gardener for his troubles, resembles genre painting. The others are
resolutely scenes of everyday life in the modern world among the bour-
| 18 |
C
h
ap
te
r
2
|
| Figure 2.1 |
Workers Leaving the Factory:lunchtime sunlight, the pursuit of leisure, and the utopian freedom of
thebicycle. Courtesy BFI Collections.
geoisie, showing their work and their leisure, with a strong emphasis on
technological achievements. It is intriguing to note how different these sub-
jects are from the content of the contemporaneous Edison films of 1894 and
1895. There we find an immediate conforming of cinema with the enter-
tainment industry, from party pieces like Fred Ott’s Sneezeto Annabelle Ser-
pentine Dance(reprised the following year by American Mutoscope, and later
filmed again by the Lumières). We could argue that the Lumières fore-
grounded the process of film, while Edison already grasped the commercial
potential of the medium (see Punt 2000: 35–68 for an extended compari-
son). Alternatively, in a familiar if by now largely discredited argument, we
might perhaps be tempted to see the Lumières as the fathers not of film but
of documentary.
But what is documented in the cinematic event? We might want to ar-
gue that it is not the event in the world, which seems to be related rather than
documented, but a specific aspect of the event. The frames themselves, in
Thierry Kuntzel’s account, are not what we watch; rather, “In the unrolling
of the film, the photograms which concern us ‘pass through,’ hidden from
sight: what the spectator retains is only the movement within which they in-
sert themselves” (Kuntzel 1977: 56). There is a curious foreshadowing of
this perception of cinema in one of the first newspaper accounts of the cin-
ematograph: “It is life itself, it is movement taken from life” (“C’est la vie
même, c’est le mouvement pris sur le vif,” La Poste,December 30, 1895, reprinted
in Ministère des affaires etrangères 1996: 16). The Postejournalist appears
confused. Is this life? Clearly not: it is a picture of life. In fact, it is move-
ment abstracted from life. But the contradiction makes sense if we under-
stand the two uses of the word “life” in slightly distinct ways: life, “le vif,” the
living aspect of life, is movement, which is brought by the cinematograph
from life into the cinema. Thus what cinema “documents” is not “la vie” but
“le vif,” not the world as object but movement. The Sortie des usinesis not a
documentary but a magical transformation, and one effected not on the
world but on a reality inclusive of both world and film. Deleting still pho-
tography’s claim to truthful knowledge of an external world in favor of a
metaphotographic technology of movement, the cinematic event empha-
sizes that the world is not the object of a cinematic subject, but that both are
part of the same process: le vif.The cinematograph is put into motion by the
contradiction between work and leisure, at the moment at which one ends
and the other begins. Cinematic time originates in the dialectic between the
| 19 |
Te
m
p
o
ra
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
P
ix
e
l
|
discrete movements of the factory’s clock and the fluidity of the flâneur’s
aimless drifting.2
These were, of course, not just any workers, nor purely hands whose
loyalty and diligence their bosses could show off to the Sociéte d’Encourage-
ment pour l’Industrie Nationale,to whom they would first be shown. They were
also workers at Europe’s most important manufacturer of photographic
plates: specialists in the art being used to picture them. Not just an industry,
but a cutting edge, high-tech industry at the brink of its most explosive pe-
riod of growth. Louis and Auguste Lumière had taken over management of
the plant from their father a few years before and turned around a specialist
local firm to become major European and international players. But they
were enlightened employers, establishing at their own expense generous
pension funds and benefits. Good Marxists will point out that the workers
had paid for the brothers’ wealth in the first instance, but Lyons at the time
was the center of a syndicalist politics that promoted the joint participation
of workers and bosses in reform and welfare, and the Lumières were hon-
ored for their pioneering of occupational pensions and workers’ welfare.
Is it possible to read the choice of the noon remission from labor as a
theme derived from the utopian socialism of the 1890s? These suggestions
for understanding an unusual choice of theme—the promotion of the firm,
respect for high technology, celebration of class solidarity—can be placed
alongside others, such as the possibility that this was the easiest spot to find
a lot of motion on the day the camera was ready for testing, all of which priv-
ilege the intentions of the authors of the film. As technologists first and
artists second, the brothers may not have cared what they filmed. But it is
significant that, unlike Marey’s chronophotography, the Lumière cinemat-
ograph was not turned immediately to anthropometric time and motion
studies, aimed at optimal mechanization of gesture in the factory, but to
leisure, to the immediately accessible utopia of time off. These girls caught
leaving the factory at the end of their shift (figure 2.2), in an innocence of
movement that never after could recur in front of the camera, these careless
boys on their bikes, these never to be repeated familiarities, all at the edge
of a leisure that cannot be remade or recorded: these are as much visions of
immanent utopia as Pissarro’s sleepy peasant girl idly playing with a stick, so
indistinguishable from her land in the 1881 Jeune fille à la baguette.
The anonymity of the workers not only underwrites the anonymous so-
cial subject formed in the cinematic event. Abstracting movement from life,
| 20 |
C
h
ap
te
r
2
|
le viffrom la vie, does away with uniqueness. There is of course the possi-
bility of there having existed several versions of a similar film, probably shot
to replace a damaged experimental roll. There is also quite separately the
aesthetic of repetition. Not only is the film always already a repetition of a
profilmic event; not only is it ready to be shown over and over; not only is it
a series of very nearly identical frames; but the event it records takes place
daily, and though every day in a unique manner, nonetheless also in some
degree every day the same. What we have is a unique exemplar, something
at once singular and typical.
Once again the Sortieamazes and delights: to have placed at the instiga-
tion of cinema’s dialectic of difference and repetition not a story but an event
that is at once an end—of work—and a beginning—of leisure—neither of
| 21 |
Te
m
p
o
ra
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
P
ix
e
l
|
| Figure 2.2 |
Workers Leaving the Factory:Women high-technology workers in department store fashions.
Courtesy BFI Collections.
which is visible, and neither of which is therefore composable as an equilib-
rium. In place of closure, we have only commotion, a document not of truth
but of the space between truths. The only truth of cinema is its movement,
its ephemeral occupation of the present. It is here that we lose the distinc-
tion between fiction and documentary, the depiction of diegetic and exter-
nal worlds, in the cinematograph, since both will depend on the uniquely
credible aspect of the movies: that they move. The cinematic event cannot
claim absolute truth, as photography had done. But neither does it deny all
possibility of truth, as Przyblyski (1995) argues of Appert’s propagandist
photomontage.3Instead it insists on the revelation that truth is imperma-
nent and exists not even in flashes but as the stuff of movement itself: time.
That this is also the stuff of fictions and lies is a matter for later chapters.
Fiat lux
The Sortieis an account of unstable movement: it lacks the narrative char-
acteristic of conforming actions to either desire or understanding. If any-
thing, the viewer is subjected to the disparate desires of the crowd of
workers. At the same time, it lacks a compositional center around which to
organize our viewing. Despite the square-on view (also used in the Arrivée
des Congressistes à Neuville-sur-Sâoneof March 1895; much the same is true
of the dramatic diagonal of the Arrivée d’un train), the description-baffling
busyness of the scene, the ways in which the near-anonymous figures move
according to their own multiple and complex motivations, asserts the inde-
pendence of the image from a composing eye. The autonomy of the ele-
ments of composition, the relative freedom of the viewer who returns to the
same short reels of crowd scenes with constantly new patterns of looking,
this anarchy of vision imitates the Impressionist move from the beaux-arts
tradition of hierarchy toward “all-over composition,” seeking attention
democratically for every area of the frame. Simultaneously, the image slips
away from the organizational control of narrative. A small experimental
proof: whereas narratives are largely memorable, in the sense that we can re-
construct a fiction after viewing it, I defy anyone to rehearse from memory
the activities figured in the Sortie des usines.
In the early days, films could be copyrighted only as collections of indi-
vidual photographs. It was only later that it became possible to copyright
not the frames themselves but the idea behind them, typically a story (Gaud-
reault 1990b). Then the organized succession of images became not just
| 22 |
C
h
ap
te
r
2
|
property but the thing itself, and even the script was sufficient to copyright
the film, regardless of the visual form it might take. Until then, we can still
see cinema in its utopian moment: the very halt and judder of the early
“flickers” that severs the frames from one another, emphasizing the discrete
quality of each moment at which the shutter opened to seize its fifteenth of
a second of light. The physical processes of perception were both beneath
the threshold of sight and just visible at its edges (Noël Burch [1990: 48]
makes much of the bourgeoisie’s dislike of this flicker-effect with its dis-
jointing of one impression from another: their complaints of eye strain, we
might say, arise from the effort they put in to trying to force the incoherent
to cohere, to hierarchize the democratic). These images—in England we
still use the plural form when going to the pictures—take the everyday apart
and figure forth, even in their linear and chronological ordering, the anar-
chy of light that makes the positive construction of objects positively un-
thinkable. We might say of the temporal raster effect of the frameline what
Krauss says of the widespread use of the grid in modern art, that it demon-
strates “its hostility to literature, to narrative, to discourse.... it is antinat-
ural, antimimetic, antireal” (1986: 9); save only that in cinema, as in the
wider modern visual culture, the struggle between the literary and the visual
remains a central contradiction. Film not only opposes the presumption of
a “natural” vision that sees the “real” world as an assemblage of objects: it
proposes another, synthetic vision.
Like the spots and dots of the divisionist aesthetic practiced by Seurat,
Signac, and Pissarro in the 1880s and 1890s, the frames of the Lumière
cinematograph fragment vision beyond the point of narrative perception.
Louis Lumière attended the March 22 meeting of the Société d’Encourage-
mentto project slides produced using the brothers’ new autochrome color
photographic process. The cinematograph made its debut at the conclusion
of the lecture as an example of the progress being made in other fields of
photography (Lumière and Lumière 1995: 17). The autochrome would be-
come a major product for the Lumière business, a line they would continue
to market long after they left the cinema. It would become the leading color
product of the day: Flaherty (2000) mentions using autochrome during the
shoot for Nanook of the North;Edward Steichen would use them throughout
World War I and into the early 1930s.
The autochrome was the result of several years of research on the part
of the brothers, at first jointly with Gabriel Lippman, later Nobel laureate
| 23 |
Te
m
p
o
ra
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
P
ix
e
l
|
for his analyses of the solar spectrum, who presented the first results of their
work in May 1892. These first plates required several hours exposure. By
1893, when they exhibited their results in Geneva the Lumières had reduced
the exposure time to four minutes. However, the Lippman process proved
intractable to industrial production, and the brothers embarked on a new
route, “indirect photography,” which would be marketed from 1903 as the
autochrome and would remain dominant in the field until the invention in
1930 of colors more reliable than aniline dyes that enabled the marketing of
Eastman-Kodak’s Kodachrome, itself first marketed as movie film (Rosen-
blum 1989: 449–450). Among those with whom they discussed the progress
of their works were Louis Ducos du Hauron, who wrote in a letter of June4,
1892:
I shall never forget that, nearly a quarter of a century ago, you were good
enough to sponsor my invention at the Société Française de Photographie on 7
May 1869.... Will [printers] not soon be able to produce immense quantities
of my three-colour photographs? I am certain they will. Then shall all contro-
versy end and the late lamented Charles Cros and I shall be fully acknowledged.
(Lumière and Lumière 1995: 7–8)
Cros and du Hauron had discovered separately and simultaneously in
1869 a three-color additive process akin to that which the Lumières even-
tually adopted for the autochrome. Du Hauron was never a successful man,
but the brothers had established him with a pension of 1800 francs a year.
Cros was a poet, an inventor, and a friend and portrait subject of Manet. All
three played a major part not only in the history of color photography but,
with Lippman, in the development of color theory generally, and especially
in the evolution of new concepts of color among the divisionist painters
around Seurat (see Rewald 1978: 134–135). It would be redundant to re-
hearse the narrative of cinema’s debt to the technologies of optical toys and
visual spectacle discussed by Oettermann (1997), Ceram (1965), and Da-
gognet (1992), or in terms of the commodification of leisure addressed by
the contributors to Cinema and the Invention of Modern Life(Charney and
Schwartz 1995), Friedberg (1993), and many others. Without wishing to
minimize the importance of these findings, and in fact in parallel with them,
let me note that the attempt to understand why the Lumières chose their
factory hands as their first motif has already led us into the neighboring field
| 24 |
C
h
ap
te
r
2
|
of avant-garde painting. Situating the Lumières as inventors of the auto-
chrome puts them in another excellently modernist context, the scientific
and artistic quest for an elementary understanding of light.
The proximity of the artistic, scientific, and cinematic realms in the
emergence of this atomist optic is well summed up in Fénéon’s account of
Seurat in “The Impressionists in 1886”: “his immense canvas, La Grande
Jatte, whatever part of it you examine, unrolls, a monotonous and patient
tapestry: here in truth the accidents of the brush are futile, trickery is im-
possible; there is no place for bravura—let the hand be numb, but let the eye
be agile, perspicacious, cunning” (Nochlin 1966b: 110). Cinematic tech-
nique comes out in the sense of unrolling, the agility of the eye rather than
the hand, the lack of the flamboyant “bravura” handling of paint that still
signifies emotional expression. The new, mechanical aesthetic beckons to-
ward egress from the impasse of the lonely Romantic artist. No longer
marked by artisanal cunning, the speed of perception waits to be standard-
ized at 24 frames per second.
Rosalind Krauss notes an even closer parallel to our conception of the
cinematic event when she notes that “the grid—as an emblem of the infra-
structure of vision” became “an increasingly insistent and visible feature of
neo-Impressionist painting, as Seurat, Signac, Cross and Luce applied
themselves to the lessons of physiological optics” (Krauss 1986: 15). This
granular severity could not be reconciled with an older Impressionism. Pis-
sarro, after a decade’s discipline in the scientific division of tones, found that
he could no longer reconcile his own anarchistic vision of the artist with the
new method, “having found,” he wrote to Henri van de Velde in a letter of
March 27, 1896, “that it was impossible to be true to my sensations and con-
sequently to render life and movement, impossible to be faithful to the so
random and so admirable effects of nature, impossible to give an individual
character to my drawing. I had to give up” (Nochlin 1966b: 59). The clash
was one not so much of two modes of painting, nor even of two politics.
Rather, we witness in Pissarro the struggle of rigorous modernity with an
older and still Romantic conception of the artist as the subjective center of
art, whose vision counts only insofar as it is deeply and intrinsically personal.
Of the options, the Lumières embraced the scientific mode. Although
many of the brothers’ own autochromes are clearly designed to demon-
strate the method’s ability to imitate the chiaroscuro technique of mold-
ing forms, many are equally clearly destined to be inspected across the
| 25 |
Te
m
p
o
ra
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
P
ix
e
l
|
whole frame. Such, for example, is the untitled autochrome of a young
woman picking flowers.4Herface obscured by her bonnet, she stretches
over an iron railing to pick blossoms against a pastoral hillside crowned
withploughed fields and a small village, behind her on the rough track a
bright red umbrella that gives a powerful optical contrast to the greens of
the landscape. The viewpoint emphasizes the diagonal of the railings in
theleft foreground, typical of the contingency celebrated in impression-
istétudes, rapidly sketched oils painted in the field, while the mixture of
modern ironwork with arcadian nature, of umbrella with dirt road, and the
clarity of textures across the whole image bring it sharply into the modern
aesthetic of Impressionism.
Brettell’s description of the disciplined way in which Pissarro handled
such motifs is illuminating: “The carefulness and technicality of the crafts-
man is replaced by the ceaseless experimentation of the representor. Sight it-
self is subject to continual scrutiny. Seeing, the most natural of faculties, has
to be learned” (Brettell 1990: 4). Brettell’s emphasis is confirmed in another
of Fénéon’s pamphlets, “The Impressionists at the Tuileries” of 1886: “These
painters [Pissarro, Seurat, Signac] are accused of subordinating art to sci-
ence. Instead, they only make use of scientific data to direct and perfect the
education of their eye and to control the accuracy of their vision” (Broude
1978: 39). Where the oil étude emphasized the contingent nature of the
artist’s position vis-à-vis his or her environment, Impressionism makes the
matter of seeing itself an issue. There is no innocent eye, and what is recorded
is not necessarily reality as it might be captured in a Dutch interior two cen-
turies earlier. The excess of the visible has become the excess of vision.
As with the autochrome of the woman picking blossoms, it is impossible
to find a unique focal point to the Barque sortant du portof 1895. The film of-
fers two focal zones: the rowers and the women and child watching them. Al-
though it is feasible to read the composition as triangular, it becomes so only
if the audience agrees to take up the position of the infant, who, guided by
the two women, watches the boat. But early audiences seem to have had a dif-
ferent interest. The success of similar films, such as Birt Acres’s Rough Sea at
Doverof 1895 and Bamforth and Company’s Rough Sea(c. 1900), suggests
that the sheer play of light on water, so meticulously sought after by Renoir
and Monet, was considered as precious as the human figure. The journalists
of both La Posteand Le Radicalsingle out the waves as special effects. In the
British Journal of Photographyof March 6, 1896, G.R. Baker, their regular
| 26 |
C
h
ap
te
r
2
|
columnist on projection and lantern shows, gives this account of the pièce
deresistance of the Lumières’ first London screening, at the Regent’s Street
Polytechnic, Sea Bathing in the Mediterranean: “here we have the breaking
waves on a shingly shore, a diving or jumping board, and the bathers in suc-
cession going down this board, jumping into the sea, battling with the break-
ers, climbing the rocks, and getting once more on the diving board, all so
faithfully to life that one ‘longed to be there’” (cited in Coe 1981: 71).
This delight in the naturalism of the cinematograph is echoed in a com-
ment elicited from The New York Dramatic Mirror by the first Lumière
screenings in New York: “The first view was A Dip in the Sea, and showed
several small boys running along a plank on stilts and diving into the waves,
which dashed upon the shore in the most natural manner” (Slide 1982: 65),
a comment that, like that of his London contemporary, emphasizes the il-
lusionistic aspects of the cinematograph. But Harry Tyrell, commenting
onthe same show, sees a different aspect: “Sea-waves dash against a pier, or
roll in and break languidly upon the sandy beach, as in a dream; and the
| 27 |
Te
m
p
o
ra
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
P
ix
e
l
|
| Figure 2.3 |
Workers Leaving the Factory:the dog saunters back toward the half-closed gates. Courtesy BFI Collections.
emotion produced upon the spectator is far more vivid than the real scene
would be, because of the startling suddenness with which it is conjured up
and changed, there in the theatre, by the magic wand of electricity” (ibid.:
67). Baker’s comments in the British Journal of Photographycontinue this line
of thought: the aspect of realism in the cinematograph that so impresses him
is the way in which several of the views “baffle description” (Coe 1981: 71).
This intensity of seeing evokes the drive toward a renovation of vision
in Impressionism. What the eye sees is, for Pissarro, not the world of ob-
jects, which begin to disintegrate in his already pixelated brushwork, but
light. Pissarro was, however, caught in a contradiction between truth to his
perception and truth to light. Seeking a clue to the translation from light to
pigment, the divisionists, like the Lumières, opted for the latter. This is in
particular why the first cinematograph films need to be seen in the light of
the schooled eye emerging from the dialectic of subjective impression and
objective optics. Pissarro’s works of this period, for example, only come into
focus as depictions when the viewer stands back from them, back further
than the painter could have done while applying the pigment. From his
point of view, at arm’s length from the canvas, what is being applied is not
an image of—of a blouse or a flower—but a specific and particular shade of
blue, or a dappling of colors selected to produce an optical mixing in the eye
of the beholder rather than the palette of the painter, a technique already in-
dustrialized in photomechanical printing in the 1890s.
In the same way, the autochrome analyzes the world as a manifold, not
of objects but of wavelengths. The cinematograph extends this spatial frag-
mentation of vision into the temporal by registering not things but the
movement of things, that movement which strikes its first audiences as at
once reality itself and a dream of reality. Where Burch (1990: 20–21) sees in
these early responses a Frankensteinian desire to suppress death, and Bazin
(1967: 9) sees a “mummy complex” that realizes an age-old desire to tran-
scend mortality, I would argue that the fragmentation of vision in first spa-
tial and then temporal terms is in fact an homage to life as animation, le vif.
It sacrifices possession of the world in favor of a dream condensing and dis-
placing film’s ephemeral truth of absolute movement, the underlying grid-
work of the dynamic present.
Peter Galassi comments on the Impressionist oil étudesthat they repre-
sent “an art devoted to the singular and contingent rather than the universal
and stable” (Galassi 1981: 25). Jacques Aumont concurs on the importance
| 28 |
C
h
ap
te
r
2
|
of ephemerality, but understands the address to “the fugitive and aleatory”
as “a new confidence in seeing as an instrument of knowledge” in the sciences
as well as the arts, specifically as “the acquisition of knowledge through ap-
pearances” (Aumont 1997b: 234). Elsewhere in the same volume James
Lastra comes much closer to the point of view expressed here when he con-
trasts 1890s photographic discourses of composition with early responses
tocinematography. Instead of attracting the criticisms directed at similarly
“undisciplined” still images, “films in which clouds and random motion pro-
liferated in unprecedented abundance represented a quantum leap in pic-
torial immediacy” (Lastra 1997: 273). Aumont’s gaze is still firmly fixed on
the photographic authority of the frame. But the open arms with which early
audiences greeted effects of water, smoke, steam, and dust suggest that it
was not the extension of empirical knowledge concerning objects in mo-
tion that interested them. That was the goal of Marey’s chronophotogra-
phy, but it does not describe the undisciplined nature of the composition in
fragmented light that the mobility of the frameline brings into play. Lastra
emphasizes the lack of a disciplining gaze, the absence of authority and its
delegation to the pure effect of motion.
As Dai Vaughan has it in his lyrical account of the Barque sortant d’un
port:“The unpredictable has not only emerged from the background to oc-
cupy the greater portion of the frame; it has also taken sway over the prin-
cipals. Man, no longer the mountebank self-presenter, has become equal
with the leaves and the brick-dust—and as miraculous” (Vaughan 1990: 65).
In that process, the presence of“Man”—in the person of the figure perched
on the stern of the boat who seems on the verge of being tossed from it in
the final frames of the film—is rendered as ephemeral as the motion of light
on the water. The effect is not, as Lastra suggests, “immediate” but tempo-
ral. It brings us into a new and properly cinematic relation with time.
The Cinematic Event
The time of the cinematic event is dispersed. Fragmentation in the compo-
sition of the Sortieproduces a dispersal of time, both as the random scatter-
ing of light-sensitive silver salts and in the roving, saccadic gaze that cannot
take it all in, alert to movements that can be attended to only one at a time
but that occur simultaneously. Cinema, in this first moment, encourages
both an analytic eye leaping from pinprick to pinprick of light, and periph-
eral awareness of movement as a blurred penumbra of the half-seen, whose
| 29 |
Te
m
p
o
ra
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
P
ix
e
l
|
detail escapes but which subsists as pure motion. The cinematic image is
nonidentical in the sense that events inside the frame are not only incom-
plete in time but fragmentary as percepts, so that each event of projection
evokes a new assemblage of focalized and marginal imagery. La Sortieis both
attraction and distraction, a locus of fine optical distinctions and simulta-
neously of a mobile, fleeting, and distracted gaze.
As attraction the cinematograph belongs to the new urbanity of the late
nineteenth century. The drain of populations toward the cities is both effect
and cause of their status as communication centers, financial or spectacular.
The attraction of the city is its energy, especially in the last decade of the
nineteenth century when the society of the spectacle is coming into being.
That society requires mass populations, which it will learn to individuate as
consumers, who will in turn, as fashionable flaneurs,not only communicate
but be communicated. The Sortiecoincides with this invention of the con-
sumer as leisured, modish, and mobile. But its charm and power derive from
its depiction of the disappearance of another moment, in which the workers
might return to their small holdings, darn socks, weed a row of vegetables,
feed their chickens. That self-sufficient remnant of the peasant economy
disappears in the cranking of the camera. From here on everyone, in Lyon,
in France, in the modern world, will be ready to be pictured. As Debord
argues (1977: ¶68), to become consumers, we must also be consumed; to en-
ter new modes of communication, we must be communicated. Once pho-
tography democratizes the portrait, everyone becomes a spectacular image.
In the cinematograph, the human vision of the audience is synchro-
nized with a machine perception in the process of formation. Designed as
camera, printer, and projector in one device, the cinematograph was at this
stage an instrument for rendering visible, and thus an instrument that pro-
foundly affected the visibility of the crowd. On the one hand, the Marey tra-
dition leads to the scientific uses of cinema for the analysis of events too big,
small, close, remote, fast, or slow for human perception; on the other, it cre-
ates the field of an omnivoyance that will enable both Merleau-Ponty’s op-
timistic phenomenology and Foucault’s pessimistic theory of surveillance.
At the same time that this “objective” vision was being formed, the cine-
matograph presented its audience with “the disintegration of a faith in per-
ception” (Virilio 1994: 16). One fragments the objects of perception, the
other perception itself. In the Marey tradition, analysis of vision leads to the
ideology of power over the object world; in the cinematograph, human and
| 30 |
C
h
ap
te
r
2
|
machine perception become mutually dependent, the human reconfigured
by the mechanical, the mechanical reliant on this newly decentered human
sensorium for its realization.
While it creates the possibility for an integral human-machine percep-
tion, however, the cinematograph also produces the myths of immortality
pinpointed by Burch and Bazin. To their reactions we might add the well-
known passage in which Gorky, attending the first screenings in Russia,
speaks of a silent and colorless realm of shadows, ghosts, and ashes. As he
castigates the immorality of the venue and the likely pornographic futures
of cinema, Gorky also adumbrates for the first time a sense of the cinema as
a machine for dreaming: “You are forgetting where you are. Strange imag-
inings invade your mind and your consciousness begins to wane and grow
dim...” (Gorky 1960: 408). At such a moment, the representational force of
the cinematograph is in question: the objects and the subjects dissolve in the
dissolving views offered by the interface between human and mechanical in-
trinsic to cinema. The analytical, Marey tradition is representational, in the
sense asserted by Gilles Deleuze, for whom representation “signifies this
conceptual form of the identical which subordinates differences,” a process
of “re-cognition,” rather than cognition or perception. In the cinemato-
graph, on the other hand, we are confronted with the possibility of a loss of
identity in both object and subject realms, gaining a sense of the uniqueness
of every instant of perception alongside the loss of self-presentation that
Vaughan observed in the Barque sortant.In Deleuze’s terms, “Every object,
every thing, must see its own identity swallowed up in difference, each be-
ing no more than a difference between differences. Difference must be
shown differing.We know that modern art tends to realise these conditions:
in this sense it becomes a veritable theatreof metamorphoses and permuta-
tions” (Deleuze 1994: 56).
As it occurred to Gorky at Aumont’s in Nizhny-Novgorod, the prolif-
eration of difference brings about a distracted state in which consciousness
fades and thoughts arise that are experienced as belonging to another. This
distracted gaze, this hypnotic trance induced in a spectator mesmerized by
the flickering of the nonidentical still exercises critics of television, console
games, and the Internet. Its emergence is not, Jonathan Crary argues, a
novel departure from an innocent and attentive consciousness. On the con-
trary, distraction is constructed in precisely those devices, like the cinemat-
ograph, that try to anchor consciousness in attention: “If distraction
| 31 |
Te
m
p
o
ra
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
P
ix
e
l
|
emerges as a problem in the late nineteenth century, it is inseparable from
the parallel construction of an attentive observer” (Crary 1999: 49). The
fragmentation that was intended to produce attentiveness also produces the
oneiric trance.
The trance is a timeless mode constructed in time. That contradiction
poses one of the fundamental problems of cinema: the problem of starting
and stopping. Elsaesser (1998a) sees in the teetering man in the closing
frames of the Barque sortanta moment of suspense constructed not only by
the abrupt end of the reel but by the framing. But whereas suspense in nar-
rative creates a concern for what happens next, for the distracted viewer sus-
pense comes from her solicitude for the wholeness of the experience that
stops without ending, without a motive or a signal from the represented as
to why the action stops. The effect of beginning is relatively easily con-
trolled in both the camera and the projector. But the end of the filmstrip is
not a function of the closure of an action, most clearly in the Barque sortant
but also in the Sortie.What is at stake, then, in the suspense of the ending is
not what happens next but what happened just now: how was that experi-
ence whole?
For Gorky the experience begins “when the lights go out”: in the dark-
ness out of which the moving image will flicker into the motion of becom-
ing from the stillness of existence. We spend much of the duration of a film
in darkness. Each frame is exposed twice, interrupted by the motion of the
shutter, which also cuts off the projector’s light while the frameline travels
across the aperture before the lens. So the frameline is doubly invisible, its
darkness hidden behind the repeated dousing of the lamp. The photo-
graphic image, and the single frame projected at the beginning of the
Lumières’ shows of 1895 and 1896, is a random spatter of light-sensitive
molecules. The still image would not become a grid until the invention of
the raster image, usually traced back to the radar monitors of World War II
(Buderi 1996). The moving image, on the other hand, begins life as a grid,
dependent on the accurate registration of the frame in front of the lens of
the camera-printer-projector of the Lumière cinematograph. Cinema starts
out as a raster display, but rather than a spatial map like the bit map of com-
puter images, it is a map of time. The frameline separating frame from
frame distinguishes between past and future, negative and positive time, so
that the frame itself, the present, appears as their pure difference, the mo-
ment of cinematic motion. In those graphs where one axis represents time,
| 32 |
C
h
ap
te
r
2
|
origin is marked as zero, neither positive nor negative but distinguishing be-
tween them. Because we look back from an age in which images are encoded
mathematically, and because in a digital age the humanities can no longer
afford to remain innumerate, the cinematic present, the frames we see on
the screen rather than the separating framelines that stay invisible, can be
considered as pixels, with the significant difference that these pixels are tem-
poral, not spatial. That cinematic present, like the point of origin of graphs,
can be given a number: zero.
Zero is not a quantity so much as a relation. We can attempt to identify
“4” as an essential fourness. But zero is not what it is—after all, it is null. On
the one hand, zero can be used adjectivally: “The number 0 is therefore
identified with the extension of all concepts which fail to be exemplified”
(Zalta 2000). For instance, you could say “there are no fairies at the bottom
of the garden,” because fairies “fail to be exemplified.” On the other, as a
noun, zero itself “fails to be exemplified”: “Since nothing falls under the
concept ‘not identical with itself,’ I define nought as follows: 0 is the num-
ber which belongs to the concept ‘not identical with itself’” (Frege 1974:
87). The concept of nonidentity reveals zero’s quality of internal difference.
Zero is a relation rather than a (no)thing because it is always already a rela-
tion of nonidentity with itself. Zero acts, rather than is, because of this in-
stability. And it acts in relation to the cardinal numbers (1, 2, 3..) because
it is the other to their identity. Nothing comes first in the beginnings of cin-
ema: zero is the nonidentity out of which the image arises, the difference
that surrounds, supports, and activates apparent motion, the instability of
the unmoving still image between what it was and what it will become.
Zero serves to denote origin in coordinate space, the point at which the
axes of graphs intersect. Traditionally placed at the center to allow for neg-
ative as well as positive values, zero is the relation between plus and minus,
existence and nonexistence. As origin, zero neither exists nor does not exist:
it is the privileged marker of difference. In the raster grid of bit-mapped im-
ages, origin stands in the top left corner of the screen, so that every point on
a computer display derives its address from that point, the pixel whose po-
sition is written “(0,0).”5 Each pixel address is symbolized by its distance
from zero, its difference from the nonidentical, the fullness of that appar-
ently empty address (0,0). As original difference, the absent pixel (0,0) of
origin is both essential and nonexistent. Its resultant instability is the per-
petual source of movement.
| 33 |
Te
m
p
o
ra
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
P
ix
e
l
|
Zero has also been the bottom line, the sum of balanced books since the
invention of double-entry bookkeeping in the first half of the fourteenth
century. As the relation between debt and credit, Micawber’s happiness, zero
is the point of equilibrium between positive and negative. Rather than a
simple absence of money, it denotes an even standing of income and expen-
ditures. This is the same zero as that which informs the first law of thermo-
dynamics, the law of the conservation of energy. In a stable system, energy
is neither created nor destroyed, and over time, whatever activities take
place, the sum of all gains and losses is always the zero of conserved energy.
It is vital to distinguish this zero from the “negative theologies” of absolute
absence that characterize a twentieth-century secularism for which “The
awesome and the gruesome no longer wear the anthropomorphic guise of
the most perfect being but take on that of a Void in whose regard our aspi-
rations are doomed to defeat” (Eco 1986: 93). The mathematical zero of
cinema read from the age of the digital image is not a zero of emptiness and
inactivity but its opposite: the sum of all activities. In this way a zero of com-
pletion complements the zero of origin. Combining the final conservative
zero of dynamic equilibrium with the zero origin of coordinate space, zero
extends throughout both equilibrium systems and Cartesian space. So zero
is the ground of pure relationality on which activity takes place. Without the
origin at zero, no drawing in coordinate space; without the divagations away
from and toward zero, no play of cash flow to induce film production.
This unseen and invisible continuum of the filmstrip that binds dis-
parate frames into a whole motion is, then, paradoxically, the continuum of
difference, zero not as void but as the sum of all differences. As temporal di-
mension, zero is neither adjective nor noun but verb: the null activity with-
out which the intermittent flashing of images would not become the illusion
of movement. Virilio fears we have usurped this “zero time” from God: “For
God, History is a landscape of events. For him, nothing really succeeds any-
thing else because everything is co-present” (Virilio 1996: 9), a simultane-
ity that we mortals can experience only diachronically. Avant-garde films are
occasionally exhibited in galleries mounted as filmstrips fixed to lightboxes.
The paradox of this kind of exhibition is that the moving image has no pres-
ence, whereas the strip itself, to which we remain oblivious during projec-
tion, can be reconstructed as a presence but only at the cost of losing its
movement. Virilio’s God sees the filmstrip, not the film. As divine and
changeless present, the frameline as we see it in those lightbox displays can-
| 34 |
C
h
ap
te
r
2
|
not act but can only be. A gallery exhibition of motionless frames is like a
museum case of pinned butterflies: lovely but dead. In the divine presence,
their life is stilled and their zero becomes void. Yet this zero time, which
from God’s seat looks like the static copresence of all times, is for us the
principle of a difference that the One God cannot perceive. And the reason
He cannot perceive it is His self-identity. Only those for whom identity is
incomplete and othered, those whose subjectivity, in other words, is non-
identical, is zero, can inhabit time rather than regard it.
The zero time of the frameline that shapes the time of cinema is in turn
shaped by a constitutive quirk of human beings: what separates us from di-
vinity is that the divine is self-sufficient, where we are incomplete. Although
we are used to saying “One says,” perhaps more correctly we should say “No
one says” to recognize this internal differentiation, this unstable lack of to-
tality and equilibrium that makes it impossible to be at home with oneself
alone, and makes us social. Cinema in its infant moments is profoundly hu-
man in just this sense. There is no still frame. In the Lumières’ earliest films,
every image is an unstable nonidentity seeking equilibrium among the so-
ciety of images that precede and follow it. Rather than breathing the puff of
life into still photography, cinema ends the discipline of the single image
that contains in itself, in Coleridge’s phrase, the reason why it is so and not
otherwise. The moving image is always otherwise. Its radical instability is
both a quality of a technology achieving its autonomy from the human (its
superhuman speed of perception) and a subjectivity attaining its autonomy
from identity. Even though, in the decades following its invention, the cin-
ema was turned toward domination and the closure of communicative net-
works, the relational principle—relations of technology to image, image to
image, subject to subject, image to subject, subject to technology—governs
all of cinema’s futures.
Against Narrative
Cinematic time originates in zero’s dynamic equilibrium. Cinema thus does
not represent time but originates it. At this foundational stage, then, we can
no longer share Bazin’s (1967) and Kracauer’s (1960) proposals that cinema’s
destiny was the depiction of the world. A rival and widespread school of
thought sees narration as the essential model of cinematic duration, and
cinema as a machine for telling stories. Now a major theme of film and cul-
tural research, narratology is nonetheless at once too narrow a focus and too
| 35 |
Te
m
p
o
ra
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
P
ix
e
l
|
broad a concept to provide us with an insight into the multiple ontological
temporalities of films. It may indeed be true that, as Deutelbaum (1979) ar-
gues, the Lumières’ first film of the workers leaving the factory can be read
as a narrative beginning with the opening of the gates and concluding with
their closing, but this seems to force attention toward what the film is, to the
detriment of looking at what it does. Deutelbaum’s argument is more stim-
ulating than his conclusion. He elaborates on an intensive formal organisa-
tion in the early Lumière films, emphasizing their sophisticated structuring
of space and their use of repetitions, mirroring, framing and staging in
depth. La Sortie des usines Lumière,for example,
nearly returns the scene before the camera to the state at which it was when the
film began. Both at the beginning and the close, the cinematic image offers only
the exterior of the factory seen from the same point of view. So similar in ap-
pearance are these opening and closing images to one another, in fact, that if one
were to loop the film into a continuous band, the action would appear to be a
single periodic event. (Deutelbaum 1979: 30)
This sense of structure, apposite to the rediscovery of early cinema in the
late 1970s by filmmakers of the structural-materialist avant-garde, is, how-
ever, betrayed by the conclusion that this symmetry is in fact narrative.
Defining structure in duration through the Aristotelian categories of begin-
ning, middle and end, as Deutelbaum does, gives an adequate description of
a film whose duration matches the opening and (incomplete) closing of the
factory gates. But as a definition of narrative, it is too general to be inform-
ative in the analysis of a particular film. To attempt to deploy the methods
of any major school of narratology, from Propp to cognitivism, in the anal-
ysis of the Sortie des usineswould be misguided, since the film’s “story” is by
any standards minimal and its duration too brief to allow the definition of
narrative functions that such analyses require.
Moreover, despite the excellence of his observations, Deutelbaum gives
the game away when he notes that the conclusion “nearly returns the scene”
to the beginning. In fact, the two frames are not symmetrical. Not surpris-
ingly, since there is only one shot and the camera is stationary, opening and
closing frames are “similar in appearance,” but in my copy the gates do not
close: two gates open, but only one is swung partly back into the closed po-
| 36 |
C
h
ap
te
r
2
|
sition, while the door on the left of the screen opens but is not closed. Mean-
while, the man who opens the gate disappears in the crowd, but he can be
seen half in shot standing next to a woman in dark skirt and blouse at the ex-
treme right-hand side of the last frames, a space unoccupied in the opening
frame. There are some other gaps in symmetry, notably between the man in
an apron who runs out with the dog, and the man in a dark blousonwho runs
back with it. Moreover, given the bicycle’s identification at that time with
mobility, freedom, and health, the four bicycles that pass through the gates
suggest to this observer at least that there is an element of anarchy, of un-
stable dispersal, which the critical attempt to narrativize the film circum-
scribes and erases.
In a response to Deutelbaum, Gaudreault (1990a) offers to distinguish
between the two modes of organization represented by the Arrivée d’un train
à La Ciotat at one extreme and L’Arroseur arroséat the other, with the Sortie
des usinesmidway between. Gaudreault’s case is that there are two modes of
narration, a primary micronarration at the level of the shot and a secondary
level created through the articulation of shots, something that of course
does not occur in the Sortie.The distinction is an important one: narrative,
in the generally accepted sense of the word, is an effect created through spe-
cial techniques. Unfortunately, Gaudreault also argues that the articulation
of time in the shot is predestined to produce this secondary level of narra-
tion: cinema is “a machine which is doomed to tell stories ‘for ever.’ This
special feature of the cinema, that of always having been narrative right
from the beginning, explains why this art, which ‘has narrativity built into
it’ so quickly found its vocation as storyteller” (Gaudreault 1990a: 71; citing
Metz 1974a: 118). Such twenty-twenty hindsight recreates the past in its
own image: because we know cinema came to be dominated by narrative fic-
tions, therefore it must have been narrative all along.
Second, Gaudreault’s definition of the content of a shot as narrative
calls on a definition of narrative so general as to be nearly universal. He cites
a definition from Jacques Aumont and his collaborators that makes narra-
tive indistinguishable from either representation or duration: “if a state-
ment relates an event, a real or fictitious action (and its intensity and quality
are of little importance), then it falls within the category of narrative” (Au-
mont et al. 1983: 77). On this definition, flicking a switch is narrative. This
is a kind of theoretical imperialism, enforcing a narrative frame on events
| 37 |
Te
m
p
o
ra
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
P
ix
e
l
|
that, in film as in reality, frequently have no definite beginning or end. Such
a universalizing definition of narrative blurs Gaudreault’s initial distinction
between telling and showing.
We can clarify the distinction by describing what we have presented to
us in the Sortie des usinesas an event. In the first instance, we should restrict
our understanding of the formal organization of this event to the simple
fact that it has duration. In the Lumières’ first films, that duration is iso-
morphic with the duration of an external time enacted for the camera, but
even that shared shape depends on the rate of projection and the problem of
stopping. The cinematic event is, then, not identical with an event in the
real world: it relatesreal or fictitious events, as Aumont’s group argued quite
correctly and precisely. The verb “relates,” however, should be understood
to mean “establishes a relationship,” not as “tells a story.” To relate is to make
a statement, and so far as a statement presumes someone to whom it is ad-
dressed, relating first and foremost establishes a relation. In Gaudreault’s
own term, early cinema’s statements are monstratory: they are events of
showing. Certainly one can assemble cinematic events into a narrative. But
equally one can assemble them to make a pattern, or even jumble them to-
gether at random. It is important to recognize that narrative is neither pri-
mary nor necessary to cinema, and it forms no part of any putative essence
of the medium.
Narrative, then, is not an essential quality of film, but only a potential
and secondary quality arising from the production of time in the differenti-
ation within and between frames. To misunderstand this leads to a more se-
rious mistake, that of endowing the discrete machinery of cinema with the
illusory attributes of continuous flow. It is exactly the lack of continuity, the
fragmentation of flow into discrete and manageable packets, that not only
allows cinema to work and be perceived working, but also, as internal insta-
bility, produces the possibility for narrative as a mode of address, one among
the many relations that cinema produces. In the first films, I want to argue,
that mode of address can be envisaged by analogy with the remaking of
numbers as nouns rather than adjectives. In Brian Rotman’s account, this
arises specifically from the semiotics of zero:
by drawing attention to the failure of the anteriority of things to signs in the case
of itself (what possible prior “thing” can it be referring to?) zero demolishes the
illusion of anteriority for allnumbers. Once zero enters the scene numbers...
| 38 |
C
h
ap
te
r
2
|
must instead be considered... to be elements of a system createdby zero; or
rather created by the counting subject whose presence as a signifying agency
zero witnesses. (Rotman 1987: 96–97)
Here zero is both a numerical sign within the system and the origin
ofthat system, both in formal terms and as the “witness” of an indefinite
andanonymous counting subject. Analogously, the frameline, the invisible
darkness out of which motion pictures achieve their motion, addresses an
indefinite, anonymous, distracted subject in the first films; the frameline is
a subject of motion itself, inhabitant of a time that is genuinely isomorphic
with the time of projection (in a way in which projection is not isomorphic
with the world depicted in the filmstrip). Narrative cinema also depends on
the prior existence of this zero subject of motion, but the zero subject does
not necessarily imply the subject of narrative as its sole outcome.
Rotman argues, in the passage just cited, that the introduction of zero
made it apparent that no number depends on the existence of an external
world to which it must refer. By the same token, the cinematic event, as a
process of perpetual change, does not depend on a prior external world. The
loss of a transcendent referent for numbers and for film might at first glance
appear to produce two entirely self-sufficient, indeed simulacral systems.
But the loss of transcendence is an ontological rather than an epistemolog-
ical event. What alters is the status of the external world (the countable or
the profilmic), which is posited no longer as the transcendent source of the
system, but instead as an integral element of it. Theories of film that see it
as referring essentially to an external world entail that film transcends its
own materiality by referring to something that transcends and predates it.
Likewise, privileging narration suggests that film transforms nonnarrative
reality into an essence—narrative—that enjoys an existence outside the cin-
ema. Over these transcendent essences, I want to prioritize the material of
film, the reality of film itself. The filmstrip neither has nor lacks a transcen-
dent origin, whether external reality or narration, that lies anterior to it.
Film and world are of the same matter. Demanding that the one represent
the other not only creates the distinction between the two; the thesis of cin-
ematic realism ensures that either the world or the cinema is condemned to
unreality. Likewise, if all film is narrative, then it is to that extent not film
but something else. Without a material theory of film we have no grounds
for distinguishing what in film is narrative and what is not.
| 39 |
Te
m
p
o
ra
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
P
ix
e
l
|
In Rotman’s argument, the place of the counting subject is marked by
the number zero. The equivalent place in perspective painting is marked
bythe vanishing point, rendering the subject as “optically specified and dis-
embodied” (Bryson 1983: 96). In cinema, the dark transport of the film-
stripundermines the subject as timeless being, specifying in its place a
constant process of coming into being. Cinematic zero inscribes the dy-
namic equilibrium of spectatorship as unfinished process. The subjects of
nineteenth-century medical, police, and social photographic archives (see,
e.g., Cartwright 1995; Gunning 1995a; Jordanova 1989; Sekula 1986; Tagg
1988) were promised whole and discrete moments of indexicality, like Vi-
rilio’s “landscape of events.” Scientists, police officers, and bureaucrats por-
ing over the files believed that power over images translated into power over
the world. By contrast, because every frame of a film is incomplete, it can-
not produce that imperial or bureaucratic gaze. Against the tyrrany of sci-
entific certainty premised on the distance between observer and observed
and the fixity of their relationship, the cinematograph constitutes the viewer
as temporal and temporary subject of the procession of images.
Narration tends toward a gestalt.6The goal of narration’s subject is its
own completion in the contemplation of the completed narrative, a goal of
closure and fixity. The cinematic event tends toward incompleteness. Its
subject is constituted in the ephemeral movement from frame to frame, mo-
bile and unfixed. This fleeting cinematic subjectivity already existed in
modernity’s drift (see Charney 1998), the flâneurcelebrated in Benjamin’s
(1973b) account of Baudelaire. Baudelaire’s “dandy” was always implicitly
male and leisured. The workers leaving the factory are female and work for
a living, but they are also of that first generation to visit the Bon Marché and
wear the new affordable fashions. The high-tech industry of photographic
manufacture celebrated by the cutting edge technology of the cinemato-
graph captures the feminization and democratization of drift. The system-
atically differed/deferred subjectivity of the urban nomad is the newly
democratic subject of the cinematic event. Unlike Edgar Allen Poe’s Man of
the Crowd, translated by Baudelaire, with his hyperindividuated sense of
alienation, the democratic subject of the frameline is social, from the mo-
ment of the first projected films. Against this social, democratic, and unfixed
subjectivity, narration sets itself the task of constructing a temporal system
that can contain that drifting mobility. Seeking to return cinema to a tran-
scendent origin it will reveal as gestalt, narrative conjures up identity as a
| 40 |
C
h
ap
te
r
2
|
method for controlling the unfixed dynamic of the event, and by implication
the democratic upwelling. The cinematic event La Sortie des usinesis neither
a self-sufficient system nor subordinate to a prior, transcendent narrative or
representational truth. Instead, its dynamic equilibrium brings us face to
face with a dynamic zero subjectivity.
Movement starts in nonidentity, the unstable zero pixel at origin. End-
ing movement begins the task of instigating identity in cinema. Ending is
not only temporal but spatial, both the cutting edge of the frame, as in El-
saesser’s account of the Barque sortant,and the cut that identifies the shot by
defining its difference from other shots. The cut that inscribes identity into
the cinema is itself a difference that proliferates difference. At the end of the
Barque sortant, in stoppage time, we confront the jolt of awareness that arises
from the sudden need to establish the gestalt of the film, a renewed atten-
tiveness, but one that also promotes a further oneiric distraction from what
is at hand to what has gone before. It is as if cinema were, in this brief in-
stant, still preconscious, emerging, dazed and entranced, into a mode of
communication that may still have the power to renew not innocent and
primordial but artificial and social perception. With the emergence of
cinematic time as special effect, we enter the universe of the synthetic.
| 41 |
Te
m
p
o
ra
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
P
ix
e
l
|
3
MAGICAL FILM: THE CUT
| |
A Slice of Life
Nothing is visible without light.
Nothing is visible without a transparent medium.
Nothing is visible without boundaries.
Nothing is visible without colour.
Nothing is visible without distance.
Nothing is visible without instrument.
What comes after this cannot be learned.
—Nicholas Poussin, 16651
The Cinematic Object
The story of how the magician took over the laboratory is probably apoc-
ryphal. One day, Méliès’s camera jammed. When it was restarted, the movie
changed a bus into a hearse, and the men into women (see, e.g., Sadoul 1973:
390–391). The accuracy of the story is less important than its status as the
canonical origin of stop-motion: the myth that the new art of trick shots
owed its creation to purely mechanical contingency. In this chapter, I will
argue that Méliès’s accident at one of the great crossroads of the Paris of
theBelle Epoque is, like a Freudian slip, the result of an unconscious over-
determination by new global cultural flows, by new spectacular forms of the
commodity, and, not least, by the internal logic of cinematography.
As Aumont and his collaborators argue, Méliès “did not really use edit-
ing principles,” rendering his films “at best mere successions of tableaux”
(Aumont et al. 1992: 46). Méliès displaces rather than repositions, synthe-
sizes, or assembles, or any of the other principles of editing. Instead, he cuts,
not just between but within frames. As Michael Chanan has it, writing of the
Voyage à travers l’impossible,“if the first audiences saw Lumière’s train as if it
could detach itself from the screen, then in a way, Méliès’s film—in which a
cut out of a train flies through the skies and vaults across the ravines of a kind
of painted backdrop—was simply the film of a train which had so detached it-
self” (Chanan 1980: 32). The Voyageanalyzes. It separates the rush of the
pixelated screen into objects and distinguishes objects from their move-
ment. Méliès is the first master of the cinematic third dimension, that of
space, analyzing movement into layers stacked in front of or behind each
other. His tableaux identify the boundaries of the screen (and so create off-
screen space). Once established, these layered and contiguous spaces create
the temporality of hiding and revealing and thus also the possibility of cut-
ting from place to place. Framing, compositing in layers (in the mise-en-
scène, in-camera or in postproduction), and jumping from tableau to
tableau are all acts of singling out and multiplying, of converting the un-
stable equilibrium of the pixel into places and objects, organizing the on-
and offscreen, the behind and before into coherent worlds. The innocent
but abstracted delight in sensation, in light moving in time, gives way to the
analytic pleasures of recognizing objects and their movements in space.
This new mode of analytic cinema I will call the cut.
Innovation is never purely accidental. Méliès had to recognize his good
luck. The jammed shutter condensed and reiterated the practice of exhibit-
ing single-shot films back to back (Bottomore 1988). But there is also an
internal logic at work in the genesis of cutting as the basis of film form. Di-
rectionless and omnidirectional, the unstable equilibrium of zero already
demands a pivot; the order of the nonidentical produces the order of iden-
tity. The mise-en-scène of the Lumières’ L’Arroseur arrosé(fig. 3.1)already
| 43 |
M
ag
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
Th
e
C
u
t
|
stages its action in discrete segments (following formulas already industri-
alized in the comic strip) and carefully framed for maximum visibility, as
when the naughty boy is ear-tweaked front and center to receive his pun-
ishment. As Aumont (1997b: 252) points out while discussing the impact of
photographic practice on Degas, “the cutting force of the frame” is a prin-
ciple of unification. The first cut in film is the power of the frame to differ-
entiate what is visible from what is not. Long before Kubrick, the Lumières
recognized the power of symmetry to spatialize looking.
Using layers in a way that would reach formal purity in the work of
Méliès, L’Arroseurcomposes its action in depth. When we see the boy stand-
ing in midground on the hosepipe while the bemused gardner inspects its
nozzle in the foreground, their relation is established in the distinction be-
tween planes. Evoking the theatrical flats of the proscenium arch stage, the
film differentiates figure and ground in order to establish hierarchies of
interest that the indifferentiation of La Sortieso signally failed to provide.
| 44 |
C
h
ap
te
r
3
|
| Figure 3.1 |
L’Arroseur arrosé:figures and ground, planes cut in depth. Courtesy BFI Collections.
The inertia of the garden acts as a foil to the activity of the figures, so that
generalized movement is separated into discrete actions of identifiable and
identified figures, distinct from the world that surrounds them. As ground,
the garden becomes one kind of object, while the actors become another. So
the process of objectification simultaneously unifies flux into objects and
multiplies the number and kind of objects—here foreground figure, back-
ground figure, ground.
Though the first spectators immersed themselves in the mesmeric
ebbing and flowing of waves, both the ideology of attentiveness and the
pointlessness of reverie demanded a more substantial organization of film’s
primal temporal flux. Framing and compositing distinguish in time as they
determine in space. Composing the image in layers not only distinguishes
movement into objects: it demands a temporal relation between layers, here
in the construction of causality (the boy steps on the hose; the water stops
flowing). Likewise in later films the construction of offscreen space creates
the temporal relation of “where next?”: the principle of the edit. In L’Ar-
roseur the only edit comes at the end, matching the gardener’s return to his
hosepipe with the end of the reel. Here is the narrative symmetry Deutel-
baum mistakenly identifies in La Sortie des usines,the symmetry of restored
equilibrium. The ending provides us with the material for a rearview (and
ideological) reconstruction of the action by making the humor and moral-
ity of the scene legible: that honest toil is more rewarding than childish
pranks. By providing this ideological conclusion, the final edit provides that
horizon which, for Merleau-Ponty (1962), was the necessary base for any
figure-ground relation. Unlike his, however, the horizon of the final cut is
temporal rather than spatial. Coming at the end rather than the beginning,
the horizon of the final cut controls retrospectively the endlessly unstable
sameness of sensation. The internal logic of indifference, the endless and
formless froth bubbling in and out of being, is too unstable to survive. The
cut that establishes foreground and background, onscreen and offscreen
space allies with the construction of a temporal horizon to convert the ran-
dom jostling of pixels into unified and discrete cinematic objects.
This task is in part purely technical. Le Radical’s account of the Salon In-
dien screening proposed that “Their work will be a veritable marvel if they
manage to reduce, if not suppress, which scarcely seems possible, the judder-
ing produced in their first scenes” (Ministère des affaires etrangères 1996:
16). Improving registration (the fit between sprocket and sprocket hole) and
| 45 |
M
ag
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
Th
e
C
u
t
|
speeding up the shutter to smooth the transition from image to image does
more than soothe the eyes. Nor did the technical stabilization of the shot
merely serve to normalize cinema for the bourgeoisie (Burch 1990: 48, 52).
The judder, still celebrated in the slang term “flicks” or “flickers,” tended to
induce the state of reverie typical of the unstable equilibrium of the pixel.
Anchoring the frame firmly at the moment of projection minimized and
managed distraction by ensuring that the image stayed in its place. Getting
pin-registration right was the first step toward that Romantic aesthetic of
organic unity believed essential for attentive viewing, the proper mode for
moral education and edifying entertainments. Though the cut is seen as em-
blematic of the fragmentation of modernity, it is that only insofar as it is also
a principle of unification, as witness both Eisenstein (1949a) and Pound (see
Fenollosa 1986). The technical fix made the image truly bourgeois when it
made it identical with itself.
Once the judder had been stilled, the frame could come into its own.
L’Arroseurdoes not invite us to speculate about what lies beyond the frame—
that would come later. It does allow us to pause long enough to consider its
shape. The rectangular frame established by the Lumières was arbitrary
only in the sense that it was dictated by the device, not its inventors. But the
device itself was the product of all those who had worked on the technol-
ogies of picturing over the centuries, from seamstresses to picture framers,
whose skills were expropriated, made concrete and automated in the ma-
chinery of the cinematograph.2The rectangular frame was both the dead
tradition of the past and the instrument for bringing it back to life. The cy-
borg process that transforms living labor into fixed technologies allows the
skills of all the dead to participate in the creativity of the present. The rec-
tangle framing L’Arroseuranchors attention by exclusion. But the world be-
yond the frame could not be kept out forever. The stolen labor of those lost,
anonymous artisans comes back to life when the frame itself begins to move.
Because the frame intimates contiguous but invisible spaces beyond it-
self, it urges the invention of reframing (moving the camera to keep an ac-
tion in shot). Reframing in turn requires the edit as a way of structuring
itself. Both techniques appear in an exemplary exploration of space as time,
Porter’s Pan-American Exposition by Nightof 1901. The camera pans from
right to left over the sunlit central avenue of the exposition until it reaches
the central axis, a tower. Here the film fades to black, and a second take be-
gins, on the same reel and from the same position, following the same rate
| 46 |
C
h
ap
te
r
3
|
of panning, but now capturing the vista by night, enlivened by thousands of
lightbulbs furnished by Porter’s employer, Thomas Alva Edison. A single
static shot could have captured the play of the searchlight and been quite as
successful financially and historically as an early example of product place-
ment. But the film clearly simulates the vistas of the popular, century-
oldpanoramas, many of which required the audience to move, rather than
thescreen image. A static shot would have invited the viewers’ eyes to rove
across the frame, as happens in La Sortie.Porter’s pan is an attempt to unify
and guide that roving gaze.
Panning (the word derives from “panorama”) transfers the inertia of the
ground to the audience, the unity of the vista to the identity of the spec-
tator, so restructuring the audience’s aimless, flickering glances as a rec-
ognizably cinematic gaze. Far from exploding the scene into fragments, the
midpoint edit transforms this public location—conventionally the most
uncontrollable conditions to shoot—into the mastered object of privatized
looking. Where the Sortie is entranced by the autonomy of its figures,
Porter’s Expositionignores the few moving people we can see. Most of them
are moving left to right, against the pan, and the moment when one male
figure can be seen walking along the midway toward the camera is the mo-
ment Porter fades to black. Here the logic of the cut is mathematical: at the
symmetrical point in the pan, the fade is already scheduled, no matter what
happens. The two shots pitch themselves toward unity through a hierarchy
of movements. The man’s progress toward us is interrupted by a fade he has
no part in, dictated by a pan whose rhythms are utterly alien to his own.
Porter’s shot is timed to absolute symmetry, mirroring day and night, sun-
light and electrical illumination in a machine that depended on both. His
apparatus of tripod, camera, and clock takes precedence over the unruly
world in front of it. The cut, then, does not sever the first and second
halves: it is a tool for joining fragments, here a mechanism for symmetry,
more generally for articulating and generating higher orders.
Initially spatial, as the metaphor of pattern suggests, the crossfade is
also an early example of time-lapse (Musser 1991: 186) and hence also tem-
poral. The frame identifies, gives identity and unity to, its contents. But the
individual frame cannot bear this burden. We are too aware of what it ex-
cludes and we want to see what has been excluded, a desire that propels the
movement of the pan. What first appears as the unity of the frame is imme-
diately remade as the desire to see something else, something whole. That
| 47 |
M
ag
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
Th
e
C
u
t
|
is the higher unity Porter achieves. The subordination of the event to the
frame cannot be completed: it must lead to another framing device, another
ground, another image to supplant the one that is now rendered static and
exclusive. An appropriately mechanical logic leads from the spontaneous
difference of every pixel from every other, the fascinating scintillation of the
Lumières’ crowding elements, toward a larger difference between succes-
sive frames, marked in Porter’s film by the cut at the axis of symmetry in the
arc of the pan. After the cut, wholeness is a matter of “re-cognition,” a tem-
poral effect.
The edges of the frame unify the image as composition, reducing the
flux of movement to the rectangle of illumination. But framing excludes at
the same time that it unifies, differentiating the framed by opposing it to the
unframed. So it doubles cinematic space into onscreen and offscreen. There
are at least two points in the fifty-four seconds of the Pan-American Expo-
sitionwhen the direction of the pan could have been reversed: once when
adaylit figure gets our attention by walking left to right against the right-
to-left reframing; the other as the searchlight tower passes out of sight. The
moving figures give the composition depth and scale, but they also distract
from the apparatus of the pan. Organizing the single shot to produce unity
through exclusion of offscreen space implies the possibility of alternate views:
a reverse pan, insert edits to identify the figures, or cutaways to the emblem-
atic searchlight. Meanwhile, the foreground figures also introduce the pos-
sibility of seeing from other points inside the figured space: point-of-view
shots and reverse angles to complete the description of the world of the
film. The struggle toward wholeness progresses by multiplication, a system
of checks and balances, levers and props, each of which implies a further ac-
cretion of fulcrums and buttresses. The unification of the shot leads merci-
lessly to the proliferation of cuts.
In mathematics and in cinema, unity is always subsequent: it derives
from that numberless movement at zero that initiates number.3The non-
identity of the pixel, the formless, initiating instant of sensation, is the mo-
ment of firstness proposed by the semiotician Charles Sanders Peirce, who
describes it as “Feeling, the consciousness which can be included with an
instant of time, passive consciousness of quality without recognition or
analysis” (Peirce 1991: 185). Jonathan Crary equates this passivity with the
distracted gaze, associating it with the timelessness of the cinematic event
(Crary 1999: 59–60). Umberto Eco suggests that firstness “is a quality of
| 48 |
C
h
ap
te
r
3
|
feeling, like a purple color noticed without any sense of the beginning or the
end of the experience; it is not an object, nor is it initially inherent to any
recognizable object” (Eco 1999: 100). For cinema, it is the interpenetration
of the physics of light and the physiology of seeing, the world worlding freely
over the senses. Duration without beginning, end, or direction, firstness is
the simplest possible awareness of sensation, and it antedates, logically, chro-
nologically, and phenomenologically, all consciousness of unified objects.
That unity belongs to Peirce’s secondness, when the formless instant
becomes an object because we re-cognize it, shaping the flux of sensations,
not yet even identifiably internal or external, into a specific object for the
contemplating subject. In terms evoking the cinematic cut, Peirce describes
secondness as “Consciousness of an interruption into the field of con-
sciousness, sense of resistance, of an external fact, of another something”
(Peirce 1991: 185). In the cinema, we are aware first of movement and only
secondarily of what moves and that its movement constitutes a coherent ac-
tion. In late fragmentary notes, Merleau-Ponty names Rückgestaltung,“‘ret-
rograde movement of the true.’... This means: there is a germination of
what will have been understood” (Merleau-Ponty 1968: 189). Making a
whole in retrospect, the literal translation of Rückgestaltung, is the habit of
mind that associates the action of photons on the optic nerves with the pres-
ence of known objects. But, Merleau-Ponty asserts, prior to objectification
is a “germination”: the pixel, Peirce’s firstness. The cut turns sensation into
perception in a retrospective ordering of raw, undifferentiated (and me-
chanical) flux into identified objects. Through framing, compositing, and
editing, the cut distinguishes the gestalt wholeness of bounded figures and
bounded duration from the effervescence of photons. Identifying the con-
tent of the image as composition, figure, and duration at once unifies and
multiplies the “germination” of the image’s pure movement by pointing in-
dexically to what moves.
In the transition from sensation (of the cinematic event) to appercep-
tion (of the cinematic object), the elementary practices of the cut convert
the play of pixels into objects, worlds, and identities. Staging in depth, the
parallax effect (objects close to the camera appear to move more quickly
than objects in the distance), the use of mattes, optical printing, and other
layering technologies separate figure from figure, and figures from ground.
These compositing techniques describe sensation as object. Framing sepa-
rates a particular fragment of the scene for our attention by use of the frame
| 49 |
M
ag
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
Th
e
C
u
t
|
edge but also by irising in on a detail, shortening the depth of field or using
scrims and other elements of the mise-en-scène (Sternberg’s favorite: Bax-
ter 1980, 1993) or masks, filters, or vaseline on the lens to discriminate cen-
ters of focus. Because it creates both offscreen space and obscure patches
within the imaged field, the frame also produces an intuition of a world ex-
tending beneath, beyond, and in front of what the frame makes visible. That
always imaginary world, whether documentary or fiction, does not exist in
La Sortie: it has to wait for reframing to be produced. Framing and com-
positing create diegesis, the properly Imaginary world. Another doubling
occurs here: the flaring photons are reduced to the objects of a masterful
gaze, the gaze of the newborn subject. But because the diegetic world so cre-
ated extends to the differentiated space in front of the screen, that subject is
also subjected to the diegesis.
For the first audiences of the Sortiethere was no expectation about how
long the experience would last, no sense that it would necessarily be time-
bound. But once knowledge that a film ends becomes common sense, audi-
ences come to expect a concluding edit and to anticipate from the unfolding
flux of motion a goal toward which it tends. Once that conclusion is reached,
as in L’Arroseur,we turn our focus backward to reconstruct the action in the
light of its conclusion. The edit instigates a doubled movement in time, one
that demands both retrospect and prospect. In Porter’s Pan-American Expo-
sition,this happens at the edit, which tells us that the second shot will last as
long, pan at the same pace, and conclude in mirror symmetry with the open-
ing shot. Retrospect and prospect, starting and stopping, recognition and
expectation, between them unify the cinematic object in time and space, but
at the same time double the subject that is both master of and mastered by
imaginary wholeness.
Serial production of distinct units and the hierarchy of unities, striving
toward the formal unification of flux, end up atomizing the flow of light into
space and time. The cut spatializes the timeless time of the pixel. Cinematic
space, however, produces temporal relations like causality and point of view,
behind and in front, inside and outside. The temporality involved is itself
double, both future and past, expectation and memory, desire and loss. This
temporal doubling mirrors the spatial doubling of on- and off-frame, pres-
ence and absence. In a process familiar from Lacan, the work of manu-
facturing the presence of desire’s object on celluloid ends only in its lack in
being. To compensate, when compositing, framing, and editing establish
| 50 |
C
h
ap
te
r
3
|
objects, worlds, and identities, they hierarchize our interest in the image.
Anticipation of an ending likewise constrains motion to a hierarchy of ex-
pectation and recall. But it only constrains; it cannot determine. The pro-
cess of guiding the audience to a single focus is never concluded. Every
exclusion is an invitation to anticipate or recall what remains unseen, what
else happens before or after, within or beyond the frame. Cutting prolifer-
ates in the endless attempt to structure the boundless flow of the pixel, so
much so that cinematic unity is indistinguishable from the proliferation of
multiplicity.
In pursuit of an ideally attentive and stable subject, the cut produces
multiple unities and hierarchies. And yet the oceanic protosubjectivity of
the pixel is never entirely subsumed into the new formation. Oscillating be-
tween focus and forgetfulness, this new subject ticks and tocks between the
nonidentity of the pixel, constantly generating new movements, and the
cut’s proliferating identities and hierarchies of attention. In that dialectic
the subject of cinema inhabits a triple time. Enticed into imagining what
happens beyond the frame as a movement toward the future, while also com-
posing a retrospective account of what has already passed by, she nonethe-
less also inhabits the zero point traveling at exactly the same speed as the
film. PaceDeleuze, film began in the time-image, the simplest dreamy iden-
tification with durée.Its reemergence in the postwar cinéma d’auteuris only
evidence of a forlorn effort to recreate the innocence of the unfurling pres-
ent. Surveillance cameras, the last bastion of the pure cinematic event, dem-
onstrate the banality of the results.
Setting boundaries within and around movement, the cut makes us
judges and manipulators of time in the cinema. If, in the transition from the
Sortieto L’Arroseur,film lost the innocence of sheer perception, it gained the
keys to time as a medium. At first and for many years after, filmmakers had
the tools to construct new temporalities for audiences, who were not only
consumed and communicated but temporalized as subjects of the cinema.
These new temporalities enabled by the introduction of the cut were not, of
course, pure productions of an autonomous inspiration or of a technology
determining its own evolution; nor did they emerge solely from the internal
logic of the cinematograph. Cinematic time is inseparable from the matrix
of the commodity, because film became, already, in the 1890s, the cutting
edge of the commodity’s reorientation as spectacle, the first intimation of
media technologies as the powerhouse of globalization.
| 51 |
M
ag
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
Th
e
C
u
t
|
Belle Epoque
The women who stroll out of the Lumière factory are walking into a new
kind of public space. In front of the camera, they share the visibility of the
men, no longer the privileged objects of a presumed male gaze. They too are
represented; they too are communicated. The anonymous mobility and mo-
nopoly over the gaze of Baudelaire’s “dandy” of the 1860s was exclusively
male (Buck-Morss 1986; Huyssen 1986a; Pollock 1988: 50–90; Wolff 1985).
But the 1890s and 1900s witnessed a democratization of flâneriethat would
embrace the women who not only worked for the high-tech photographic
industry but had replaced more expensive, traditionally skilled men in the
office trades with the introduction of the typewriter and adding machine,
and who were the primary workforce in the new retail business.
This feminization of the cutting edges of the late nineteenth- and early
twentieth-century economy reinforced and was reinforced by the reorienta-
tion of metropolitan capital toward consumerism. The preserve of the male
flâneurwas the arcade; the privileged domain of the emergent and cross-
class flâneusewas the department store. The new security offered by electri-
cal illumination and plate glass promoted shopping as a female occupation
by assuring women of protection from weather, darkness, and unwanted ap-
proaches (Rappaport 1995). Urban space became available for women to
promenade through in a way impossible a scant decade before. Anne Fried-
berg writes, citing Walter Benjamin (1973b: 170):
The department store that, like the arcade before it, “made use of flânerieitself
in order to sell goods,” constructed fantasy worlds for itinerant lookers. But un-
like the arcade, the department store offered a protected site for the empowered
gaze of the flâneuse. Endowed with purchase power, she was the target of con-
sumer address. New desires were created for herby advertising and consumer
culture, desires elaborated in a system of selling and consumption which de-
pended on the relation between looking and buying, and the indirect desire to
possess and incorporate through the eye. (Friedberg 1993: 37)
The price of the liberty to stroll is a certain indifferentiation, a gener-
alized equivalence of men and women. The flâneusenot only abrogated the
dominance of male desire but anulled desire as a whole by anchoring it no
longer in the person but in the visually charged form of the commodity as
spectacle, which not only targeted her, but in the newly democratizing fash-
| 52 |
C
h
ap
te
r
3
|
ion trade, made her a commodity spectacle herself. This equation of dis-
parate and uneven desire, shaped not even by the presence but by the pres-
entation of goods, also shapes cinematic unification in the cut. At the same
time, like the cut, the internally contradictory nature of the commodity pro-
duces the endless procession of fashionable novelties, the multiplicity on
which consumerism depends. In this it shares that vertigo discernible among
the filmmakers who first engaged the cinema in the articulation of fantasy.
In the emergent consumer culture of arcades and department stores,
fashion, and spectacle, the erotic seeped into public space as a guiding mo-
tivation for individuated success, individuated consumption, individuated
madness: no wonder that the spectacle, psychoanalysis, and cinema share a
birthday. At the same time that fashion became available as a mass enter-
tainment, industrialized, and reduced in price so that working women like
those from the Lumière plant could afford it (Wilson 1985; Williams 1982),
the female body was being partitioned into a montage of fetishized parts
(Apter 1991). Simultaneously, the obligation to be looked at implied the lib-
erty to look (Gleber 1997). The price of entry into the democratized world
of consumer capital was visibility: not just to be seen but to see as and in
terms of the commodity form. The privileged moment at which this historic
shift in the formation of the psyche was achieved lay in the same “dream
world of mass culture” (Buck-Morss 1989: 253) of late nineteenth-century
France that first gave rise to the moving image. In the Paris of the depart-
ment stores, these contradictions of the commodity were endlessly inter-
worked with the spectacle of the new technologies. Far from unifying, the
democratization of the commodity as spectacle splits and multiplies. Spec-
tacularizing the erotic, eroticizing the spectacle, generates a curiously asex-
ual unconscious, explored and exploded in the films of Georges Méliès.
In 1888, newly ensconced as proprietor of the popular Théâtre Robert-
Houdin (after which Houdini was to name himself), Méliès began to en-
liven the already florid late-century stage with new tricks (Barnouw 1981).
Like the North American theater described by Eisenstein (1949b), the
spectacular school in which D.W. Griffith acquired his sense of cinematic
form, the melodramatic theaters of Paris were majestically devoted to earth-
quakes, waterfalls, railway crashes, airborne apparitions, imaginary jour-
neys, stampedes, battles, and mythical beasts. The apparatus of traps and
projections, prestidigitation, wire acrobats, wrangling, massive and mobile
sets, lighting and sound effects put it on a par with the 1990s music theater
| 53 |
M
ag
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
Th
e
C
u
t
|
of Andrew Lloyd Weber. Méliès belonged to this tradition, and as a designer
of trucagesfor the stage (Arias 1984) already in the 1880s he occupied the
keyposition of technologist-engineer-artist central to the cultures of tech-
nological media. Magic lantern shows and panoramas had, by the early
years of the French republic, achieved a degree of movement and three-
dimensionality unrepeated until the virtual reality experiments of Krueger
and Lanier in the 1980s (see El Nouty 1978: 49–58; Levie 1990). As the
technologization of spectacle accelerated, its thematics moved bizarrely in
the opposite direction: to folklore (giants, féeries), the gothic (ghouls, ruined
castles), the melodramatic grotesque (guignol, satanism), and the exotic
(tales from the Arabian Nights, “exotic” dances). Only in the theatricaliza-
tion of the works of Jules Verne did the fantastic imaginary of technologized
consumerism express itself in motifs derived from engineering, and even
then only after the massive success of Dennery’s stage adaptation of Around
the World in Eighty Days,itself a classic of orientalism.
The avant-gardes of the imperial powers orientalized the Bible, arche-
typically in the sensualist Salomës of Wilde, Beardsley, and Moreau—the
symbolist painter with whom, putatively, Méliès studied for a year in 1888.
Meanwhile, the popular culture of spectacle produced the Indian rope trick,
Maskelyne’s Egyptian Hall (home of conjuring on the London stage), and
the pantomime traditions of Ali Baba and Aladdin, enduring legacies of a
love affair with imagined empires. Imperial dreams suffuse Méliès titles (see
Frazer’s 1979 filmography). Many of them developed from trucs initially
presented at the Robert-Houdin (Deslandes 1963: 33–49), titles like Les
Miracles de Brahmanand Le fakir de Singapoureindicate a decade-long infatu-
ation with the image of the orient. Other orientalist extravangzas like Fer-
dinand Zecca’s Pathéshorts and Wilde’s transvestite performance as Salomë
constitute the orient as other in the sense of the objet petit “a,”the impossible
object of desire. For Méliès the East is a core though not unique form of
what speaks in the unconscious as Other, the constitutive ventriloquism of
a subjectivity that never speaks but is always spoken by a desire it perpetu-
ally disavows.
In Méliès’s films, the absolute exteriority of hallucinations, like the
elephant-moon of his 1911 Les Hallucinations du Baron Munchausen,derives
from the crisis of overconsumption experienced as indigestion, the sup-
pressed bodily life of his lunatic scientists and whacky academicians.
Dressed in the formal evening wear of the professional magician, Méliès is
| 54 |
C
h
ap
te
r
3
|
already ringmaster of an unforeseeable universe of transformations, master
of them all yet perpetually condemned to plunge back into the ring with
animals, imps, and clowns, embodiments of Bakhtin’s “lower bodily func-
tions” (Bakhtin 1968). In his favorite guise of carnivalesque Satan, “he could
mobilise a recurring, yet continually shifting bricolage of otherness—par-
ticularly in terms of religion, race and gender—in order to invert the hier-
archical values of modern French society and hold them up to ridicule in a
riot of the carnivalesque” (Abel 1994: 65).
Méliès’s sexuality is still patriarchal, fleshed out in his pneumatic star-
maidens and mermaids, and unabashed. The orient as something inherently
unconscious in the European order of commodities is not just erotic, be-
cause eroticism was obscenely conscious in the Belle Epoque. Zecca’s ori-
entalism is commodity fetishism proper, a denegation disguising desire for
the commodity-spectacle as desire for the spectacle, pure and simple, fig-
ured as the unknown East. Méliès instead speaks to the constitutive un-
knowability of the spectacle, evoking as demonic the inattentive, reckless,
feckless, irrepressibly pointless imps of distraction that the commodity
fetishism of the cut has come to control. Méliès’s unconscious is the form-
less chaos underlying the order of objects, spectacle, and the commodity.
In the Vernean titles (Voyage dans la lune, Voyage à travers l’impossible),
which for audiences a century later most evoke Méliès, the cineast makes up
for slow lenses and emulsions by widening the aperture to admit more light,
diminishing the depth of field as a consequence. Compensating for this
foreshortening with trompe l’oeilbackdrops, the living actors and foreground
props project toward the front of the image, like the foregrounded layering
effects characteristic of Peter Greenaway’s digital films (Spielmann 1997).
Of the twenty-six tableaux making up the Voyage à travers l’impossible(fig.
3.2), only two use backdrops that are explicitly designed to give a sense of
receding space. The others rely on building up planes. The prop submarine
and the cutaway railway carriage occupy only extremely shallow spaces.
Even outer space and the deep ocean are inert grounds that propel the hu-
man figures up to the surface of the screen. The human environment is re-
stricted to a single shallow plane of action or, at most, a double plane divided
only by the cardboard cutout of the circulating wheel in the second tableau,
the interior of Crazyloff’s factory. In the Swiss scenes, some action occurs
across a diagonal axis—the exit of the porter in the ticket office and the scat-
tering of the peasants when the motor car crashes into the inn. But these
| 55 |
M
ag
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
Th
e
C
u
t
|
scenes are closed off by a high horizon line that limits movement into the
scene along the z-axis, rendering the performance space discrete from the
layered theatrical flats that make up its landscape. The only apparent depth
comes in those scenes from which the human protagonists are absent and
the machines take on their own lives: the traverse of the Alps, for example,
in which the train crosses left to right in the background and right to left in
the foreground.
In this positive sense Méliès’s films are superficial. The shallow space of
the reflective screen folds distance and desire into one another. A visual
repertoire already démodéwhen the later films were released, the personifi-
cations of celestial bodies and the incessant magical transformations of
Méliès’s imaginary come not from far way but from before. Where Zecca’s
other is elsewhere, Méliès’s is removed in time to the postmortem universe
of mummies, the afterworld, the vanishing temporal perspectives of “once
| 56 |
C
h
ap
te
r
3
|
| Figure 3.2 |
Voyage a travers l’impossible:layering theatrical flats and trompe-l’oeuil compensate for the flattening
effectof brilliant daylight. Courtesy BFI Collections.
upon a time.” Eroticized, commodified, desire is constantly confounded
with the ridicule of death, the body, eating, sleeping, and disorganization:
whatever is here. And what is here is the impossibility of existing as pure sur-
face, pure spectacle. The shrinking dimensions of the shallow screen figure
the commodity form not as yearning and desire but as anxiety, a troubled re-
lation with the disavowed past of immersion in zero’s aimless satisfaction.
Beneath the foreshortened image of space lies the suddenly compressed ar-
chaism of the unconscious: beneath these pictures of the nonexistent, the
commodity evokes the conflicting temporalities of the nonidentical only to
deny them.
Between Worlds
Sadoul is not the only historian to see in Méliès the realization of the cinema
beyond the technological spectacle achieved by the Lumières and Edison.
Cavalcanti (1979), Richter (1986), and Eisenstein (1988) among many oth-
ers attribute to Méliès the beginnings of the fantasy film. It is equally a tru-
ism to see in the films of Dadasaheb Phalke, the pioneer of the Indian
cinema, an imitator—of genius, but an imitator—of Méliès in the years just
after Méliès, bankrupted by sharp practices in the North American market-
place, gave up his cinema business. But chronology can be a liar. Phalke’s
nationalist reworkings of stories from the Mahabharata and the Ramayana
draw from the same Asian traditions that, since Dryden and Racine, had fed
the spectacular theaters of the great colonial powers with stories, imagery,
and techniques. Phalke’s dramas are palpably cosmic, but his cosmos pos-
sesses the dignity of ancient belief, where Méliès’s makes a game of its dis-
tinction from the commonsense scientism of his age and is at its most poetic
when at its most debunking. Moreover, Phalke operates at the scale of an
ideal village life and the home-industry Swadeshi movement associated with
Mohatma Gandhi; Méliès’s is a tangibly urbane art. And whereas Méliès’s
work is, with some exceptions, studio-based, Phalke’s is shot on location in
full daylight, thereby enjoying a depth of field that Méliès eschewed.
Like Méliès, Phalke was a skilled artisan and trained artist, with a pas-
sion for magic tricks, some of which he filmed under the anagramatic pseu-
donym Prof. Kelpha. Unlike the boulevardier Méliès, however, he had
onlya brief visit to London in which to acquaint himself with the state of
film technique. “Phalke’s greatness,” notes Firoze Rangoonwalla, “can be
realised from the fact that he had to work almost single-handed, doing
| 57 |
M
ag
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
Th
e
C
u
t
|
the pioneering and innovating in every respect, while his contemporaries
abroad had the benefits of resources, equipment and specialised services in
studios” (Rangoonwalla 1983: 35). Phalke even perforated his own film-
stock by hand. This became a strength: “My films are Swadeshi,” he wrote,
“in the sense that the capital ownership, employees and the stories are Swa-
deshi” (cited in Dharap 1985: 40). Despite the foreign technology, in his first
experiment, a short on the growth of a pea-plant, Phalke had to reinvent the
principles of stop-motion photography. Rajah Harischandra,probably com-
pleted late in 1912, like all of Phalke’s features, was a devotional film. Its
audience too was new to the cinema: “The people who came were seldom
two-rupee customers. Most paid four annas, two annas, or even one anna,
and most of them sat on the ground. The weight of the coins, on the home-
ward trip, could be enormous” (Barnouw and Krishnaswamy 1980: 15), ne-
cessitating a bullock cart on at least one occasion. His success is also credited
with enabling a viable indigenous cinema, and he is praised for making it
possible for Indian women to appear on Indian screens.
Phalke’s effects are not only beautifully achieved but integrated with
both traditional and anticolonial cultural formations. Religiously legiti-
mated magic not only evades colonial censorship but charms the unwitting
colonizer. Lanka Dahan, Shri Krishna Janma, and Kaliya Mardandelighted
viewers with familiar stories, much as silent film historians have argued of
the use of narratives from the Bible, folklore, and the popular stage in Eu-
ropean and North American cinemas of the early period. Méliès conforms
to the thesis of the cinema of attractions as proposed by Gunning (1986),
narrative taking second place to spectacle. In Phalke, however, the narrative,
though fragmented by the vagaries of preservation and transmission, occu-
pies a sovereign position, but as metonymic, almost holographic shards of
the Hindu epic tradition. According to Gaudreault (1987), Mitry (1968),
and Jenn (1984), among others, the often overlooked complexity of the nar-
rative structure of his editing is evidence of Méliès’s ambition as montageur.
Phalke’s cinema deploys similar cuts, trimming to circumnavigate the diffi-
culty of in-camera editing for stop-motion action scenes, cutting between
shots with similar framing, following characters’ actions from tableau to
tableau, and establishing montage within single frames through multiple
exposure in camera or optical printing. But where Méliès is spectacular in
objectifying the internal dialectic of the commodity form, Phalke’s cinema
subordinates the film to the revealed truth of the Mahabharata. In Peirce’s
| 58 |
C
h
ap
te
r
3
|
terms, Phalke’s cinema is indexical of the theology of apparition, the making-
manifest of the Lords Krishna and Rama, whose human forms are always
only aspects of their being.
Ashish Rajadhyaksha notes that Phalke’s “initial influences of art de-
rived from the great painter of kitsch, Raja Ravi Varma. Phalke’s work was a
logical successor to Varma, for it actually implemented what Varma merely
expressed—an art of the post-industrial, mechanical reproduction age”; he
adds that, though cinema was seen as an art for the urban middle classes,
Phalke moved away from Bombay to distance himself from the Western-
ization of urban life (Rajadhyaksha 1985: 230; on Varma, see Khanna and
Kurtha 1998; Mishra 2002: 10–13). At the same time, his acceptance of
foreign-made technology and foreign travel for a fundamentally nationalist
appeal to traditional beliefs indicates both a commitment to modernization
and a belief that the new devices are assimilable within an authentically In-
dian tradition of conjuring and illusion. Two of his greatest successes, Shri
Krishna Janmaand Kaliya Mardan,are stories of the infant Krishna. That as-
pect of tradition which is a handing on from father to offspring, and so a
kind of immortality, is here joined to a more secular faith in the possibility
of a future in reach of the child—Krishna is played by Phalke’s daughter
Mandakini, who could be expected to live long enough to see independence.
Phalke’s theological modernity animates the devotional past in the colonial
present as the promise of a future guided by the twin principles of demo-
cratic nationalism and the centrality of the rural (see Gandhi 1948), his films
the foreshadowing of Nehru’s midnight speech.
Phalke’s “mythologicals” gave Bollywood a genre and a value structure
that still forms the genotype for the Bombay melodrama (Mishra 1985).
Where Méliès’s class was fading, and he sang its swan song in a glorious if
short-lived duet with popular working-class culture, Phalke’s feels itself
ascendant and in its strength can afford to be democratic. He speaks with
pride of the swadeshi achievements of his class in a 1939 interview with
Mauj Magazine: “If I had not possessed the artistic and technical facilities,
required for film-making, namely drawing, painting, architecture, photog-
raphy, theatre and magic and had not shown the courage and daring, the film
industry would never have been established in India in 1912” (cited in Nair
1999: np).
Assured of the power of the merchant class and of Hindu nationalism
ina presumptive postcolonial India, Phalke could free his films from the
| 59 |
M
ag
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
Th
e
C
u
t
|
necessity to represent caste differences. As Nair (1999) argues, “the organ-
isation of space and movement within the frame, the entry of characters,
their movements, looks and exits and the props they carry, the clothes they
wear” reveal a mutual respect and readiness to forgo caste privilege, a pow-
erful statement for a Brahmin’s son to make, in the interests of national
unity. This democratization within the Hindu community, however, ex-
presses a sense of emancipation in which the interests of nation and the spe-
cific class and gender interests of Phalke’s community are identical (see
Guha 1982).
At the same time, it is important to understand that Phalke’s films were
an effort on the part of his Brahmin caste to assume leadership over the
massive groundswell of popular resistance that peaked in the anti-Rowlatt
movements of 1919, in the name of a rising bourgeoisie (see Guha 1988: 40–
41). Moreover, the Extremist leader Bal Gangadhar Tilak’s influence on the
Swadeshi movement, as much as the success of the Tata iron and steel mills
that financed it, led to a gradual reorientation toward a more radically
Hindu nationalism, rather than a simple anticolonialism. Indeed, we find
Phalke publishing under his given name Dundiraj, in the pages of Tilak’s
house organ (Phalke 1988/1989; see also Shoesmith 1998/1999). From its
birth in 1905, Swadeshi tended to absorb an increasingly bitter anti-Muslim
element (Read and Fisher 1988: 89–91).
Hindi nationalism also evolved toward a deep masculinism. In an anal-
ysis of the Indian rope trick, Lee Siegel discovers, in the rigidification of the
rope, the defiance of gravity, and the dismemberment and reconstitution of
the boy who climbs the rope, a celebration of a masculine generative power
in which women have no place (Siegel 1991: 218–220). Phalke’s Swadeshi
readings of the Ramayana and Mahabharata draw on this masculinist ideol-
ogy. Anand Patwardhan’s documentary film on Indian masculinity in the
communal violence of the late 1980s and early ’90s, Father, Son, and Holy
War(1994) traces the crisis of Indian machismo to the Raj’s sneering disre-
gard for an imagined effeminacy among Indian men. Patwardhan traces the
history of the stunt spectaculars which so dominate contemporary Bombay
cinema, often tuned to the extreme right-wing Hindi nationalism of the
Shiv Senna faction, to this magical response to colonialist discourses of mas-
culinity. Child of his time, Phalke in his films asserts the honor and strength
of Indian masculinity as a core ideological project of a highly ideological
cinema.4If Phalke’s films work in a theological time in which the past sub-
| 60 |
C
h
ap
te
r
3
|
sists in the present as the gateway to the future, it is as a function of their at-
tempt to legitimate and administer a specific postcolonial future in the name
of an educated, nationalist, Hindu, and male elite.
Both reaction and tradition are inventions of modernity. Phalke’s
antiurban, anti-Westernizing tradition is modern because it is asserted as
countermodernity. Reclaiming and Indianizing Ruskin’s idealization of pre-
industrial culture, Phalke offers an alternative model of modernization in-
volving technological mediation in the reproduction of ancient pieties for
the new circumstances of twentieth-century India. Here the miraculous is
mythical, coextensive with but separate from the historical time of oppres-
sion and colonization. The function of cinema in Phalke, then, is to realize
the conditions for a mythic subject, capable of entering the closed world of
colonization from outside, and of intervening to create the radical historical
leap of independence. What seeks assimilation into real time is the other
time of the miraculous. If this time is in some sense past—precolonial India
for Phalke, the “once upon a time” of fairytales for Méliès—it is also a re-
flection on modernist mastery over “other existing temporalities” (Sakai
1989: 106), in both cases not a hybridization but a dialectic of technology
and tradition, technology and magic.
Despite Méliès’s canonical place in the history of special effects, his de-
bunking evaluation of the consumer carnivalesque has had less “influence”
on later film than the obscured career of Phalke and his fragmentary legacy.
This is not to argue for influence: quite the contrary. Phalke’s films have
rarely been seen in Europe and North America; he scarcely figures in non-
Indian histories; and the films themselves exist only in fragments now. Yet
in his work we can see the modernization of ancient traditions that was com-
modified in the orientalist cinema ten years earlier, that continued to form
the basis of cinematic orientalism through the 1940s, and that provides the
understructure of a certain strand of contemporary special effects cinema.
Méliès and the contemporary blockbuster tradition alike learned from the
Indian master the capacity of cinema to evoke a time other than historical
time, a time of myth.
Phalke’s cinema fell outside the nascent society of the spectacle largely be-
cause the India of the first quarter of this century was only incompletely col-
onized by the commodity. The conservative ethic of self-help in the Swadeshi
movement was enabled more by the persistence of precolonial consumption
evaluated by purity and pollution than by the efforts of British reformers or
| 61 |
M
ag
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
Th
e
C
u
t
|
the fetish form of the commodity (see Bayly 1986). In the absence of full-
blown commodity fetishism, the autonomous object has no chance to domi-
nate material culture. It was only when Swadeshi products like Phalke’s films
began to circulate in the West that it was possible to see them commodified
(in this, similar to the European market for village homespun cloths), a pro-
cess sped up by the overseas audience’s ignorance of the source stories. Like
the magic of the nineteenth century, the commodified and orientalized cin-
ema of Phalke, divorced from the culture that gave it meaning, could be-
come the very type of a cinema of pure effect, much in the way that African
statuary could become the icon of pure form for Clive Bell (1931).
As outsider, Phalke spoke to the colonial metropolis as an Other who
could be internalized as the object of consumption, appearing to negate the
colonial imagination while confirming its right to consume him. The Lon-
don Bioscopeof June 4, 1914 “feels, therefore that Mr. Phâlke is directing his
energies in the best and most profitable direction in specialising upon the
presentation by film of Indian mythological dramas... in which, if they are
to be fully understood and sympathised with by foreigners, vivid realism of
atmosphere and setting are essential considerations” (reproduced in Bar-
nouw and Krishnaswamy 1980: 21). Deliberately or unconsciously blind to
the anticolonialism of the films, the Bioscopeorientalizes them. As Albert La
Valley suggests: “Science fiction films cannot do without some special effect
shots: they constitute the world of the other,the non-human, all that is for-
eign or future, or technologically possible—hence all that the non-special
effects part of the movie, the realistically photographed, the human, must
do battle with, learn from, overpower or adapt to” (La Valley 1985: 185).
Phalke’s confrontation of ancient tale with imperial history contests
and entrances the realistically human world of the colonial metropolis. His
accommodation of the mythical world to the diegetic objectification of vil-
lage India permitted his London audience to further the process of objecti-
fication by commodifying the films as orientalist spectacle and so to miss the
point completely.
In Rajah Harischandra(figs. 3.3, 3.4),for example, the daylight shoot al-
lows a far greater depth of field than Méliès had been able to achieve in the
studio. Its action is staged in depth, with character movement through the
z-axis. The village locations not only supply a sense of an intertwining of the
mythical and quotidian realms, permitting the English critics to patronize
the film as a window into the Indian “soul,” but give Phalke the space in
| 62 |
C
h
ap
te
r
3
|
which the figure and ground are in far more democratic relation than they
are in films of his French contemporary. Méliès’s limiting device of the
bounded horizon creates a mythical space, where Phalke is able to anchor
his tales in the lived space of the everyday. The secular myth of the com-
modity, then, seems to belong to an enclosed universe, whereas the divine
myth is presented as inhabiting the world. On the other hand, Méliès’s
flights of ambition and imagination are always subject to sudden and ba-
thetic returns of the repressed body, whereas in Phalke’s religious world, the
body itself is an illusion, so that any claim to realism must be tempered with
the recognition of the priority of eternal things over material.
In Phalke’s movies, devotion is inseparable from myth. Seen from the
vantage of divine temporality and cosmic order, the past, present, and future
are conjoint as they inhabit the here and now. Confronted with audiences
used to paying two annas for six-hour theatrical performances and reluctant
to part with more for a shorter film, Phalke advertised “Raja Harishchandra:
A performance with 57,000 photographs. A picture two miles long! All for
| 63 |
M
ag
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
Th
e
C
u
t
|
| Figure 3.3 |
Raja Harischandra:the male line as guarantor of fidelity to tradition. Courtesy BFI Collections.
only three annas” (Multichannel (India) Ltd. 1996: np). To consider his film
as a collection of stills is not, as it was in Gaudreault’s account of early copy-
right in films, a method of securing their commodity status. Rather, it de-
scribes the temporality of the film as a wholeness captured in every frame,
amythological temporality. In mythological time the dead walk among the
living, the living walk among the spirits, and the future is already written.
The love that Phalke’s divinities evoke, as befits constructions of a folkloric
nationalism, is the love of a father for his children. His wife Saraswatibai fig-
ures constantly in his biography, making extreme sacrifices to enable him
tocontinue, but her contribution is always subordinated to the masculine
creativity and the parthenogenesis of the male line. For Phalke, this is the
fruit of the political-intellectual vanguard of turn-of-the-century anti-
imperialism: the trace of a male autogenerative machine that, as technique
divorced from its religious origins, would help to generate the Western
myth of the self as autonomous signifier.
| 64 |
C
h
ap
te
r
3
|
| Figure 3.4 |
Raja Harischandra:location, space, and movement in depth. Courtesy BFI Collections.
In some ways, for Western culture Phalke’s cinema became the purest
of commodities because, since its use-value was shaped by its marketing in
the West rather than by its producers in the East, it could be presented as
just such an autonomous signifier. Western projectors screened, robed in in-
definite sensuality, an image of a diegetic world other than the society of
thespectacle. But just as tradition, posed as countermodernity, depends on
modernity, so the orientalist spectacle turns the absence of the commodity
form into the spectacle of its absence, in the first and necessary instance by
turning it into an object for the newly constituted cinema spectator. The
mystique of the East would permeate the fantastic cinemas of Hollywood,
Pinewood, Neu Babelsberg, and Billancourt for thirty years. Only in the
aftermath of World War II, when so many had experienced the exotic places
figured in the films, did the glamour begin to wear off. Moreover, the settle-
ment in 1945 of the great commercial conflict for commercial control of the
Pacific instigated the economic globalization orientalism had prefigured.
Henceforth there was no terrestrial paradise, no earthly space, where the
rule of the commodity no longer held. The function of Other passed to the
potential endlessness of outer space: from the global to the universal.
The closer it comes to pure spectacle and pure exchange value divorced
from use, the more the commodity presents itself as occupying a time out-
side history. The imaginary orient of nineteenth-century Europe provided
a graphic model for this changeless and timeless time, just as outer space
does for us in science fiction films. To become a commodity, the object has
to acquire an essence: it has to be.The filmic object’s being is imaginary, in
the sense that it is an image. In this way it prefigures the full-blown society
of spectacle, where essence is image, that Debord analyzed in the 1960s.
Though its duration onscreen is limited, the cinematic object (talismanic
objects like Méliès’s train or Bogart’s cigarette, but also the film itself) ac-
quires an existence beyond its moment on screen, both as imaginary di-
egesis, and because it is endlessly repeatable. This imaginary timelessness
depends on a process of othering. Orient and outer space suggest a merely
spatial separation of subject and object. But in cinema, the process is clearly
temporal. The production of the cinematic object as the other of its viewing
subject takes time. Likewise the production of a subject of perception occu-
pies, and lasts for, a certain duration. This time is the time of the cut.
The separation of object from subject provided Phalke with an entry
into the cosmological time of a patterned universe. As Rajadhyaksha and
| 65 |
M
ag
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
Th
e
C
u
t
|
Willemen (1999: 243) note of the 1917 Raja Harischadra,“continuity is de-
fined by the juxtaposition of spatial planes (e.g. the space of the family idyll
and the space beyond).” Like Méliès, Phalke constructs a cinema of tableaux.
But the tableaux are not the sequential scenes of a comic strip, but depic-
tions of copresent realms, one historical, one mystical, that intersect and in-
terpenetrate as layers in the shot and at the edit between scenes. Phalke’s cut
facilitates subjectivity in the movement between the two worlds, intimating
the continuing cosmic pattern underlying and structuring the conduct of
both the histoire évenementielle(Braudel 1972: 20–21), the sensuous fullness
of everyday life and the broader historical struggle for independence. His
subjective time is thus one of the immanent future, already present because
it is eternal. This is how the time of the cut becomes the time of identity.
Orientation
There is a history of the processes of perception. The nineteenth century
moved from the physics of light to the physiology of vision (Crary 1990).
The twentieth shifted from the physiological thesis of retinal retention
tothe cognitive thesis of the Phi effect, from the eye smoothing over the
gaps to the brain interjecting the “missing” elements of intermittent im-
ages (Gardner 1987: 111–112; the term was coined by Wertheimer in 1912).
Looking back from the twenty-first century, film’s visual coherence depends
on suturing light, eye, and brain, optics, physiology, and psyche—the en-
semble film theory calls the cinematic apparatus. In the pixel, film, ret-
ina, and mind are not distinguished. The cut distinguishes them, then
reassembles them into an apparatus for organizing space and time. The
atomic jostling of silver nitrate grains produces a directionless flux of pure
movement, independent of beginning or ending like waves on the sea. Its
oceanic primal temporality becomes navigable only once the cut instigates
endings: a delimited field of vision, composited spatial relations, and the
spatiotemporal assemblage of shots into sequences (Burch 1973: 3–16). No
longer adrift on the sea of duration, the spectator can now steer past charted
landmarks. The aimless event and its associated reverie is spatialized, thus
preparing directionless duration for directional temporalities like hiding
and revealing, moving on, causality.
The pixel inhabits the balmy limitlessness of the newborn child, bathed
in its world, unable to distinguish between itself and its environment. By
presenting the world as object over against the spectator as subject, the cut
| 66 |
C
h
ap
te
r
3
|
repeats the moment in which the infant first distinguishes itself from the
world (Lacan 1970). The step beyond the infantile pleasure of bathing in
light is experienced, Lacan emphasizes, as a split not only between subject
and object but within the emergent subjectivity of the child. Without this
separation, there can be no empathy (as when we see someone stub his toe
and wince on his behalf), but this first identification is narcissistic, in the
sense that we identify ourself with objects in the world because we have only
just separated the two from one another. Where Lacan emphasizes the loss
of integral wholeness in this splitting, however, the theory of the cut em-
phasizes the unification of dispersed, atomic sensation. Cinema structures
not by loss but by gains.
To adapt Lacan, the step from the pixel to the cut is the step from being
to having the camera. The presubjective subject of the pixel is at one with
the apparatus, sensing the world mechanically as a meaningless flux of light.
The cut splits apart the elements of the apparatus so that one—the self—
can take possession of another—the camera-projector—as object. The first
articulation of shots, frames, and composites turns the moving image into
an instrument by which the world can be possessed.5 The organizational
power of the cut controls flux by reconstituting it as space-time, as figures
on a ground, as objects in a world. Orientation takes the place of immersion
as the source of pleasure for the spectator. Here again, the cut enables a cer-
tain narcissism. As in Lacan, the unity it proposes to the subject in the pro-
cess of construction is the unity of individuation. Immersive reverie is always
already social. The self-same flux of pixels is the same for every viewer, dem-
ocratic and undifferentiated. The moment at which we perceive objects in
space is the moment at which we can conceive self-sameness as a property
of the self, subjectivity as a unique space-time effect.
As structuring device, the cut produces unities or, more accurately, mul-
tiplies units in hierarchies that always strive for higher levels of unification,
the sense of an ending crucial among them. The aesthetic of organic unity,
for example, leads to the scriptwriter’s adage that everything included in the
script should “pay off”: the gun we see in the drawer must at some later point
in the film be fired. In effect the shooting later on determines the hidden
gun in the earlier shot—the effect shapes the cause. The ending of the well-
made film structures everything that went before. In this sense the cut, as the
archetypal tool of continuity and of normative cinema generally, has tended
toward a teleological cinema, a cinema of predestination. This has led many
| 67 |
M
ag
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
Th
e
C
u
t
|
commentators to believe that cinema is essentially a narrative form. The
presumption is that causality is a process of the world, not of its interpreta-
tion. In the pure examples of the cut that Méliès and Phalke left for us,
causality is not an empirical given. Both offer more varied and more com-
plex times than narrative causality.
In Phalke’s case, the ending exists beyond the film. Under conditions of
colonial rule, Phalke’s revolutionary ending has to be encrypted. The polit-
ical goal of the narratives is expressed as the messianic moment in which the
Mahabharata will be realized in the return of the gods and their ahistorical
time. It cannot be explicitly spoken, and it cannot be represented because it
is both future and eternal. Méliès meanwhile deploys spectacle as the pre-
mature ghost of the old middle class. His films are monuments to an age
whose historical disappearance belies the way its truth, its beauty, and its
values survive beyond the moment of its annihilation. The sense of nostal-
gia for a value system that has outlived the class that produced it is the source
of the archaisms and the supernatural settings, the postnatural, postmortem
afterlife that so fascinates Méliès, for whom the symmetry of narrative al-
ways skates over the abyss. The highest unity of the cut in both Phalke and
Méliès is outside the film itself, in the ghostly past or the mythic future.
The pinnacle of the cut’s hierarchy for Méliès is the moment of annihi-
lation, death, and the afterlife that haunt the prehistory of European cin-
ema. For Phalke it is the moment of origin. The unphotographable essence
of gods is their eternity. The juxtaposition of divinity with the causality of
narrative time also mimics that divine intervention in human history evi-
denced by miracles. This miraculous time is overlaid onto the time of
identity in the depicted world, and the time of the audience for whom the
presentation of the divine epic constitutes an axial transgression of the lived
time of the cinema visit. Another temporality intervenes: the heroic trans-
historical time of the epic, the time of the archetype, the time of recurrence
and pattern. Such a time is not specific to Hindi cinema: it inhabits a certain
strand of European thought from Propp and Jung to the structuralists. The
linearity of time common to modern European thought, however, although
it provides the cut with the logic of causality, is undercut by the fact that
“every story is homeostatic since it simply retraces the disruption left by dis-
order and returns everything to its proper place” (Aumont et al. 1992: 104).
This problem in structural temporality appears rather differently in Hindi
| 68 |
C
h
ap
te
r
3
|
mythic time, where recurrence takes the place of death, functioning as a
treadmill of destiny.
To tell stories inside this cycle is either to break the cycle or to confirm
it. The function of Phalke’s films is to affirm the cycle by reiterating its
founding moments in the legend of the Mahabharata. Thus his films repli-
cate and repeat, and, at the same time, instigate a crux in representation by
offering to show the first foundation of a historical cycle that, because it is
infinite, can have no foundation or beginning. In this way Phalke engages
us with one extreme of the dialectic of effects: the imagination of a moment
of creation when the motive force of narration, the mythic point of origin,
is identified. But there can be no narration without history, just as there can
be no society without language or language without society. We are, then,
predestined to a cycle of recurrence, lacking exactly that impossible mo-
ment of origin which it is Phalke’s privilege, at the founding moment of In-
dian cinema, to figure in his films. In this context, it is important too to note
the playing of Phalke’s wife in the role of Rama’s mother, not the traditional
male: an admission of the sexual in the primal moment, an admission of
Otherness at the moment of origin. Playing on the indefinition of origin,
Phalke is the purest of cutters, first because the cut is an ending that denies
its origin, and second because the cut at its purest creates a dialectic between
flux and cut in the mythic, deferred, and unrepresentable moment of eman-
cipation. It is a dialectical structure of which Hegel might have been proud.
| 69 |
M
ag
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
Th
e
C
u
t
|
4
GRAPHICAL FILM: THE VECTOR
| |
Taking a Line for a Walk
In all these examples the principle and active line develops freely. It
goes out for a walk, so to speak, aimlessly for the sake of the walk.
—Paul Klee1
Undecidability
The poetry of sheer movement in the Sortie,still potent after all these years,
could not maintain itself. Cinema had to move from the sensation of the
event to the perception of objects, from nonidentical immersion to the pro-
liferating unities of navigable space-time. The cut brought the principle of
representation: of delineating commotion as discrete objects in space-time.
To that extent, and to the extent that it implies a subjection of the perceiver,
the cut is always lacking, always inadequate to the plenum it depicts. Its
unity not only implies multiplicity; it exists in a dialectical relation to the
flux of pixels without which it has nothing to organize, but which to it is al-
ways only nothing. Out of that dialectical construction of object and subject
a third principle arises: communication. Immersion in the pixel’s commo-
tion corresponds to Peirce’s firstness, the Lacanian Real; the cut to Peirce’s
secondness, the Lacanian Imaginary. The early history of animation gives
us a privileged glance at the transition to Peirce’s thirdness, the Lacanian
Symbolic, to concept and meaning, socialization, the paradigmatic axis of
film. In deference to its digital destiny, I will refer to it as the vector.
A vector is any quantity that has magnitude and direction. Computer
imaging uses vectors to define shapes by describing their geometry rather
than allocating an address and color value to every pixel. For example, in-
stead of specifying every point on the surface of a sphere, it is far more eco-
nomical to instruct the computer to draw a circle and rotate it about its di-
ameter. In graphical terms, then, a vector is a line moving through time and
space. In the zero of raw movement that first amazed the patrons of the cin-
ematograph there is at base only the invisible motivation of the black frame-
line. In a strict sense, the unities produced by framing, compositing, and
editing make the cinema visible, lifting it from the undifferentiated imma-
nence of the nonidentical to the “being” of the object. The vector takes us
one step further: from being to becoming, from the inertial division of sub-
ject, object, and world to the mobile relationships between them.
In La Sortie,the motion inherent in the instability of the frameline acts
as a given, as something that, since it sums all movement as equilibrium, is
perpetually now. Cutting literally puts an end to the eternal now of the non-
identical. Constructing objects by defining their spatial and temporal limits,
it endows objecthood in the same way it orders time into linear progression:
retrospectively. Terminal (but not final) the cut defines the term and the
terms of objection, transforming raw perception into an object for con-
sciousness, establishing the object as a perception of which an “I” is con-
scious. Even though both object and subject come into existence in the same
instant, the perceiving I perceives the cinematic object as something that
preexists its consciousness of it (since, from the subject’s point of view, the
object has always been there) and that is therefore always already over.
Where the cut instigates endings, the vector enacts beginnings. It gives the
moving image a future, the possibility of becoming otherwise than it is. The
pixel grounds us in the film as a present experience, the cut in the preexis-
tence of the filmstrip to consciousness of it, the vector in the film as the
| 71 |
G
ra
ph
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
V
e
c
to
r
|
becoming of something as yet unseen. It is the principle of transformation,
the quality of changing what we expect from moment to moment.
Causality, logic, law, interpretation, and dialogue belong to this emer-
gence, though they are only historically specific modes of the vector, which
is the openness of thinking to the as-yet unthought, the connection as yet
unmade. In the purest form we have available, the early animations of Emile
Cohl, the principle of cinematic thinking is transformation governed only
by analogy. Debating Umberto Eco’s fictional (1989) and theoretical (1990,
1992) counsels against analogy, Barbara Maria Stafford argues that analogy
not only has the potential to provide sudden and vivid insight, as in the
works of artists like Joseph Cornell; it is also a principle other than causa-
tion or identity that allows us to make connections within and between
media (Stafford 1999: 8). Analogy is moreover intrinsic to the paradigmatic
axis of substitutions, where ostensibly unrelated words (love, dinner, pots,
hay) reveal unforeseen relations when added to the end of the phrase “Let’s
make....” The analogy between a question mark, a cat’s tail and a fishing
rod may not be apparent—until you have seen old Felix the Cat movies,
where they are liable to turn into each other on the sole basis of visual sim-
ilarity. John Canemaker catches this quality of the early 1920s Felix: “Dis-
sembling and reassembling his form, Felix is a Cubist cat, a symbol of
post-war modernism... Felix (especially before Bill Nolan redesigned
him) is full of angles that fragment and juxtapose in exciting new ways”
(Canemaker 1991: 75). As in Braque and Picasso’s analytic paintings of the
1900s, the graphical code works on the basis of likenesses that shift con-
stantly with our perspective on them, so we see a mark as at one moment a
tail, at another a question mark, and simultaneously as nothing less magical
than a line in motion. The vector thus redefines movement as a function of
relations and interactions. Reversing the polarity of the cut, the vector tem-
poralizes space.
The philosopher de Selby of Flann O’Brien’s comic novel The Third Po-
licemanexamines “some old cinematographic films which probably be-
longed to his nephew,” and that, a footnote informs us, he described “as
having ‘a strong repetitive element’ and as being ‘tedious.’ Apparently he
had examined them patiently picture by picture and imagined that they
would be screened in the same way, failing at that time to grasp the principle
of the cinematograph” (O’Brien 1967: 50).
| 72 |
C
h
ap
te
r
4
|
De Selby’s film theory builds on the ancient paradox of Zeno, according
to which Achilles, racing against a tortoise, can never catch it because, hav-
ing given it a start, he must first run half the distance between him and his
competitor, by which time the tortoise has moved on. So Achilles runs half
the new distance, while the tortoise advances another fraction of the dis-
tance, and so on ad infinitum.The ad infinitumis the critical point. Seeking
to prove that the universe is stable, Zeno hit on the concept of the infini-
tesimal, the ever diminishing approach toward zero that, however, never
reaches it: the concept of the infinitely small. Just as you can add a digit to
any cardinal number to make it bigger, so you can add digits to a decimal to
make it smaller. In Zeno’s example, the gap between Achilles and the tortoise
reduces from 1 to 0.5, to 0.25, to 0.125, to 0.0625, and carries on reducing,
always adding more decimal places, toward a zero that it never reaches.
When plotted on a graph, this gives an asymptote, a curve that plunges to-
ward zero but gradually flattens out, never quite arriving at origin.
This asymptotic curve is not composed of points and the distance be-
tween them. The real numbers, the infinitesimals that form the “real” line,
are more geometrical than arithmetic. They cannot be counted and are of-
ten better described as goals toward which the line tends than as numbers.
For the mathematics that dominated the first quarter of the twentieth cen-
tury, undecidability and infinity are inextricably intertwined.2According to
Alan Turing, founding figure of computing, some arithmetical procedures
go on for ever. Turing addressed the “halting problem” through the analogy
of an imaginary computer, itself extraordinarily like a machine for drawing
animations, being composed of an endless strip of paper tape and a read-
write head that would make marks or erase them according to mathematical
rules. In the case of an uncomputable sum like the square root of two, the
machine will never stop. The finally undecidable numerical value of a point
on the real line is the infinite transformational power of the graphic line in
cinema. The infinitesimal adds to cinema the unfinished, unending, unde-
cidable metamorphoses of expectation so poetically manifested in one of
the earliest of animated films, Emile Cohl’s 1908 Fantasmagorie.
Spectator, Author, Animator
James Stuart Blackton, one of Cohl’s few predecessors, performed The En-
chanted Drawingfor Edison (copyrighted in November 1900) and Humour-
ous Phases of Funny Facesfor his own Vitagraph company in 1906, both based
| 73 |
G
ra
ph
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
V
e
c
to
r
|
on variety stage lightning-sketch acts. Both films featured the artist prom-
inently as he would have appeared on stage, with the addition of stop-
motion effects giving the impression that certain of the drawings drew and
animated themselves. In one of the rare accounts of the popular varietyacts
on which these films were based, Matthew Solomon argues that the protean
metamorphoses of quick-change and lightning-sketch artists “quickly
came to represent the path not taken by the new medium” of cinema (Sol-
omon 2000: 17). By drawing attention to Cohl’s work and to thevector code,
I want to offer a counterargument: that the tradition of transformation did
indeed enter cinema, and as a fundamental resource, although the promi-
nence given to photographic realism led to a marginalization of its most
characteristic form, the cartoon (see Cholodenko 1991; Klein 1993; Smoodin
1993, 1994).
Another commentator, Donald Crafton, writes of Blackton’s early ex-
periments that
the spectator was never allowed to forget that he was observing a theatrical per-
formance. The filmmaker (often represented by his hand) was the center of
attention. Yet there were no straight recordings of a performance; each was
slightly altered by camera tricks to create a magical illusion.... For an artist to
be able to bring something to life bestows upon him the status of a privileged
being.... In the cinema, as Bergson said, movement is life, and the ability to
synthesise screen movement was quickly grasped as a magic wand by Blackton
and the others. (Crafton 1993, 86–87)
Crafton rightly emphasizes the performative aspect of these early cartoons,
but he oversimplifies slightly the philosophical complexity of the cartoon-
ing process.
These earliest stop-motion animations address us through the syntax of
the cut. The presence of the artist in the first and the drawing hand in the
second of Blackton’s films cuts by layering the foreground photographic im-
age over the background animation, while the frame edge composes the
plane of the drawing, in The Enchanted Drawingas a chalkboard and in Hu-
mourous Phases (fig. 4.1) as identical with the image plane of the screen.
Whereas the first film comprises a single gag, the second employs stop-
motion not only to give the illusion of self-animating picture, but as a form
of editing that allows a compilation of several scenes over its three-minute
| 74 |
C
h
ap
te
r
4
|
length. In the transition from The Enchanted Drawingto Humourous Phases,
then, the cut extends its powers to order, control, and provide linearity. But
even in the reversal of the process of drawing, when a smudged image be-
comes clear and begins to undraw itself, Humourous Phasesnever finally breaks
with the sheer symmetry of zero’s great balancing of the books, emphasized
by the conclusion of each scene in the erasure of the image. Charming as
they are, these two films of Blackton’s only begin the process of exploration
that will be brought to fruition a couple of years later by Cohl.
To some extent, through its increased dependence on the cut, Hu-
mourous Phasespulls back from the full potential of the animated cartoon by
signaling its subordination to the syntagmatic structures of both the variety
act and of narration. In Cohl’s film, however, we witness a series of transfor-
mations apparently without cutting. Fantasmagorieis a brief line animation
| 75 |
G
ra
ph
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
V
e
c
to
r
|
| Figure 4.1 |
Humourous Phases of Funny Faces:the transition from lightning sketch to animated drawing.
Courtesy BFI Collections.
in which a mischievous puppet, Pierrot or fantoche, and his environment
change seamlessly (see figs. 4.2 , 4.3). Flowers become bottles become a can-
non; an elephant becomes a house; Pierrot becomes a bubble, a hat, a valise.
The vector of Cohl’s line, as it draws and redraws itself, disrespects the frame
edge and equally ignores the syntax of layering, most notably in the small
“screen” that appears at the left of the image as the action with the woman in
the hat takes place. Not only does this appear to reprise the scenes that
wehave just watched, but it also lies on an axis of depth from which the other
characters are debarred. For example, when the little Pierrot gets bigger, it is
not because he is closer to the virtual eye of the rostrum camera, but because
he has been inflated. Likewise, the sword-wielding giant shares the same
plane as the Pierrot. However, it is not simply that the rules of the cut are be-
ing broken: rather, Fantasmagorieobeys another set of rules in the same way
that the real line is bound by laws other than those of Euclidean geometry.
Cohl’s line is the same one that, a mere thirteen years later, Klee would
describe as going for an aimless walk (Klee 1961: 105). It is the activity
oftheline that counts, rather than the end points, which are in effect de-
termined after the fact rather than before it, the result of drawing, not its
givens. Klee, of course, was able to exhibit only finished drawings: Cohl
could show in the cinema the active vector of the line that draws itself. Much
more than an idiosyncratic technique, his constantly permutating line is a
literal transcription of the linear motion of the filmstrip taken as a line that
is always open to alteration, a motion without destination, open to every
distraction. In the cut, the structure of linear motion is complete: in the vec-
tor, it is undecidable. As the grid provides the unstable basis of motion be-
tween images, the vector provides the transformative principle in the frame
itself, so every moment of every frame is the result of a unique transforma-
tion that might have come out differently.
Linguists use the term “paradigmatic” for the rules for substituting one
word for another. The rules of syntax govern the structure of meaningful
sentences. The structure of “My life is an open book” is the same as that of
“His cat is a wicked creature” or “Your teeth are ivory castles.” What differ-
entiates them is the substitution of “his” and “your” for “my,” and “cat” and
“teeth” for “life.” Linguists speak of grammar as the syntagmatic axis and
imagine it as a horizontal line, rather like this line of print. The paradigmatic
axis is correspondingly the vertical axis, like the reels on a slot machine, al-
lowing us to select which word to put into the slots created by the syntax.
| 76 |
C
h
ap
te
r
4
|
Paradigmatic rules govern matters such as the substitution of nouns by
nouns (in the first sentence, we could substitute for “life” words like “face,”
“husband,” “novel,” “bank account”). In Cohl’s film we witness the cine-
matic equivalent. At any point, the line permits its transformation into any-
thing that can be depicted as a line. The rulebook Cohl adopts, and to which
he submits his creative process, stipulates that the line is always the same
thickness and that it describes objects and planes only in outline. Given
those rules, the metamorphoses are potentially infinite, limited only by ex-
ternal constraints such as the length of the film roll and the economic ne-
cessity of finishing in order to show it and earn some money. To gain this
freedom, Cohl sacrifices the grammatical structures that had proved so
profitable, artistically and financially, in the cinema by 1908: editing, narra-
tive, staging in depth. This is why Fantasmagorieis so wonderful to study: it
is a film within a hair’s breadth of being governed by the paradigmatic code
of the vector alone.
In a brief account of the film, Paul Wells emphasizes the element of
chance in the vector code:
Cohl employed a technique in line drawing where the lines would fall randomly
into the frame and converge into a character or event. Cohl’s incoherent cinema
was essentially the free flow of seemingly unrelated images in the stream-of-
consciousness style of the Modernist writers. Further inspection reveals an im-
plied, and more significant, level of relatedness in the imagery, prefiguring later
animated films which trust the elements intrinsic to animation, chiefly, the pri-
macy of the image, and its ability to metamorphoseinto a completely different im-
age. Such metamorphoses operate as the mechanism which foregrounds this
new relatedness by literally revealing construction and deconstruction, stasis
and evolution, mutability and convergence. Such imagery did not operate as a
set of visual tricks or jokes, nor did it constitute a conventional literary narrative,
but was a kinetic construction wholly determined by the choices made by the an-
imator, relating images purely on his own personal terms, sometimes by obvious
association, sometimes by something entirely within the domain of his own psy-
chological and emotional involvement with the visual system. (Wells 1998: 15)3
Wells reads his history backward, crediting Cohl with an inchoate un-
derstanding of the anthropomorphisms of Felix the Cat and Gertie the
Dinosaur, as though Cohl’s permutations of the line are best understood as
| 77 |
G
ra
ph
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
V
e
c
to
r
|
foreshadowing the mature cartooning of animations like Felix the Cat in the
Oily Bird, in which a burglarious chicken jimmies open a window with an
exclamation mark, and Felix lassoes the culprit with the outline of a pond.
Quite rightly, however, Wells also emphasizes that Cohl’s roving, weaving
lines never stabilize into the kind of solidity enjoyed by Gertie, Felix, Mickey,
and the others. And although the reference to deconstruction suggests a
Derridean différanceassociating Fantasmagoriewith the zero of instigation
and equilibrium, like Crafton, Wells’s reference to stream of consciousness
situates Cohl in relation not to Derrida but to Bergson, if not to William
James, in order to anchor the endlessness of metamorphosis in an authorial
psychology.
| 78 |
C
h
ap
te
r
4
|
| Figure 4.2 |
Fantasmagorie:Four years before Griffith’s Those Awful Hats, Cohl satirizes women’s headgear.
The line momentarily describes 3-D space, only to redefine it as a pure surface in the next metamorphosis.
Reproduced from Crafton (1990) with permission.
Three major arguments are raised against cinematic authorship: that
filmmaking is social production; that any artisan is as much the tool of her
craft as vice versa (Barthes 1977a); and that the construction of authorship
is a mode of cataloging with no more and possibly less relevance to a text
than its date, publisher, geographical origin, or any one of a hundred other
determinants (Foucault 1979). However, if it is the case that a film is a prod-
uct of social forces, then film scholarship cannot ignore the critical impor-
tance of individuation as a result of social process, however unwanted or
illusory. The issue has been raised by many feminist and antiracist scholars,
appalled that the academy should abandon the concept of authorship at the
very moment at which women, African Americans, British Asians, and other
ethnic groups have achieved significant recognition as cultural authors.
Their argument is significant here because, as Adorno argues, art is com-
pelled “to undergo subjective mediation in its objective constitution”
(Adorno 1997: 41).
In fact, for Adorno, this is an integral element of modern art, which
takes up the task of negating the atomism of a divided and individuated so-
ciety: “If the artist’s work is to reach beyond his own contingency, then he
must in return pay the price that, in contrast to the discursively thinking
person, he cannot transcend himself and the objectively established bound-
aries” (ibid.: 42). Unlike philosophy, art cannot transgress the borders of re-
ality, nor can the artist pretend to have negated his own subjectivity. Instead,
the passage through the individual author actually strengthens the claims of
art to communicate the social, something it could not do if it werefree of
the individuation that so deeply marks contemporary society. Crafton’s bril-
liant biography of Cohl is important not because it reveals the deep psy-
chology of the “stream of consciousness” that Wells believes in, but because
it situates that creative mind in a historical society whose traces are deeply
marked on Cohl’s career and creations. Adorno casts further light on the
temporalities of animation when he concludes that “every idiosyncracy lives
from collective forces of which it is unconscious” (ibid.). The intimate per-
sonality of a mark, the idiom that allows us to recognize a Klee or a Picasso
line, is an articulation not of an irreducible and total personality but quite
the opposite: it sums all those social and historical forces that congregate in
the idiosyncratic act of making, even in the decision to make, in the artists’
understanding of why and how they make, in the very movement of the hand.
| 79 |
G
ra
ph
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
V
e
c
to
r
|
The film’s innocence of narrative coherence is a function of its inno-
cence of key frames. Later, more industrialized animation studios would di-
rect their leading animators to provide frames that defined the beginning
and end of a motion. Junior staff would then be hired for “in-betweening,”
drawing only the frames required to provide a smooth transition between
key frames. In Cohl’s case, there are no key frames: no line’s action is ever
complete, but metamorphoses into the next without the stability and unifi-
cation afforded by key framing. At the same time, these are not just doodles
but drawings in the process of becoming pictures of something. The dis-
tracted, dreamy reverie of the pixel immerses us in the Real, the referent in
Saussure’s semiotics. The syntax of the cut transforms these sensations into
signifieds, representations, the chain of cinematic objects. The vector is the
dimension of the signifier: “Pierrot” becomes the wending line. The signi-
fier is the material of signification, and its task is not to represent but to be
exchanged. Because Cohl’s line is a line, a material signifier, it can exchange
signifier for signifier, on the principle of analogy. It is the token of exchange
between object and object in metamorphosis, and so adumbrates the ex-
change of subjectivities that is communication. Cohl’s line is not his con-
sciousness materialized, but the medium of social exchange. It does not
represent: it communicates.
At every moment, Cohl’s paradigmatic signifiers may become other
than they are in the present. The meaning of this shape depends on the
substitutions and transformations to which, as material signifier, it is open.
The vector of Fantasmagorieis never complete. So it has to change inter-
minably—and so does its interpreter. It is as if the vector’s subjectivity is
constantly launching itself outward, like a child playing, or even more like a
playground full of children racing from game to game, persona to persona,
utterly invested in what happens next. The cut anchors motion in destiny,
in the necessity of an ending. In the vector, there is nothing behind—every-
thing is in front. Mathematically, the pixel is perfectly symmetrical: the
same in any direction. The cut breaks that symmetry by establishing the
principle of being: what has become. The cut is teleological, determined by
its ending. The vector breaks it on a different axis, treating what is as the be-
ginning of becoming. The vector is eschatological: its future is open, gov-
erned only by hope.
Fantasmagorieis not, then, a simple stream of consciousness. Instead,
that stream is the raw material for a job of work, subjecting the preconscious
| 80 |
C
h
ap
te
r
4
|
firstness of undifferentiated sensation to the machinery of production. If we
try to imagine Cohl’s stream of consciousness, we have to imagine him con-
templating how the public and, differently, the producer will respond; how
to get around the constraints of his technology; submitting to fatigue and
the economic imperative to stop. In all these moments, our imaginary Cohl
inhabits a nexus of exchange, with living customers, with networks of trade,
with the dead labor embodied in chalk, chalkboard, camera, and rostrum.
Mere firstness would produce nothing but a chaotic scribble. Mad scrawl-
ing would merely flag a pretended liberation from individuation, but one in
reality still governed by the rational image of individuation: a resistance that
depends on the dominant that it resists.
Cohl’s animation, however, neither succumbs to the administrative
principle of the cut (secondness would imply simple depiction, in the mode
of Winsor McKay), nor pretends to a schizophrenic loss of subjectivity. In-
stead it reaches out from the unhappy mismatch between the universality of
preconscious difference and the particularity of ordered unity, toward a
freedom they cannot achieve separately or together, but toward which their
struggle necessarily points. This is not the freedom of the “free” market or
“free” choice, terms that scarcely mask the monopolistic character of con-
temporary capitalism. Rather, it is a capacity to exist otherwise than under
those conditions. Only by accepting the subjective role of individuality in
authorship can we understand how it can be overcome: not by regression to
infantile states, nor by the simple negativity of irrationalism, but by con-
structing semantic behaviors that at once expose the social failure to recon-
cile chaos and order, preconscious and reason, and at the same time produce
techniques for another way of making that is subservient to neither and that,
although it can neither reconcile nor negate them, poses the possibility of
meaning.
It is easier to make this case for Cohl than for most subsequent film-
makers. As an artisan, he had far greater control over the processes of film-
making than any studio-based producer. But there is a third level to the
subjectivities involved in the making of Fantasmagoriethat makes it an espe-
cially fruitful study. It is possible Cohl had seen the Blackton films. Cer-
tainly he was fascinated by cinema, and as an active participant in the
Bohemian life of Paris for thirty years prior to his first films he would have
been technologically and scientifically literate. Nonetheless, his practice in
making Fantasmagoriemust have been almost purely experimental. What
| 81 |
G
ra
ph
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
V
e
c
to
r
|
speeds to move things at, how long to hold a frame or a pose, at what pace
to render a transformation: all of these he must have been experimenting
with as he went along. He would not have been able to view any of his work
until all the drawings had been made and photographed. Is this a human
psychology at work, or the liberation of an entirely modern sensibility
through the subordination of will, of authorial psychology, to the agency of
technology?
The Lumières’ negotiations over the supply of film stock documented
in their correspondence makes it clear that they could have gone for square
or circular frames, or the portrait format of many of their autochromes.
Certain technical constraints made it simpler to go for the landscape format
still ubiquitous today. Like the mechanism of the sewing machines incor-
porated into the cinematograph’s claw mechanism for film transport, the
rectangular frame fixes, as fixed capital, the dead labor of generations of
handicraft. But like the anonymity of the printing press and the adding ma-
chine, that fixing bears also a gift of autonomy. In the new machine, dead la-
bor is restored to new life. The invention of offscreen space is not a product
of human ingenuity but of a new mode of life: the human-machine hybrid
built on the anonymous autonomy of the machine and the autonomous
anonymity of the industrial worker under commodity capital. The condi-
tions of modernity prized invention and inventiveness above all, because
they helped the acceleration of consumerism on which the new wealth was
predicated. The ensemble of economics, technology, and the anarchic modes
of Lyons syndicalism in the Lumières, old bourgeois carnival in Méliès,and
Parisian bohemianism in Cohl combine to form the apparatus of cinema.
That apparatus, with its doorway through which consciousness can enter
and reside mesmerized, as producer as well as audience, crystallizes the con-
tradictions of attentiveness and distraction into a single productive machin-
ery of delight.
In Cohl, the result, as so often in computer media, is an expression of
wonder at the new relation with machines. The latest gift of the technolo-
gization of the media circa 1908 was freedom from psychology. The atten-
tion devoted to physiological and unconscious reflexes, to hypnosis and the
psychoanalytic unconscious, especially in its more mechanical “economic”
model, help pinpoint this as a moment at which excitement and invention
arose neither from consciousness nor from fantasy but from an autonomy
granted to the interface between craftsman and tool. By 1908, this tool was
| 82 |
C
h
ap
te
r
4
|
already a complex and quasi-autonomous machine—Fox-Talbot’s “pencil
of nature”—capable of partnership in the creative act.
Fantasmagorie is the product of a kind of willful ignorance achieved
through the submission of the willed act of drawing to the unmanaged op-
eration of machinery. At the same time, because it is no longer the object of
control, the machinery itself sheds the role of relation of production, which
it occupied in the industrial factory. In Marxist terms no longer a relation
but a force of production, the camera enables Cohl to rid himself of both the
irrationalism of preconscious difference and the instrumental rationality of
socialized technologies of production. The autonomy and anonymity of
Cohl’s line should not be confused with randomness: they are achieved only
through the thoughtful and decisive acceptance of determinations external
to the work itself, since that is the only way those determinations could be
superseded and a new, distinctively modern mode of cinema be produced.
The secret consciousness of the vector is this human-mechanical hybrid.
Hence we can no longer speak of the author as originator of the cartoon: in-
stead we are confronted with the animator, no longer a subject of the social
world, but an exile seeking asylum in the machine world from all demands
external to the work itself. We might think of the animator as the subjectiv-
ity of the text. For both audience and author, consciousness is an external
factor that is nonetheless intrinsic to the making and experiencing of the
film. From the point of view of the film itself, however, history enters the
film through cyborg authorship and socialized interpretation, qualities that
are as much raw materials as light and time. For the author, the time of mak-
ing is a time in which the future becomes past; for the spectator, one in
which the past becomes future; but for the animator, the present is the bi-
furcation of all vectors, the moment of autonomy.
It is, however, only a moment. Where the ancients disputed the neces-
sity of ontegeny with theories of autocthony and parthenogenesis, since the
birth of cinema we moderns maneuver at the unclear frontier between hu-
man and machine. But like the metamorphoses celebrated by Ovid two
thousand years ago, where the human-animal border is crossed in joy and in
pain, the beauty of the animator’s autonomous present must be ephemeral:
its pleasures must be fleeting so that we can know that cruelty too will pass.
In this sense, ugliness, as the grotesque and as depicted violence, is the last
bastion of representation, the remote picturing of the savage necessities of
contemporary life. In the digital era, these are characteristically enacted in
| 83 |
G
ra
ph
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
V
e
c
to
r
|
the paranoid-depressive movie of the data-image, in films like The Netand
Enemy of the State,and the manic-psychotic movie of technology out of con-
trol, of which Terminator 2 and The Matrixare only the best known. Their
concern, which can be traced back to Fantasmagorie,is with a fleeting pres-
ent in which distinct definitions of human and machine are not possible, a
moment of semantic and categorial play intrinsic to the mimetic precisely
at that point where it is no longer representational, a point at which the cri-
terion of resemblance is most at risk.
In Cohl, we can trace the genealogy of this indistinct human-machine
relation. The vector in Fantasmagorie, the unstable, ephemeral line, moves
into and away from resemblance in a constant play of instability. We ask re-
peatedly what the line is becoming, but have only the briefest moment for
the pleasure of recognition before it changes again. What we witness here is
the moment at which naming occurs, but a naming that is already subject to
the paradigmatic substitutions that underlie all interpretations. The mean-
ing it produces—the kind of meaning that allows us to recognize the line as
a horse or a spider—is itself ephemeral. In this way, though the film itself is
limited to its fifty-second duration, Cohl’s line demonstrates that the pos-
sible substitutions are infinite in number. Becoming signified, the line is un-
fixed. It is a lens through which pass the infinities of interpretation.
Dynamics of the Vector
For Adorno, the world was already negative, degraded by its very modernity.
Art’s task was to negate that negativity. For us, however, at the dawn of the
twenty-first century, the world’s negativity has already been negated by the
engulfing denegation of the commodity form in the society of the spectacle.
For all their pessimism, Jean Baudrillard’s analyses of contemporary (West-
ern) society as a simulation machine make a powerful case for the loss of the
world. Baudrillard believes that reality was constituted in the differences be-
tween real things; but under the conditions of serial production, there are
no longer any differences between things (Baudrillard 1993a: 55). Worse
still, the same is true of communication: “Communication, by banalizing
the interface, plunges the social into an undifferentiated state” (Baudrillard
1993b: 12). The proliferation of identical mass media messages, the mass
production of public opinion, the unchanging frame of the browser window
or the VDU, the obligation to participate even when we have nothing to say,
all conspire to produce a hyperreal social process in which all communica-
| 84 |
C
h
ap
te
r
4
|
tions are undifferentiated and to that extent unreal. In the digital era, ac-
cording to simulation theory, the world has been transformed into data, and
the data has negated the world. But if the world has already been negated,
art that seeks to negate it again is only doing the work of simulation. There-
fore art can no longer afford to be negative: in our time, art’s work must be
positive.
The vector is critical to this reorientation of cultural work as a positive
production of meaning and, since all meaning depends on shared commu-
nication, of society in a time when, as Baudrillard argues, the social itself has
been derealized. In this light, we should not read the absence of keyframes
in Fantasmagorieas a negation of editing. Rather, it is the positive depiction
of the act of drawing at the moment when the work of representing hangs in
the balance between resemblance and the pure mark. Without keyframes to
anchor it in a unified shape, the mark achieves a determined autonomy in
which its resemblance to objects in the external world is constantly in ques-
tion and so both open to the uncertainties of interpretation and anchored in
the social from which its idiosyncracy arose and where all interpretation
takes place. The idiosyncracy of the line as a trace of its maker and the idio-
syncracy of infinitesimally graduated differences in interpretation are the
social grounds on which cinema moves from the presentation of objects to
the stimulation of concepts. The vector does not tell us what to expect: it
requires us to think. In this way the vector brings us into the realm of the in-
tellect and offers us the delight we take in the pursuit of meaning. The vec-
tor is the art of curiosity.
Cohl’s mobile mark, the animated line as a visible and visual practice, is
a device of metamorphosis, in which the emphasis should lie on the prefix
“meta”. As metamorphosis (and as opposed to the computerized technique
of morphing), the line is not the “in-between” of two fixed states or two an-
chored points but the action of becoming that may or may not result in a
fixed state such as a keyframe. The grid depends on the copresence of un-
differentiated viewer and viewed; the cut organizes the indifference of flux
into being by separating viewer from viewed in the subject-object relation;
the vector depends on the recognition of the autonomy of both viewer and
viewed. It extends and deepens the separation of the grid by instigating a
recognition of the object as other rather than as dependent on the viewing
subject. Keyframes anchor the changing line at moments of cutting, for ex-
ample, in the identifiable faces between morphs in the Michael Jackson
| 85 |
G
ra
ph
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
V
e
c
to
r
|
| 86 |
C
h
ap
te
r
4
|
| Figure 4.3 |
Fantasmagorie:endless permutations of the line in perpetual transformation.
Reproduced from Crafton (1990) with permission.
| 87 |
G
ra
ph
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
V
e
c
to
r
|
video Black or White. By contrast, the struggle to recognize and name the
metamorphosing line in Cohl, always incomplete, never settles in identity
but constantly remakes the relation between subject and object as that be-
tween self and other. In this way it cannot, as the Jackson video does, suborn
the technology of morphing to commit to a color-blind ideology of liberal
multiculturalism (Sobchack 2000; on multiculturalism, see Zizek 1997;
Araeen 2000). Instead it confronts the uneasiness of the viewed with its sta-
tus as object of the view, forced by its endless mutation to recognize its au-
tonomous existence, an autonomy that at once confronts the viewer with the
limitations to control and with her own instability.
The autonomy of the line in Fantasmagorieis, as we have already seen, a
product of the relation between Cohl and his apparatus. On a certain under-
standing of the technological relation, for example, that voiced by McLuhan
(1964) when he describes tools as extensions of the hand, the relation be-
tween human and machine is purely one of control. The machine is an in-
strument of humans, and that instrumental relationship defines the user and
the used as subject and object. What Cohl’s practice reveals is that another
relation is possible, one in which the privilege of subjectivity is abandoned
in favor of granting an autonomy to the machine equivalent to that assumed
by the user. The new relation between human and machine isthen no longer
instrumental but ethical, in the sense advanced by Emmanuel Levinas, since
it demands a mutual recognition of each other’s right to be, beyond the re-
lationship itself. No longer dependent on Cohl’s authoring control, the ma-
chine is free to collaborate in the creation of the work—or to refuse, as is so
often the case when we try to enlist the aid of a recalcitrant computer in
some task we are unsure of. This is not to ascribe intelligence to the ma-
chine, but to emphasize that it is capable of rich and complex relationships
with humans. The pacing of the transformations in Fantasmagorieis one
such example of machinic contributions to creativity; another is the possi-
bility of animated drawing.
The last remnant of the older lightning-sketch acts in Cohl’s film is the
appearance of his hands. The very appearance of the hand in the opening
shot of the film is a conundrum. According to Crafton (1990: 121, 140) and
Abel (1994: 286), Cohl drew the bulk of the film in black India ink on trans-
lucent white paper over a lightbox and then printed the film in negative to
achieve the white-on-black effect. The effect of the hand drawing the fan-
tochein the opening frames must have been shot by another method, and dif-
| 88 |
C
h
ap
te
r
4
|
ferently printed, so that the hand would not appear in negative. So the mo-
ment at which the hand withdraws and the drawing comes to life is also a
moment in which the film process is reversed, as must also be the case with
the second entry of the hands when they appear to reassemble the broken
fantocheafter his fall from the house. The first of these moments is the equiv-
alent of the moment of shock when the still projection of the Lumière cin-
ematograph suddenly began to move; but it is a new effect in the sense that
the transition to a purely machinic vision (negative) and to an animation
without the support of a visible maker introduce the sense of the cinema ap-
paratus as autonomous participant in creation.
The drawing hand in the opening frames and the mending hands later
on can also give us a sense of the structure guiding the relations between hu-
man and mechanical collaborators. In the latter case in particular, we are
confronted with the three-dimensionality of the fantochewho, though flat,
can be picked up. There is of course a self-reflexive joke here, but at the same
time we are offered a second way of viewing the film. The movement be-
tween animated and photographed actions works on the paradigmatic axis,
integrating two diegeses, one the fictional world of the drawings, the other
the “real” world of filmmaking. Whereas the first entry of the drawing hand
is explicable as a throwback to the lightning-sketch genre, the second adds
a whole new axis to the film, attributing autonomy to both the fantocheand
the maker in addition to the autonomy of the apparatus. This is effected
through a paradigmatic substitution of real for drawn hands in an action
parallel to the cubist application of found papers (newspaper, wallpaper,
labels, tickets) in Picasso’s and Braque’s breakthrough papiers collés of au-
tumn 1912 to spring 1913. One of the effects of the substitution in cubist col-
lage was to assert the independence of the world from the artist, who no
longer translated it into paint, but could apply items from it directly to the
surface of the work. In the cubist case, this also entailed alertness to the fact
that these cut-out pieces of printed material were already signs, already arti-
facts of a thriving visual culture. In Cohl’s case, the gluing hands admit that
they too are already a part of the apparatus of cinema. They disrupt the
grammar of the cut, but only to extend the capabilities of film.
There is no documentary evidence that these are Cohl’s hands, cer-
tainly, but they are presented generically as the hands of the maker. The
presence of the photographed hand for that instant at the beginning of
thefilm is thus a kind of signature, but one that presents itself in the act of
| 89 |
G
ra
ph
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
V
e
c
to
r
|
disappearing in a process of subordination to the autonomy of machine.
The hand as motif returns in the final frame, but now as a drawn hand, as
thefantochewaves to the audience from his horse. The whole film, then,
moves from the hand as instrument of control—the photographed, autho-
rial hand—to the gesture of waving goodbye, from authorial power to spec-
tatorial address via the autonomy of the relation, embodied in the fantoche,
between maker and apparatus. By reserving the act of mending for a pho-
tographed moment, the film reasserts the partnership, and appeals to an
ethical commitment of the maker to the creation, as that creation takes on a
life of its own. That act allows the spectator to enter into the role of the per-
son addressed by the film. As Sobchack argues, this is a critical instance in
cinema, one in which the recognition of the film as a body that signifies is
also one in which we recognize the film as an other: “Thus, while still objec-
tifying visual activity into the solidity of the visible as does the photograph,
the cinematic qualitatively transforms and converts the photographic
through a materiality that not only claims the world and others as objects for
vision but also signifies its own bodily agency, intentionality and subjectiv-
ity” (Sobchack 1992: 62).
In Sobchack’s semiotic phenomenology, the photograph belongs to
what I have here been calling the regime of the cut. The “cinematic,” which
in this instance equates to the concept of the vector, moves beyond objecti-
fication toward a process in which the film is able to take on the task of sig-
nifying. As a material body that signifies, film becomes an other. Only at this
moment does the cinematic subject become a self, capable of social rela-
tions. This is when the vector socializes film.
The Cinematic Sign
The first evidence of the vector’s socialization of the cinema is interpreta-
tion. Film always calls on us to interpret it. In the case of Fantasmagorie,
where the activity of the vector is controlled to only the most limited degree
by the structure of the cut, that interpretation is not governed by gestalts
that order and predestine our negotiations with the text. Rather, Cohl’s film
activates a constant engagement of the viewer in guessing not only “what
happens next” but “what is it doing now,” inferring the agency of the film it-
self. Even such a rigorously minimal figure as the fantochecan evoke emo-
tions of sympathy, extending beyond identification to action, encoded in the
mending of the broken puppet. More specifically, the film calls up a series
| 90 |
C
h
ap
te
r
4
|
of responses that take the form of a running commentary on the film, an in-
ner speech.
The notion of cinematic inner speech was first broached by Boris
Eikhenbaum in 1927. Reading silent film as a syncretic form of photogeny
(defined as “an art which uses the language of movement” [Eikhenbaum
1974: 17]) and montage, he sees it overcoming the medium-specificity of
the older arts, and evoking in its viewers an inner speech that comments on
the film, its phrasing, its metaphors, and the gaps between shots. This inner
speech “is much more flowing and indefinite than uttered speech” (ibid.:
16), and it “is not realised as an exact verbal formulation” (ibid.: 31). As Paul
Willemen notes, this inner speech is compounded of iconographic, sym-
bolic, and visual codes as well as verbal ones. Citing Vygotsky’s (1962) argu-
ment that inner speech is characterized by a tendency to omit the subject of
the sentence while emphasizing its power of predication, Willemen argues
that inner speech’s blending of visual and verbal presentations in an internal
dialogue on the one hand establishes the internal dialectics of the viewer’s
psyche and at the same time becomes “the cement between text, subject and
the social” (Willemen 1994: 42). The process is clear to anyone who has
attempted a frame-by-frame analysis: we say “the line does this,” emphasiz-
ing the predicate, not the subject that does the predicating. Eikhenbaum’s
argument is that this is also true of film, which shows us events and objects
without implying a someone who does the showing. This isomorphism sub-
sumes the moment of subjectivity enacted in the cut to its disappearance in
the communication of meanings.
The vector’s particular future-directed temporality addresses us no
longer as termini but as media: as people who make sense, but only as nodes
in interweaving trajectories of signification. It is no longer a matter of
recognition, of deciphering what is already encoded. Rather it is a matter of
reinterpreting, of adding a new spin to a trajectory that has not yet realized
itself. The vector is the regime in which the temporality and the labor of
makingsense is paramount. If in the pixel we are engaged by an undifferen-
tiated union with the visual, and in the cut by the subjection-objection pair,
in the vector we confront the double presence of the screen image as at once
object and image, such that what we normally expect to be true of the ob-
ject—for example, that it possesses a single, discrete, and stable identity—
is no longer the case. No longer pointing to an entity separate and opposed
to us, but offering itself as medium, the image becomes cinematic sign. Like
| 91 |
G
ra
ph
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
V
e
c
to
r
|
every sign, it implies the existence of other signs. To say of one of Cohl’s
lines that it “is” a flower, an elephant, or a house is inaccurate. On the one
hand, it is only legible as referring to (conventional images of) flowers, ele-
phants, and houses for brief moments in a trajectory that is never stable. On
the other, it is always a line, a signifier, which is what gives it its transforma-
tive power.
The line, like the written word, speaks to us simultaneously as the
drawn/written and as the act of drawing/writing, as iconic sign and as the in-
complete, infinite process of signifying. Thierry Kuntzel voices this in a rare
theoretical essay on animation, arguing that photographic frames repro-
duce, but animated frames produce. Distinguishing between the grid of the
filmstrip laid out for analysis and the film-projection we experience in the
cinema, he describes the function I have been terming the vector thus: “The
animator conceives the film-strip (each photogram, the articulation be-
tween the photograms) in relation to the film-projection and in relation to
a meaning which movement will actually bring about” (Kuntzel 1979: 52).
Meaning is a function of the transition from the découpage, the analytic eye
of the editor, to the trajectory of movement, brought about in the relin-
quishing of the animating hand to machinic projection.
In the graphic code of the vector in Fantasmagorieit is possible to descry
that rare creature, a signifier without a signified. Cohl’s cyborg cinema ap-
proaches Peircean thirdness, “synthetic consciousness binding time to-
gether, sense of learning, thought” (Peirce 1991: 185), at its purest. The cut
established signifieds as the products of subject-object relations, grounded
in the resistance of the world to consciousness. Divorcing perceiver and
perceived, it establishes time as a serial process of distinct causes and effects,
hidings and revealings, insides and outsides. The vector synthesizes the
multiple times of transformation into a trajectory that engages the delight
we take in thinking the ambiguities and ambivalences with which it flavors
the rough parceling of the world in the cut. In Peirce’s terms, the cinematic
sign is a symbol, “any utterance of speech which signifies what it does only
by virtue of its being understood to have that signification” (ibid. 240). Fan-
tasmagorieis such an “utterance,” dependent on interpretation, on the active
participation of the viewer in its production, and otherwise merely a redun-
dant collection of scribbles. Explaining thirdness, Eco speaks of a line draw-
ing of a circle and some inverted Ws, denoting sun and birds: “First I had to
| 92 |
C
h
ap
te
r
4
|
decide that they were two signs that stood for something, and only afterward
did I try to understand them” (Eco 1999: 386). The first moment is that of
secondness, of identifying the marks as objects that denote. Only in the sub-
sequent moment of thirdness do we arrive at whatthey denote. This move-
ment of subjectivity from recognition to mediation is the achievement of
Fantasmagorie.
The cinematic object does not require this interpretive moment, but
the animated vector depends on our synthetic participation in its becoming,
on the viewer’s temporality (and on the apparatus’s). As exchange, the signi-
fier represents a subject for another signifier: it is a passage from subject to
subject. But by the same token, subjectivity never originates signification.
Instead it too is a passage that focuses and distributes signification, the ani-
mator of a vector of signification that flows through her (from the point of
view of viral language, “I” am only a medium for reproduction and muta-
tion). In this way, too, the cinematic sign leads us toward the socialization of
vision at the point at which cinema becomes Symbolic.
Lacan thinks of the Symbolic (for which I will reserve the initial capi-
tal) as the order of both consciousness (the “I”) and of language, social sys-
tems, and all structures that enable meaning and communication. Entry
into the Symbolic comes in the Oedipal moment in which the child first
internalizes the psychoanalysist’s founding rule: the prohibition against
incest. Whether one accepts the specific instance or not, Symbolization de-
pends on passing a threshold when first we learn that socialization is gov-
erned by rules. Following the mirror phase, in which the infant acquires the
ability to identify with his or her own likeness narcissistically, the Symbolic
constructs the more abstract sense of an ego marked by the word “I.”But be-
cause this word is used equally by any conscious speaker, the Symbolic per-
mits an extension of identification beyond identification with oneself,
toward identification with an other.
Though Lacan’s pessimistic account of socialization sees this process as
one of loss, instilling a permanent and ineradicable sense of lack in the hu-
man adult, there is nevertheless a gain. From indifferent immersion in the
world, via a narcissistic (and sadistic) separation between subject and object-
world, we emerge into a socialized universe. If for psychoanalysis, with its
individualist premise, this represents a loss of primal unity, for a more social
theory it marks the acquisition of those fundamental communicative skills
| 93 |
G
ra
ph
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
V
e
c
to
r
|
that allow us to enter into relationships not just with ourselves but with
autonomous others. Fantasmagorie’s multiple acts of cruelty and the penul-
timate act of kindness (mending the puppet) might be read allegorically as
an account of that Oedipal transition from the isolated self as pure and static
image in the opening frames, through confrontation and breakage, to a sub-
mission to the other (the photographed hands) that enables socialization
(the fantoche’s final wave to the audience).
Of course, this allegorical reading is very much an interpretation after
the fact. Crafton’s careful analysis (accompanied by an invaluable set of 69
frame stills documenting the film) emphasizes the cruelty of Fantasmagorie
(Crafton 1990: 258–266). Both he and Abel (1994: 286) stress the spon-
taneity and fluidity of the images as analogous with dream states. Wells, as
we have seen, stresses the authorial stream of consciousness. Bendazzi con-
trasts Cohl with his North American predecessor Blackton, who “was al-
ways careful to introduce or justify the presence of a cartooned world next
to a real world. On the contrary, the Frenchman jumped into the graphic
universe, animating the adventures of autonomous characters” (Bendazzi
1994: 9). None of these accounts, with the partial exception of Crafton, is
moved to analyze the film as narrative. Reading Fantasmagorieas a story is
subsequent to experiencing it as a formally (but never absolutely) autono-
mous signifying agent.
In a discussion of the foundations of a philosophy of space, Henri
Lefebvre raises the specter of autonomy in the context of the commodity:
Things—which for Marx are the product of social labour, destined to be ex-
changed and invested for this reason with value in a double sense, with use-value
and exchange-value—both embody and conceal social relations. Things would
thus seem to be the underpinning of those relations. And yet, on the Marxist
analysis, it is clear that things quacommodities cease to be things. And inasmuch
as they remain things, they become “ideological objects” overburdened with
meanings. Quacommodities, things can be resolved into relations; their exis-
tence is then purely abstract—so much so indeed that one is tempted to see noth-
ing in them apart from signs and signs of signs (money). (Lefebvre 1991: 402)
Lefebvre’s missing underpinning, neither Logos nor empiricist material-
ism, is communication: the primacy of relations, even though those rela-
| 94 |
C
h
ap
te
r
4
|
tions are expressed in the autonomous form of signifiers that, in cinema,
take on the commodity’s monstrous property of repeating relations back to
people in the guise of objects. The fluidity of Fantasmagorie’s metamor-
phoses enacts the resolution of commodities back into relations, relations of
mediation, signification, and communication that perpetually test the lim-
its of and propose alternatives to the dominance of money as the signifying
chain par excellence that governs communication under capital.
To confront the autonomy of the signifier is to come face to face with
the film as other. In the philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas, the confronta-
tion with the other is the foundation of ethics in a transition from freedom
to socialization. The subject is free in the sense that it is “for itself,” but this
comes at the price of solipsism: “in knowing itself or representing itself it
possesses itself, dominates itself, extends its identity to what of itself comes
to refute this identity. This imperialism of the same is the whole essence of
freedom” (Levinas 1969: 87). The knowledge the subject has of itself is a
mode of representation—the cut—that allows it to control both its world
and itself as objects. Confronted with the other, the subject becomes self in
recognizing the limits to its sameness, its control and its freedom. It does so
because in the other it is forced to recognize another’s freedom. “Morality
begins,” argues Levinas, “when freedom, instead of being justified by itself,
feels itself to be arbitrary and violent” (ibid.: 84). The ethical arises when the
subject confronts an object that is as free as itself, a confrontation with the
other that brings with it the realization that domination over the object is at
once arbitrary and homogenizing. Recognizing the freedom of the other
limits my freedom, but freedom can have no limits. Therefore the self is not
free, but forced to take the other into account, to be responsible for the
other, since the other defines the limit of freedom.
At the same time, knowledge of the other alters our relations to the
world. “Certitude rests, in fact, on my freedom and is in this sense solitary”
(Levinas 1969: 100), whereas “the locus of truth is society” (ibid.: 101). Cer-
tainty that we possess the unique and absolute truth belongs to the order of
the subject, but connection with others opens to us the limits of certainty,
since they too have their own and different certain knowledge. The possi-
bility of truth then depends on the society of interpretations, on mediation.
Certainty is a kind of destiny: it determines what it is possible to know,
by defining the world as the object of a subject and subordinating it to that
| 95 |
G
ra
ph
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
V
e
c
to
r
|
subject’s identity. Thus, apparently paradoxically, freedom is synonymous
with necessity, whereas responsibility, duty, and care free the self to the pos-
sibility of change.
For Vivian Sobchack, this confrontation with the other occurs also in
the cinema: “What we look at projected on the screen... addresses us as the
expressed perception of an anonymous, yet present, “other.”... [T]he con-
cretely embodied situation of the film’s vision also stands againstthe viewer.
It is also perceived by the viewer as a “There where I am not,” as the space
consciously and bodily inhabited by an “other” whose experience of being-
in-the-world, however anonymous, is not precisely congruent with the
viewer’s own” (Sobchack 1992: 9–10). We can see here why Wells so easily
slips into reading Fantasmagorieas evidence of a specific human other, the
author, Emile Cohl, because film presents itself to the viewer as an other ca-
pable of signifying and thus possessing its own freedom. But the film is more
“other” even than that. It is not the sole product of an author but evidence
of a cyborg integration of human and machine into a signifying apparatus.
It is that apparatus that confronts us as the other in vectoral cinema.
The certitude we bring to the identification of the world as object or
collection of objects is, in Levinas’s terms, thinking in the mode of totality,
“a reduction of all experience, of all that is reasonable, to a totality wherein
consciousness embraces the world, leaves nothing outside of itself, and
thus becomes absolute thought” (Levinas 1985: 75). Universal and imper-
sonal, this totality is also inhuman. Levinas contrasts totality with infinity,
an open-ended relation based in the necessarily incomplete relation with
theother. “If one could possess, grasp and know the other, it would not be
other” (1989: 51): the possession, grasping, and knowing that characterize
the subject of totality are impossible to the self of infinity, who instead must
face the circumscription of selfish freedom by the opposing freedom of al-
terity. In the vector’s endless permutations and substitutions, we come face
to face with an other whose freedom resists total knowledge. Its radical
otherness and the infinity of interpretations and negotiations it entails em-
body the impossible object of desire. For Levinas, “what is at stake is soci-
ety. Here the relation connects not terms that complete one another and
consequently are reciprocally lacking to one another, but terms that suffice
to themselves. This relation is Desire” (1969: 103).
Signifying, then, is no longer Lacan’s endlessly thwarted pursuit of com-
pletion down the endless chains of signifiers, but a richness of infinite vari-
| 96 |
C
h
ap
te
r
4
|
ety in the paradigmatic twists and turns of the vector and the parallel rolls and
tumbles of the self that enters into dialogue with it. The cyborg mode of the
cinematic other, whether mechanical as in Cohl’s practice or inscribed as
computer algorithms in digital vector graphics, opens a society of image and
spectator where desire is the mutual attraction of autonomous selves rather
than the subject’s narcissistic pursuit of lost dominance over its object.
This social relation of desire as dialogue has implications for the theory
of representation. Seen from the standpoint of graphical cinema, represen-
tation is never essential. As Lev Manovich argues, “Born from animation,
cinema pushed animation to its boundary, only to become one particular
case of animation in the end” (Manovich 1997: 180). At some point in the
near future when historians recognize that the photomechanical cinema is a
brief interlude in the history of the animated image, representation will be-
come, like narrative, a subcode of interpretation rather than an essence of
motion pictures. In a discussion of visual perception, Jacques Aumont ob-
serves that a two-dimensional projection of a three-dimensional space “may
be projected as an infinite number of potential objects” (Aumont 1997a: 24),
whereas “an infinite number of possible objects could produce this [flat]
configuration” (ibid.: 33). He points out that on empiricist accounts of per-
ception, accumulated experience leads to the “correct” identification of the
object. Empiricism, however, is grounded in the belief in objects. The vec-
tor principle of desire as dialogue between autonomous selves reanimates
the paradoxical infinity of relations between two- and three-dimensional
experience as a process of interpretation and variation. Refusing the totality
of the predestined serial image in favor of the infinity of the images’ move-
ments, it finds onscreen the self’s own signifying, its inner speech, as process
of desire, reaching out toward, interpreting, performing elaborate pas-de-
deuxwith the uncapturable transformations of a world that presents itself as
signifying other, not transcendental sign.
We are now in a position to summarize the findings of the first section.
PIXEL CUT VECTOR
The iteration of The objection of The production of
time space meaning
Firstness Secondness Thirdness
Sensation Perception/representation Communication
| 97 |
G
ra
ph
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
:
T
h
e
V
e
c
to
r
|
Event Object Sign
Preindividual Individual Social
Indifference (Zero) Unity/multiplicity Infinity
Real Imaginary Symbolic
Timelessness Destiny Hope
Referent Signified Signifier
One reason for beginning in the pioneer period is to isolate the ele-
mentary aspects of cinema at the moment of becoming. The task of the fol-
lowing chapters is to historicize them: to show how these raw principles
develop and interact in the ongoing dialogue between cinema and society,
to see how the virtual cinema became actual. The vector completes the ele-
ments of the moving image, but it does so by becoming human. In the nor-
mative cinemas that followed, the apparatus would take its revenge.
| 98 |
C
h
ap
te
r
4
|
| Part II |
Normative Cinema
Eisenstein: The Dictatorship of the Effect
In hours like these, one rises to address
The ages, history, and all creation.
—Vladimir Mayakovsky, April 14, 19301
Norms and the Rhetoric of Totality
A norm offers itself as a model for subsequent makers, a stable structure that
can hold good for decades, like the three-minute pop song, or longer, like
the Petrarchan sonnet. Norms legitimate particular practices and sanction
deviations. Talcott Parsons (1951) anchors normativity in the “double con-
tingency” of social intercourse, when each partner’s communication is mod-
ulated in relation to the reaction of the other, who likewise reacts to the
contingent circumstances of the first partner’s address and so on. Reviewing
this thesis, Giddens (1979: 85–88) argues that in the construction of norms
there is also a play of power. This is clear in the case of Eisenstein, and it is
documented with almost indecent clarity in an account, written by the ac-
tor Cherkasov and his brother, of a meeting he attended with Eisenstein to
hear criticisms of Ivan the Terriblefrom Stalin and his two closest associates
Molotov and Zhdanov (Eisenstein 1996: 299–304). Unvoiced menace sweats
from every interchange. There is never a doubt as to whose thoughts carry
the most weight. The double contingency of cinematic norms is indeed a
function, as Parsons argued, of relations between interlocutors. But the spe-
cific norm depends in part on who the interlocutors are—who is the in-
tended or most significant audience for the filmic model. For Eisenstein in
the late 1930s, it appears to have been a tightly defined group within the
state bureaucracy who held power over his life and, perhaps more impor-
5
TOTAL FILM: MUSIC
| |
tant, over the exercise of his craft. The realist and classical norms, as we will
see, also address themselves to specific audiences that we might describe as
the citizen and the consumer.
Put in slightly different terms, then, norms are a solution to the question
of social order: how do individuals come to work together as societies? The
presumption of an opposition between individual and society lies at the heart
of the sociological theory of normativity. That opposition governs the cham-
pioning of individuals against society in the classical norm. Renoir’s films of
the Popular Front period are an attempt to reconcile individualism and soci-
ety. The Eisenstein we will be engaging with, the Eisenstein of Alexander
Nevskyand the dialogue with Stalin, must champion the triumph of society
in the form of the state over the individual. This is a normative cinema.
From Abel Gance’s Napoleonof 1927 (King 1984), via Korda’s Things to
Come(Frayling 1995), with its grandiloquent appeal for technocracy, through
Leni Riefenstahl’s Triumph of the Will and Olympiadof 1934 and 1936 via
1950s sword and sandal epics to the militarist rock epic Top Gun,total film
is by no means the exclusive property of Stalinism. What these films share
is the attempt to deploy maximal rhetorical control over cinematic effects,
removing the extraneous and filling the aural and visual wavebands of the
film with a single theme, so minimizing the possibility of the audience cre-
ating its own meanings, becoming distracted, or missing the point of the
film. The term is chosen not only to implicate this norm with totalitar-
ianism, but to recall Levinas’s definition of totality from chapter 4 (“a re-
duction of all experience, of all that is reasonable, to a totality wherein
consciousness embraces the world, leaves nothing outside of itself, and thus
becomes absolute thought” [Levinas 1985: 75]).2Total film aspires to bring
| 101 |
To
ta
l
F
ilm
: M
u
s
ic
|
to the audience a diegesis that can be understood, mentally appropriated,
totally. By making the world a theme, it calls the audience to possess it as a
whole, and to identify their thought with the world imaged on screen rather
than with individual figures, though often enough a protagonist, Christ or
Tom Cruise, will provide the rhetorical gateway through which absolute
possession can be depicted.
Alexander Nevsky(see figs. 5.1–5.4) is widely held to be “the very worst
film in Eisenstein’s oeuvre” (Aumont 1987: 18). Working under Stalin after
the destruction of his previous film,Bezhin Meadow(Barna 1973: 192–199;
Seton 1960: 367–391), Eisenstein was under constant threat of imprison-
ment. For several years he was not allowed to direct, and for some time he
was even debarred from teaching at the Film School. When finally, in 1937,
he was assigned Nevsky, a project not of his own choosing, he had to work
with a codirector, D.I. Vassiliev, whose job was to ensure compliance with
the ideological, political, and aesthetic demands of the regime (on other
constraints, see Eisenstein 1983: 65, 226; 1970: 42; Barna 1973: 213–216;
Leyda 1973: 349). The film is significant for us for three reasons. First, it
isnot an “Eisenstein” film, product of genius, but a film by a master crafts-
man shot under the discipline of Soviet realism and subordinated to the
propaganda aims of Stalin’s state bureaucracy. Precisely because it is so com-
prised by its production under conditions of systemic duress, Nevskyserves
as the best-known and most accessible example of Stalinist cinema. Second,
Nevsky,Eisenstein’s first sound film, was the culmination of a decade’s think-
ing about the relation between sound and image. And third, despite the con-
ditions under which he was working, Eisenstein arranged the filming not
only according to a strict plan of action but with the determined vision of
what the film should achieve, and the stylistic means through which it would
evoke precise and predetermined emotions and meanings in its audience.
Like Hitchcock, Eisenstein believed in the almost mechanical manipulation
of the audience (and actors: see Leyda 1973: 350); in this film, he reaches to-
ward the apogee of rhetorical filmmaking.
The word “rhetoric” has come to have a confusing set of meanings, not
least because the Romantic movement of the late eighteenth and early nine-
teenth centuries saw the older rhetoric as an irrelevant straitjacket binding
the free creativity of the solitary genius. In ancient times, rhetoric was the
art of persuasion and was taught in five aspects: inventioor subject matter;
dispositioor structural arrangement of the major parts of an argument; elocu-
| 102 |
C
h
ap
te
r
5
|
tio, the choice and ordering of words; pronunciatoor the actual speaking of
the discourse; and memoria, the art of memory. According to Ducrot and
Todorov (1972: 100), over the ensuing centuries, the discipline of rhetoric
was reduced to elocutio alone: the rule-governed teaching of style, more
properly called “stylistics.”
Nevskyis indeed a work of stylistics, the bene dicendi scientiaor science of
speaking well, but it is also a rhetorical film in the ancient sense. Eisenstein
has his own vocabulary for the parts of rhetoric: in particular, elocutiobe-
comes depiction, while the theme or “image” stands in the place of inventio.
By contrast, realism embraced depiction as its central interest, whereas
classicism, as the name suggests, focused on the structuring principle of dis-
positio and its relationship with pronunciato, the address to the audience.
Eisenstein, however, holds the ancient belief that of all the parts, it is the
theme, the image, that governs every aspect of the discourse. His goal is
topersuade.
| 103 |
To
ta
l
F
ilm
: M
u
s
ic
|
| Figure 5.1 |
Alexander Nevsky:The hero, the nation, the land: Cherkasov, member of the Supreme Soviet,
as Stalin as Russia—not depiction but image. Courtesy BFI Collections.
| 104 |
C
h
ap
te
r
5
|
| Figure 5.2 |
Alexander Nevsky:Eisenstein’s drawings for the Pskov set: folkloric art as cartoon. Courtesy BFI Collections.
The ancient Stoics distinguished between rhetoric and dialectic: the
latter the fount of wisdom and knowledge, the former mere verbal dexter-
ity. Of all people, it was the African theologian Saint Augustine who coun-
tered that “dialectic could be treated as the ground of rhetoric, hence as
notmerely verbal, but in the realm of things, the realm of the universal or-
der” (Burke 1950: 60). The fifth-century Christian provides the twentieth-
century Marxist with the articulation of rhetorical form with the dialectic of
nature that underpins his filmmaking. In what follows, it is as well to recall
that the art of persuasion is not identical with the science of propaganda.
Moreover, when we are tempted to believe that persuasion is a task unwor-
thy of film, remember that Nevskywas made on the eve of a war that would
cost fourteen million Russian lives.
The Golden Section
Eisenstein was not the only one among many prominent directors to regret
the lost universality of silent cinema—René Clair (1972: 126–131; 1985)
and Charlie Chaplin (1964: 321–323) were among those who struggled with
synch sound aesthetics. Like them, Eisenstein was particularly distressed at
the way synchronized sound cinema was reduced to the less ambitious “talk-
ing picture,” with its presumption that dialogue would play the leading role.
Their fear was partly that the scale of investment required to wire hundreds
of thousands of cinemas worldwide, coincident with global economic de-
pression, would cause studios to go for the safest and most standardized
forms of entertainment. To some extent, the success of films like The Blue
Angel and Clair’s own Le Millionin 1931 assuaged their concern: creative
work was still possible, and critical and popular success could be reconciled
in the talking picture.
Earlier, however, just as news of the talkies arrived in Russia in 1928,
Eisenstein cosigned a manifesto deploring the illustrative use of dialogue
and sound effects and arguing for a “contrapuntal” use of sound as a mon-
tage element. Eisenstein would abandon the contrapuntal analogy (though
not the metaphor of the orchestral score) by the time he made his own sound
films, almost a decade later. Yet the manifesto includes an important state-
ment on the principle of montage as it stood under threat from synchronized
recorded sound: “To use sound in this way will destroy the culture of mon-
tage, for every ADHESION of sound to a visual montage piece increases its
| 105 |
To
ta
l
F
ilm
: M
u
s
ic
|
inertia as a montage piece, and increases the independence of its meaning”
(Eisenstein, Pudovkin, and Alexandrov 1949).
The montage principle as it was being voiced in the 1920s was based on
the dialectical model of clashes between shots. The authors believed this dy-
namic model of montage to be at risk for two reasons. First, synchroniza-
tion would anchor each shot so strongly to its role of depicting the world
that it would no longer be available for the dynamic interplay required of
montage pieces. And second, the shots would thus acquire their indepen-
dence from the overarching theme of the film expressed in the montage. It
was a criticism already voiced in a response to Béla Balasz’s argument that
“the cameraman is the alpha and omega of film” (Eisenstein 1988: 77).
There Eisenstein links the praise of the individual shot with the individual
hero and the individualist narrative. For Eisenstein, the isolated shot was
merely figurative. Balasz’s belief in it was a result of his failure to recognize
“the externality of the shot” (ibid.: 79) as an object in its own right, one that
acquires meaning not by resemblance or by inner beauty but by its associa-
tion with the other shots in the sequence and the whole film.
The resolution Eisenstein proposed in an essay written shortly after the
manifesto was to develop “a new sense: the ability to reduce visual and sound per-
ceptions to a ‘common denominator.’”His example comes from kabuki theater:
“the unique combination of the hand movementof Itsikawa Ensio as he slits
his throat in the act of hara-kiri with the sobbing soundoff-stage that graphi-
callycorresponds to the movement of the knife” (Eisenstein 1988: 119).
Here, in 1928, Eisenstein already proposes the “new sense” of cinema as
fundamentally graphic: gesture and sound share a common trajectory, a
shared vector. Critical to an understanding of Eisensteinian montage in
general, Eisenstein’s particular understanding of the vector in the later 1930s
is even more important to the concept of total film.
Writing shortly after the completion of Nevsky,Eisenstein offered a di-
agrammatic rendition of the concept of organic unity. The organicism of the
Romantics was based either on vague concepts of what ought to be the case,
or on a mystical faith in the morphological similarity between parts and
wholes in the living world (e.g., between the shapes of pine cones and pine
trees). For the generation that came to creative maturity in the wake of the
1917 Revolution in Russia, science provided the model for experiment in
art. Unsurprisingly, then, Eisenstein finds his type of organic development
at the conjunction of life sciences and mathematics in the logarithmic spi-
| 106 |
C
h
ap
te
r
5
|
ral. This spiral occurs in nature in shells, in the pattern of sunflower seed-
heads, in the growth of animals’ horns and the structure of spiral galaxies,
the geometrical expression of growth. Eisenstein derives the maths of his
spiral from the golden section, promoted since antiquity as the most elegant
of proportions. For Eisenstein, the coincidence of classical proportion with
the mathematics of growth combines “the golden section as the most per-
fect mathematical image of the unity of the whole and its parts and the log-
arithmic spiral as the most perfect image of the expression of the principle
of proportional evolution in general” (Eisenstein 1987: 18).3
His example is the outward spiral of Battleship Potemkin,starting from a
minor dispute about maggots, expanding to execution, mutiny, and the at-
tack on the Odessa Steps, and culminating in the meeting with the Imperial
Navy squadron. Reading this as the five-act structure of classical tragedy,
Eisenstein goes on to analyze the rhythm and duration of the second act,
seeing a caesura that serves as a pivot about which the viewpoint or emo-
tional content of the drama reverses, each caesura arriving at approximately
the appropriate mathematical moment specified by the golden section. In
his brief foray into mathematical aesthetics, we might be tempted to argue,
Eisenstein foreshadowed the most advanced form of vector graphics. His
failure can also be described mathematically. Where the rate of growth of
the spiral is nil, the result is a circle. Under conditions of Stalinism, and per-
haps also because Nevskydefers to the urgent demands of its historical mo-
ment, Eisenstein’s spiral seems to have been destined to chase its own tail.
The well-tempered scale of diatonic music, the Western classical scale,
is one of the most familiar artistic phenomena describable in terms of the
natural logarithm, the organicist principle of the harmony of the parts in the
whole. For Eisenstein, the same principle extends to a specific definition:
“rhythm has always been the ultimate means of generalising about a theme,
as being the very image of the internal dynamics of its content” (Eisenstein
1991: 235–236). Rhythm is a vector extending from the infinitesimal mi-
crostructure of shots to the infinite macrostructure of cinema. This over-
arching rhythmic structure, like the uneven stabilities of the golden section,
thrums at every level of the film. It does so as the theme or image, a term
Eisenstein’s translators use to distinguish the thematic structure of the film
from its depictionof external reality. That image is not just the ideological or
semantic content, but its highest generalization as pattern.
| 107 |
To
ta
l
F
ilm
: M
u
s
ic
|
There is also an implicit distinction here between two types of organic
unity, the Romantic ideal of “any work in general that possesses wholeness
and an inner law” (Eisenstein 1987: 11) and Eisenstein’s own in which partic-
ulars as well as generalities are structured by a single law. Romantic formal-
ism required merely an order; Eisenstein’s rhythmic unity was specifically
suited to realism because “the forms of its compositional embodiment also
fully reflect the laws peculiar to reality” (ibid.: 12). In claiming the natural
logarithm as the basis of pattern, he could isolate a formal structure that
shapes not only the film and its depicted reality but also the film’s audience,
“because the law of its structuring is also the law governing those who per-
ceive the work, for they too are part of organic nature” (ibid.).
One immediate effect of this common vector shaping reality, film, and
audience is that Eisenstein can refer to “music in its broadest sense—in-
cluding words, voice and sound in general” (Eisenstein 1991: 239). All dis-
tinctions between wordless and speaking voices, the sounds of the body, of
the socialized human, of the random and uncontrollable noises of land-
scapes and cities—in short all conflict in the film’s auditory dimension is
thus condensed into music as the auditory aspect of the image. In his earli-
est writings on sound, Eisenstein had feared the isolation of the shot from
the montage. By making all sound music, all music rhythm, and rhythm and
montage a single image, Eisenstein gains control. It is an operation com-
mon to the musical avant-garde, from the Futurists to John Cage. Kahn
identifies a moment in the history of musical modernism when “the sounds
of the world were to be themselves categorized, explicitly or implicitly, into
referential sounds and areferential noises, such that a noise could be incor-
porated into the areferential operations of music.” As a result, “these noisy
correspondences within music were emphasized as themselves bearing
traces of the world of true extramusicality” (Kahn 1999: 69). This avant-
garde assimilation of the noise of the world subordinates extramusical ref-
erence to the formative work of music.
By contrast, Eisenstein’s contemporary Dziga Vertov wrote in 1925, “If,
with respect to vision, our kinok-observers have recorded visible life phe-
nomena with cameras, we must now talk about recording audible facts”
(Vertov 1984: 56). Dismissing the claim that the world was not “audio-
genic,” and that therefore filmmakers and radio producers should con-
centrate on recording sounds in soundproofed studios, Vertov demanded
location sound, creating complex audio tracks for his first sound film En-
| 108 |
C
h
ap
te
r
5
|
thusiasm(Fischer 1985). At the same time, he took exception to the “State-
ment” on sound that Eisenstein had coauthored in 1928, and especially with
the contrapuntal, asynchronous aesthetic proposed there: “neither synchro-
nizationnor asynchronization of the visible with the audible is at all oblig-
atory” (Vertov 1984: 111); indeed, workers speaking with their own voices
intheir own audio environments were integral to his documentary concept
of film.
For Eisenstein, however, Vertov’s “factographic” documentarism was a
form of naturalism restricted to the level of depiction: “Their mistake was
to be so busy propagating fact that they forgot that in this period a fact was
at the same time an image.A revolving wheel was not only a fact, it was at the
same time an image, a figurative representation of our country” (Eisenstein
1996: 19). Vertov’s direct sound recording thus stands accused of a lack of
motivation in the formal sense of the word: it stands apart from the grand
design of the image and so falls prey to formlessness. Direct sound was de-
pendent on a relation to the ungovernable productivity of the world, and as
such it could not be guided into the rhetorical unity of the film as image.
Underneath these accusations lies Eisenstein’s fear of an artform that would
not be governed.
In music, as opposed to sound, Eisenstein found the model of a time-
based art that gathered the power of every microtonal vibration in the or-
chestra into the totality of composition. The lilt of a spoken phrase, the
clatter of hooves, a distant cry could all be brought together in a single har-
monious movement of the score, “For it is precisely tone which decisively
adds the ultimate image, interpretation and generalized meaning to what is
a collection of separate words joined into a sentence” (Eisenstein 1991:
244). The normative drive of Eisenstein’s theory parts company with the
digital theory of the vector: interpretation and meaning are derived from
and controlled by the organization of the diegetic world as montage image.
In the pages immediately preceding this appropriation of tone of voice to
musicality, Eisenstein has made a schematic table of levels of generality. In
the single shot, the general image is provided by the graphic shape ab-
stractable from the frame. In silent montage, generalization “was expressed
by the moving line along which the montage sequences are combined,”
whereas in sound film generalization “is expressed beyond the bounds of the
montage combination of sequences and into the moving line of musicwhich
runs through them” (ibid.: 243). This in turn permits Eisenstein to rethink
| 109 |
To
ta
l
F
ilm
: M
u
s
ic
|
his concept of contrapuntal relations between image and sound under the
rubric of total film:
the movement of counterpoint within a piece of music also corresponds exactly
to the phenomenon whereby the visible materialoutline of the picture in a film-
shot evolves into the mental “path between sequences,” the process that occurs
when cinema moves on from the single set-up stage to multiple set-up.... The
juxtaposition of a number of melodic sequences also gives rise to a certain gen-
eralizing “line” that is not conveyed materially but which emerges, the line of
harmony. (Ibid.: 246)
This harmony is a central tenet of the essay on rhythm and of the pro-
duction of Alexander Nevsky.In earlier theoretical writings on montage, Ei-
senstein proposed the cut as the controlling device that would establish
thegraphic compositional qualities of the individual shot and build those
compositions into a structured whole through editing. But in the writings
of the 1930s and early ’40s, the vector takes the dominant role as the high-
est and most abstract form of generality, and its model is no longer dialec-
tical or even dissonant but harmonious, contrapuntal, and melodious. Ten
years after the Revolution, it had been possible to imagine a new sound art;
twenty years after it, the academic music of the previous century was mod-
eling the whole of cinema.
Electing even this dated form of music as the principle of sound-film
montage brings certain risks. Because the soundtrack has its own “technical
vehicle,” and because it is easier to grasp musical themes than the mental im-
age produced by the visual montage, “the danger is all the greater of the
soundtrack becoming ‘self-sufficient’ and not organically integrated with
the picture” (Eisenstein 1991: 252). In the silent film montage, contra Ver-
tov, “the montage combination of a series of segments is notinterpreted by
the mind as a certain sequence of details,but as a certain sequence of whole
scenes—and scenes, moreover, which are not depicted but arise within the
mind in image form” (ibid.: 128). Lurking just below the surface is a distrust
of the documentary’s claim to reveal reality. Five years earlier, in a note on
Méliès, he calls on the camera to “penetrate” reality, “so that we move from
the routine monitoring of an illusory, composed reality to an authentic
unity of images joined in juxtaposition in order to reveal their sense” (Eisen-
stein 1988: 260). Retailing their own lives back to people is both routine and
| 110 |
C
h
ap
te
r
5
|
suspect; only the image is powerful enough to penetrate the veils of appear-
ance to show the unphotographable: class struggle, revolution, Russia. Just
as the succession of still frames produces the impression of movement with-
out consciousness of the content of each frame, so the juxtaposition of shots
gives rise to a pre- or subconsciously formed intellectual image.
For Vertov, the machine was the model of the new humanity: efficient,
scientific, objective, and socialized. Eisenstein anthropomorphizes the ma-
chine rather than mechanizing the proletariat. Where Vertov seeks union
with the mechanical, Eisenstein shuns it and deploys his fears not only in
Nevskybut across his works. Discussing a dark, suicidal period in his auto-
biography, Eisenstein begins a discussion of fate, described in terms of “an
impersonal, soulless machine, the precursor of Guderian’s herds of tanks,
the rush of the iron ‘swine’ of Teutonic knights in Nevsky./ Again faceless.
This time physically enclosed by helmets, whose eyeslits echo the slits in the
future Tigers and Panthers” (Eisenstein 1983: 197; the oblique stroke de-
notes one of Eisenstein’s frequent paragraph breaks.). These foreshadows of
the German tank divisions at the siege of Leningrad are also motivated by a
memory of the rail yards at Smolensk at the height of the Civil War.” The
most frightening thing in my life,” he writes, was the trains:
Their implacable, blind, pitiless movement has migrated to my films, now
dressed in soldiers’ boots on the Odessa steps, now directing their blunt snouts
into knights’ helmets in the “Battle on the Ice,” now in black vestments sliding
over the stone slabs of the cathedral, in the wake of a candle shaking in the hands
of the stumbling Vladimir Staritsky.
This image of a night train has wandered from film to film, becoming a
symbol of fate. (Ibid.: 198)
Gorky’s maxim that opens Non-Indifferent Nature,the claim that “man”
is the core of his art, is neither a submission to Stalinist rhetoric, nor an evo-
cation of a bland humanism, but a decision to side with the human against
the mechanical in that cyborg dialectic that defines the cinematic apparatus.
This siding with the human is not restricted to Eisenstein’s representa-
tional and stylistic strategies, however: it pervades the aesthetic of the total
film. Eisenstein mistakes totality for infinity and so reorients the vector as
the rhetorical principle of a monodirectional transmission of belief and
affect from producer to audience. Eisenstein struggles to maintain unity as
| 111 |
To
ta
l
F
ilm
: M
u
s
ic
|
dynamic and to harmonize into completion the dialectical uncertainty of
the vector. In the norm thus constructed, the integration of human and
machine is adapted to a static and harmonious intertwining of object-world
and subjectivity into a whole. The totality of total cinema is then achieved
through a detournement of the vector from the openness of mutual evolu-
tion toward a model in which the present is the already achieved conclusion
of that history. As in the union of pilot and plane in Top Gun,of Skywalker
and X-wing fighter in Star Wars,the present is mythologized as the eternal,
and the cyborg dialectic tamed as the always already achieved union of world
and spirit in an eternal truth, which George Lukas had the sociological in-
sight to call The Force. Eisenstein’s nightmare in Smolensk has given rise to
a cinema of truth, where truth has the overwhelming power of a rhetorical
statement of what we are presumed to know already. Total cinema places it-
self at the end of history. If nonetheless Nevsky remains a film that can be
watched and studied, it is because, in the last instance, the machinery of fate
that so oppresses it is identical with the cinematic machinery of resistance.
| 112 |
C
h
ap
te
r
5
|
| Figure 5.3 |
Alexander Nevsky:Teutonic knights foreshadow the Panzer tanks at Leningrad. Courtesy BFI Collections.
| 113 |
| Figure 5.4 |
Alexander Nevsky:The Battle on the Ice: turning the summer sky to winter. Courtesy BFI Collections.
| 114 |
C
h
ap
te
r
5
|
Yet, in the words of the Borg, resistance is futile: resistance demands a dom-
inant to resist, and domination defines itself as that which dominates all re-
sistance. The triumph of any side is always the triumph of Victory, always
the renewal of totality.
Eisenstein’s challenge in the years after the 1928 “Statement” is no
longer to invent a dialectical form of cinema in which sound and image
would, through their conflicts, produce an art form of an entirely new kind.
Instead, total cinema must face the necessity of their coexistence and act as
if with the knowledge that their struggle has already been resolved. At this
stage, totality has been achieved by nominating music as the pinnacle of the
sonorous hierarchy and the graphic, compositional line as the governor of
the visual, thus finding in the analogy between the moving lines of melody
and of graphical cinema the core of a newly harmonious and whole film-
making practice.
Composition
In the years following the production of Nevsky, Eisenstein would add a
new element to the mix: “Solving the problem of audiovisual montage is solving
the problem of. . . colour in cinema.In other words only colour cinematog-
raphy... is capable of fully solving the problem of genuine audiovisual syn-
chronicity and consequently of montage in sound film” (Eisenstein 1991:
253). This startling assertion resurfaces in Eisenstein’s memoirs, where he
explains that “The higher forms of organic affinity of the melodic pattern of
music and of tonal construction of the system of succeeding color shots are
possible only with the coming of color to cinema” (Eisenstein 1983: 257).
The gradations of color, even more than those of the grayscale in black and
white film, could be recruited for a cinematic art that would be capable of
totality. This faith in color as the resolution of the sound-image dialectic
takes its strength and meaning from a long series of contemplations on the
relations between sound and image. Its central innovation, however, is less
the sense of color as such, and more the move from the line as the central
metaphor of composition, both visual and musical, toward tonal gradation.
In “The Fourth Dimension in Cinema” Eisenstein distinguishes be-
tween montage by dominants, governed by the major element of a shot, and
overtonal montage, which draws in the reverberations and connotations of
the frame. The shift, he says there, is necessitated by “the non-dialectical
postulation of the question of the unambiguity of the shot in itself. / The
shot never becomes a letter but always remains an ambiguous hieroglyph”
(Eisenstein 1988: 182). Since any one shot, say, of a field of snow, might sug-
gest winter, or whiteness, or purity, and even a combination of shots cannot
definitively tell the audience to think “old age” or “cold,” the images remain
as ambiguous as Egyptian picture-writing, unless and until they make the
move from denotation to cognition, from Peircean secondness to thirdness.
What is required is, first, an understanding of the overtones of the shot.
Eisenstein is careful to assert that the overtones are not “impressionistic”
emotional hues, but strictly measurable, as brightness and gloom can be
measured by a light meter. Another example: “where we designate a shot as
a ‘sharp sound,’ it is extremely easy to apply this designation to the over-
whelming number of acutely angled elements in the shot that prevail over
the rounded elements (a case of ‘graphic tonality’)” (ibid.: 189). The second
requirement is that these overtones are deployed in the composition to max-
imize effect, as a musician would use the overtonal frequencies of bells or
organ pipes in the overall sound of a composition.
At this stage, Eisenstein adds another schema, of five levels of montage.
The first four are the “primitive motor effect,” the kind of rhythm an audi-
ence responds to physically; the rhythmic, more subtle than the first cate-
gory because less capable of being acted out physically; the tonal (or
“melodic emotional”); and the overtonal. Throughout this schema, despite
citations of graphical and temporal qualities specific to the visual arts and to
cinema itself, the language is musical and makes a point of insisting that the
vibrations that make up sound are the basic units of both rhythm and tones.
The fifth category, the “fourth dimension,” however, is quite different: “In-
tellectual montage is montage not of primitively physiological overtonal
resonances but of the resonances of overtones in an intellectual order, / i.e.
the conflicting combinations of accompanying intellectual effects with one
another” (Eisenstein 1988: 193). One feels the director struggling for an ex-
planation that will permit him to continue his experiments. But not even
quotations from Lenin can alter the tendency of the thought: the dialectical
is less and less a matter of struggle and conflict, more and more a synthesis
of the classless and therefore conflict-free victory of the proletariat in Stal-
inist Russia. The theory of overtonal montage is an attempt to integrate the
paradigmatic axis of cinema—the semantic reverberations of images that
| 115 |
To
ta
l
F
ilm
: M
u
s
ic
|
might lead to stray thoughts of winter, old age, or innocence—into a
planned and administered thematization. In effect, it represents the attempt
to treat the paradigmatic axis of the vector as though it could function
syntagmatically.
At the same time, there remain elements of a dialectical conception.
The future, he says in a lecture given at the Sorbonne in February 1930, be-
longs to the sound film, “Particularly Mickey Mouse films. The interesting
thing about these films is that sound is not used as a naturalistic element./
They look for the sound equivalent of a gesture or a plastic scene, i.e. not
the sound that accompanies it in reality but the equivalent of this optical fact
in the acoustic domain” (Eisenstein 1988: 200). For Eisenstein, the power
of the cartoon soundtrack is that it has no need to resemble or anchor the
animated gesture in reality. Synchronization he had feared as overly depic-
tive: here he could hope for a dialectic between sound and image. Instead,
Eisenstein’s reading of Mickey Mouse brings both gesture and sound into a
single organic image, a common vector, which has the additional benefit of
being free from pernicious documentarism with its risk of autonomous
shots and unruly connotations. Where, in chapter 4, we read in the vector
of Cohl’s graphical cinema the recognition of the other as the precondition
of the social and desiring subject, Eisenstein’s refusal of a “routine monitor-
ing” allied with his delight in the total artificiality of Disney leads us toward
a cinema not of socialization and desire but of totalization and control. The
perversion of the vector in total cinema turns it into the Symbolic gover-
nance of the subject by the desire of the other, a product not at all of Eisen-
stein’s putative homosexuality, but of the mechanism of repression. Total
cinema reverses the emancipation of interpersonal desire as the grounds of
futurity.
The move from line to gradation corresponds to a newly static concep-
tion of the vector: “In cinema the movement is not actual but isan image
of movement” (Eisenstein 1991: 145). So, although movement is the Ur-
phänomen of film (ibid.: 273), it is at the same time only an induced state of
mind, that is, an image in Eisenstein’s technical sense of the word. The pixel
itself is reduced to stasis, excluded because it is not actual from the realm of
the image: “The undefinedimageless stages between two reasonable combi-
nations are not ‘read’ and only exist as though non-existent in the mind of
the perceiver” (ibid.: 192). If actual movement in the world is a matter of an
infinite number of infinitesimal increments, the process of filming renders
| 116 |
C
h
ap
te
r
5
|
only those parts (the initial and final states, the keyframes) that can be read
as image. This is one element of Eisenstein’s sense of the frame cutting a
slice out of reality: the formlessness of pure movement is eliminated by an
initiating cut (“Perception is intermittent but here it is the role of the obtu-
rator or interrupter to remove from our perception the non-significant ele-
ments of the progression or movement from phase to phase” [ibid.]). The
realization of cinematic movement is the reassembling of the transition thus
edited into an intellectual image of movement trimmed of its distracting
actuality.
Nor is this transition itself a dialectical one, at least at this stage of play.
In “Montage 1937” Eisenstein writes of the movement between particular
and general “the only tension of contradiction that remains is in the area
ofinteraction between different dimensions in which the same thought is
expressed” (Eisenstein 1991: 52). Here vectoral possibility mutates into a
stable cinematic form, and especially toward a physically, emotionally, and
intellectually unambiguous meaning that can be both signified and under-
stood straightforwardly. An even clearer reading of dialectics as an element
of harmony occurs in the “Laocoon” essay concerning the exclusion of the
Bergsonian, infinitesimal movement: “In film, the chromatic nature of this
modulation of one phase into another undergoes what is no more than tem-
pering (like a sound that is fixed, unalterably, by the keys of a piano... )”
(ibid.: 192). Mere sensation, which I have argued forms the basis of cine-
matic movement, is explicitly excluded even from the raw material of the
shot. Motion exists only as a psychic image for Eisenstein, and the dialecti-
cal cut of his earlier montage is subordinate to that core ideal.
It is on this premise that it is possible for Eisenstein to propose the sub-
ordination of depth to the graphical composition of the work. Since there is
no primary sensation (because the world has already been cut into form by
the mere fact of recording on film), every depiction lends itself to vector-
ization. But the vector has itself been reduced to a horizontal movement of
the eye, a movement that can be “trained” in a specific sequence to follow a
particular direction, “as though in a series along the horizontal,” a process that
allows the montage director “to line up shot to shot on the horizontal and to
structure the progression of the music in parallel with them” (Eisenstein
1991: 389). Eisenstein’s italics leave little doubt. The deep staging of the se-
quence from Nevskyhe analyzes exists only to train the viewer’s eye into
lateral movement. There is only field, but not depth; or rather depth is
| 117 |
To
ta
l
F
ilm
: M
u
s
ic
|
rendered as a vector, not, as in Bazin and the mise-en-scène tradition, as die-
gesis. Deprived of the motivating force of sensation, there can arise a kind
of hybridization of cut and vector, perception and signification, into a total-
ity, “including the ‘total,’ polyphonic, reciprocal ‘sensory’ resonance of the
sequence (musical and pictorial) as wholes. This totality is the sensory fac-
tor which most immediately synthesises the principle image of the se-
quence.... With this the circle, as it were, is completed” (ibid.: 336).
The language of synthesis, tempered chords, total resonance, linear
progression, and accumulation does produce the image, in Eisenstein’s spe-
cific sense, of the unified stability and symmetry of an enclosed circle, rather
than the open line of the vector we celebrated in Cohl’s Fantasmagorie.But
this had not always been the case. In Immoral Memorieswe find Eisenstein
citing “the wise saying of Wang Pi, of the 3rd century B.C.:‘What is a line?
A line speaks of movement’” and, eulogizing the unshaded line drawing,
adding “My constant passion remains the dynamics of lines and dynamics of
moving on and not staying put,” citing his “inclination and sympathy for
teachings that proclaim dynamics, movement and becoming as their basic
principles” (Eisenstein 1983: 42). But the concluding pages of the same
book emphasize a different aspect of the vector. Speaking in the character
of “a detached researcher” he says of himself that his single theme through-
out all his work has been “the ultimate idea of the achievement of unity.”
This contradiction between the dynamic and the unified is critical to an un-
derstanding of the rhetorical effect in Alexander Nevsky.
Nevskyis the most achieved expression in Eisenstein’s oeuvre of this
stabilized image. The film begins with an exordium,a general statement de-
signed to bring the audience onto the side of the orator: here the initial state-
ment of a Russia in ruin, besieged by the Tartar Khans. The second stage of
the formal construction of an argument is the statement of one’s own posi-
tion: this is the function of Alexander’s speech withholding violence against
the Khans until the Russian forces are ready for the task. Third, the nature
of the case is argued, introducing the opponents’ point of view: a function
carried out in the debates over whether to fight the Teutonic Knights. The
body of the argument follows, with a full unfolding of the case occupying
the central section of the film and culminating in a rebuttal of the opposing
argument (the Battle on the Ice sequence occupying almost a third of the to-
tal running time). The final peroration is composed traditionally of vitu-
| 118 |
C
h
ap
te
r
5
|
peration of the adversary (the prisoners, especially the traitor Tverdilo) and
an expanded celebration of one’s own point of view, carried out in the jubi-
lation and closing speech to camera. The five acts are not so much a the-
atrical borrowing as a structured argument.
Aristotle identified three modes of rhetoric. Deliberative arguments are
aimed at the future and are proper to public debate on policy; forensic ar-
guments set out to judge the past and belong to the law courts. Eisenstein’s
rhetoric addresses the present and is specifically epideictic. One of Aristotle’s
examples is precisely the task of Nevsky: the praise of one’s country and
countrymen (“My subject is patriotism”: Eisenstein 1996: 117). This pane-
gyric mode of rhetoric addresses the present, not least because the epi-
deicticconcerns itself with moving the audience, with heightening their
commitment to issues of which, often enough, they can already be assumed
to be persuaded. As Burke observes,
Perhaps the sturdiest modern variant of epideictic rhetoric is in “human inter-
est” stories depicting the sacrificial life of war heroes in war time, or Soviet
works (including propaganda motion pictures) that celebrate the accomplish-
ments of individuals and groups who triumph over adversity in carrying out the
government’s plans for exploiting the nation’s resources. For Cicero says that
epideictic (panegyric, laudatio) should deal especially in those virtues thought
beneficial “not so much to their possessors as to mankind in general.” (Burke
1950: 70–71)
Burke goes on to observe that the epideictic is closely associated with
the “tempered,” restrained style of oratory, a style whose aim is to please
rather than to persuade. This, however, is the originality of Eisenstein’s
rhetorical gambit, for he chooses the grandiloquent style, once again echo-
ing Augustine for whom the grandiloquent is most appropriate when minds
are to be swayed. The heightened language, the score, the accelerando and
rallentando pace of cutting and the use of multiple angles to create a sculp-
tural effect in the depiction of protagonists, and the graphical compositions
(mise-en-cadre), especially the frontality of many shots, are throughout ac-
cumulated in the interests of a grand style, a sweeping argument, a flam-
boyant call for selfless action. In some of his earliest writings Eisenstein had
already decried narrative along with the star system and the individualist
| 119 |
To
ta
l
F
ilm
: M
u
s
ic
|
ethos of Hollywood. We should not be surprised that a director who once
dreamed of making a film of Marx’s Capitalshould produce a film that takes
the form of a well-formed thesis rather than a well-made play.
The fine detail of the film also reveals a voice sufficiently powerful to
translate the thirteenth century into the twentieth: “Thus the hoof-beats of
the Teuton knights in Alexander Nevskydo not merely ‘hammer for the sake
of hammering,’ but out of this ‘hammer for hammer’ and ‘gallop for gallop’
there is evolved a universal image, galloping across the thirteenth century to
the twentieth—toward the unmasking of fascism” (Seton 1960: 382; this
passage does not appear in the retranslated version of the article, Eisenstein
1970: 149–167). Two large-scale structures help provide this allegorization
of the film’s themes: first its score, which, despite the evocative use of an-
cient instruments and use of themes from folk traditions, is concentrated on
the resources of the modern orchestra; and second the deliberately artificial
mise-en-scène in Eisenstein’s first entirely studio-based film, with its folk-
loric reconstruction of Novgorod and Pskov and cartoonlike figures from
popular ballads like Vaska and Gavrilo. Both factors add to the present tense
of the film’s address. And both add to the graphical nature of the film a fla-
vor as schematic as slapstick, for example, in the drowning gurgle of the
trombone playing the Knights’ theme as they sink below the ice, or the
mickey mouse percussion as Vaska bashes in the eyebrowed helmet of a Teu-
tonic Knight, for all the world like a Laurel and Hardy bowler hat gag.
Bazelon notes a further example: “As the Russian people’s army routs the
German invaders in Alexander Nevsky,Prokofiev gives his folk theme a Mack
Sennett-Keystone Kop treatment, perfectly mirroring the silent-film movie-
music chase accompaniments” (Bazelon 1975: 145). Yet though it is tempt-
ing to read these as borrowings from Hollywood, it is rather the case that
Eisenstein and slapstick both borrow from an older and common source.
As David Bordwell notes, “In both narrative and style, Nevskystrives
forthe bare, grand outlines of pageantry or legend” (Bordwell 1993: 211).
This spartan clarity of inventio, of image, derives in part from the folk tra-
ditions the Russian avant-garde (Kandinsky, Chagall, Mousorgsky, Rimsky-
Korsakov) had been learning from since before the Revolution. These
simplified forms lend themselves especially well to repetition and the
forms of delay Eisenstein had urged on his students (Nizhny 1962: 93–139).
Delaying tropes in Alexander Nevskyinclude digression and its neatly turned
| 120 |
C
h
ap
te
r
5
|
return to the main theme, as occurs in the romantic subplot and the use of
silent pauses. Repetitive tropes include asyndeton, a listing without the use
of conjunctions, in fact a highly typical trope of montage in general; distri-
bution, or dividing a theme into components that can be addressed sepa-
rately, a technique employed both by Alexander (first the Teutons, then the
Tartars) and in the separation of the Grand Master, the black monk and the
white Bishop at the conclusion of the battle; and antithesis, constantly used
in the graphical oppositions between shots.
Central to the aesthetic of Nevskyis the rhetorical device of exemplifi-
cation, almost every character and action typifying the patriotic theme or its
antithesis. Of particular interest is the technique called gradation, which
provides for a mounting triad of terms from small to large. This structure of
threes is an often-observed feature of Eisenstein’s framing, but it also ap-
pears musically, for example, in the reprised cello theme in the final scene
played first for the entry of the prisoners, reprised for the arrival of the trai-
tor in harness, and returning a third time for judgment, itself a triple gesture
of gradation—freeing the footsoldiers, ransoming the knights, delivering
the traitor to the people he betrayed. Bordwell quotes Tissé, Eisenstein’s
cameraman, on another example: the advancing knights are shown in long
shot in slow motion, at standard speed in the middle ground, “and their
foreground attacks at rates as slow as 14 frames per second” (Bordwell 1993:
221). This triadic gradation, a species of the wider rhetorical family of
tropes called amplification, formalizes Eisenstein’s association of growth
with the mechanics of ecstasy in Non-Indifferent Nature(1987).
According to Eisenstein’s own analysis of a scene from Nevsky, “the
decisive role is played by the graphic structureof the work, which does not
somuch make useof existent or non-existent correspondences as establish
graphically those correspondences which the idea and the theme of the given
workprescribe for its structure” (Eisenstein 1991: 371). The theme or im-
age dictates a graphic structure that provides the correspondences. Any cor-
respondences that preexist the idea, that is, any correspondences that belong
either to the world or to the literary material on which the film is based, are
insignificant. Instead, the sense of a moving line, both visual and musical,
dictates what materials will be used and how. The task of combining audio
and visual depends on what is commensurable between them: “movement,
which is fundamental both to a passage of music and to the structural
| 121 |
To
ta
l
F
ilm
: M
u
s
ic
|
imperatives of a pictorial sequence” (ibid.: 374). Since Eisenstein eschewed
the sense of pure movement as formlessness, this movement is already vec-
toral, “the path of movement” (ibid.: 377).
In the analysis in “Vertical Montage” (previously translated in The Film
Sense,Eisenstein 1942: 155–216), the rhetorical dimension of this structur-
ing path is apparent: its social nature reduced from intersubjectivity to one-
way address to the audience, a mode common to almost every major speech
in the film, where the rhetorical figure of communicatio, inviting dialogue
with the audience, is signally lacking. However, Eisenstein is also con-
cerned to clarify that the path may also be followed through tonal transi-
tions from dark to light, as he had earlier argued for color transitions as a
similar way of directing attention. “Vertical Montage” makes the case for a
vectoral composition within the frame, by analogy with the analysis of
painting that sees the viewer’s attention constructed through the gradations
of light and color to the central thematic elements. However, the frame-
by-frame analysis Eisenstein gives of the dawn sequence, waiting for the
Teutonic Knights’ attack, concentrates on a line-based, graphic abstraction
from depictions (shots) and musical score, via a schematic of the shots to a
graphical “Scheme of Movement” that emphasizes a repeating pattern of an
s-shaped sine-wave and a horizontal that he argues is common to both score
and image.
Roy Prendergast takes issue with this attempt to read the audiovisual as
vectoral: “the recognition of the metaphorical picture rhythm of shot IV
[the distant horizon with two flags] is instantaneous, while the musical
rhythm that Eisenstein claims corresponds to the picture rhythm takes 61⁄2
seconds to be perceived” (Prendergast 1992: 213), and that “the music is
speaking to the psychology of the moment (i.e. apprehension, fear) in terms
of the characters involved rather than to any abstract notion of shot devel-
opment or metaphorical ‘picture drama’” (ibid.: 214). Responding to these
criticisms, Royal S. Brown notes that musical transitions are experienced as
movements “up” and “down” in Western culture, and that Prendergast is
projecting a Hollywood psychologism onto Prokofiev’s score. He adds that
“One of the major pleasures to be had from any artistic experience lies in the
deeply experienced dialectic created between the diachronic time in which
the work of art is perceived and the synchronic time evoked by its struc-
tures” (Brown 1994: 137) and that here the very un-Hollywood discontinu-
ous editing and commentative staging of the score “keeps the viewer at a
| 122 |
C
h
ap
te
r
5
|
certain distance from the temporality of the narrative flow” (ibid.: 138). The
total film, then, is less dependent on psychological identification and there-
fore on the emotional cues provided by programmatic scoring in the Holly-
wood vein. At the same time, contra Brown, Nevskydoes address the audience
in the present tense, the better to immerse them in the total image.
The iconic winter landscape required dressing 30,000 square meters of
the studio lot with 17.5 tons of asphalt, white sand, water glass, and chalk
laid over sacking, while the trees were painted white and dotted with cotton
wool to extend the graphical effect of Tissé’s inventive camerawork (Seton
1960: 384). Like analogous landscapes in other cinemas—most of all per-
haps Monument Valley in Ford’s Westerns—this promulgates a sense of na-
tion by lifting the land out of history to plant it in myth. The original title
of the Nevskyscript, Russ,isolates the mythos of the motherland in the land
itself, and the finished film is as staunch a myth of national origin as She Wore
a Yellow Ribbon,whose landscape passages also function as moments of total
cinema.
The precise function of the temporality of the present in total cinema
belongs to this mythologizing process: the process of reading the past as
model of the present, reading there, in germinal form, the idealized image
of the nation as it exists eternalized in the present. This is why psychology
is so marginal to total cinema, which not only prefers types, but even seems
to propose a fixed set of stock figures (the spineless, the self-serving, the trai-
torous; the big-hearted buffoon, the idealistic boy, the folksy old man...)
in a predominantly male universe. In Ivan the Terrible, Eisenstein would
push this epic simplicity to its limit by providing Ivan with a psychological
conflict. In Nevsky, however, that conflict is entirely externalized. Nor is it
only the Teutonic Knights who are anonymous, in their faceless helmets; the
Russian masses too are without personalities. As they wait for battle, it is
only the trinity of types—the midshots of Vasilia, Ignat the armorer, and the
nearly anonymous Stavka who are singled out as representative. Otherwise
we have only Alexander and his two generals pointed up against their coun-
terfoils, the Grandmaster and his wretched priest and monk.
Montage, the Sublime, and the Cyborg Orator
Alexander Nevskyspirals toward the international battlecry of the film’s last
lines from the domesticity of the opening fishing scene. The film must take
its audience from the local to the universal, from home to homeland (under
| 123 |
To
ta
l
F
ilm
: M
u
s
ic
|
Stalin’s doctrine of “socialism in one country” it was impossible to go fur-
ther). The cartoonish studio-bound and graphically oriented aesthetic works
toward this ascent into totality.
One aspect of this aesthetic is caught in Bordwell’s description of a shot
from the battle sequence:
There are no cues of cast shadow, color, perspective, or haze. The space is thus
relatively shallow. We must rely on overlapping contours and familiar size to
place the knights in relative (if vague) depth against the sky. The knights rise and
fall, the foreground rider occasionally occluding his mate. But the shot is a very
unconvincing depiction of riding a horse. The men’s metronomic lungings are
implausible as a cue for the thudding and swaying of a horseback ride. And if
thisis a tracking shot following subject movement, there need to be some cues
for relative displacement of figure and background: shifting highlights, slight
changes in the knights’ positions in the frame. And some background features
that by their changing aspects suggest motion parallax. In the absence of such
cues, the shot is more easily construed as a static image of two knights rocking
to and fro against a backdrop. (Bordwell 1985: 116)
Bordwell’s observation is good, but his judgment is off. This is not a failure
to achieve Hollywood norms but a successful adoption from Russian folk
arts of an aesthetic that abstracts not only the knights from their environ-
ment but the diegesis from history.
The word “frame” has two senses in film: the cell marked out on the
filmstrip by the framelines and the rectangular edges of the image, the latter
meaning reinforced by its linkage to the frames surrounding paintings.
Eisenstein’s term for this second usage is kadr.4Aumont cites a 1929 essay in
which Eisenstein distinguishes between “the worn out method of the spatial
organization of the phenomenon before the camera” (the principle of mise-
en-scène) and “The other method, apprehension by the camera, organiza-
tion by it. A piece of reality is sliced off with the camera lens” (Aumont 1987:
37). Aumont believes this is accomplished through the cutting force of the
frame edge. I believe Eisenstein has something else in mind, suggested by the
(twice translated) word “slice.” For him the camera is not a means for seizing
and reproducing motion. Instead, he seems to consider movement as a form-
less mass hurtling through time toward the camera in all its shapelessness,
| 124 |
C
h
ap
te
r
5
|
and it is the task of the camera to slice it as one slices sausage, into synchronic
cold cuts that, far from replicating movement, bring it to absolute stillness.
The task of the montageur is, then, to apply formal techniques to these slices
to create a psychic rather than a mimetic mode of motion.
In a powerful critique of Nevskyin the pages of his Theory of the Film,
Siegfried Kracauer contrasts this abstracted, constructed motion of the
Battle on the Ice with the pure movement of the world in some of the more
evocative location shots in Potemkin:“Not forced to lend color to any given
story lines, the rising mists in the harbor, the heavily sleeping sailors, and
the moonlit waves stand for themselves alone.... They are largely pur-
poseless; it is they and their intrinsic meanings which arethe action” (Kra-
cauer 1960: 226). Like Balász before him, Kracauer is an afficionado of
Tissé’s camerawork, and in particular its ability to capture the indetermi-
nacy of mist and waves, those characteristic movements of enraptured vi-
sion, and of the cinema’s realist mission (the subtitle of his book is “The
Redemption of Physical Reality”). Unsurprisingly, then, he is less impressed
with the heightened, studio-shot, and rhetorical nature of Nevsky:
the pattern of motifs and themes which make up the Nevskystory are so pro-
nounced that they subdue everything that comes their way. Hence, even assum-
ing that the Battle on the Ice were cinematically on a par with the episode of the
Odessa steps, these patterns which spread octopus-like would nevertheless cor-
rode its substance, turning it from a suggestive rendering of physical events into
a luxuriant adornment. Owing to the given compositional arrangements, the
Battle sequence cannot possibly exert the influence of that Potemkinepisode and
thus on its part upset the theatricality of the action. It is nothing but an excres-
cence on the body of an intrigue imposed upon the medium. (Ibid.: 227)
There is a puritanical streak to Kracauer’s condemnation in the equa-
tion of “luxuriant adornment” with “excrescence” that recalls both the mod-
ernist (and racist) warcry of the architect Adolf Loos, “Ornament is crime,”
and the Romantic refusal of rhetoric as soulless decoration. The medium
has already suffered the indignity of having an intrigue forced on it; now
Nevskyredoubles the insult by dressing up the unwanted narrative structure
in the formal patterning of rhetorical tropes, not so much clothing it as
growing on it like warts. Worst of all, Nevsky is “theatrical,” not filmic.
| 125 |
To
ta
l
F
ilm
: M
u
s
ic
|
Since Nevskylacks the fluidity of Potemkin’s mists and waters, Kracauer
argues, it cannot have the medium-specific quality of existing for itself that
those images have. Placed alongside Bordwell’s critique of the stilted lack
ofmotion and depth cues, this suggests that the purposiveness of Nevsky’s
framing signals the bare fact that the montage segments are framed and
composed. Often enough such evidence of preconstruction connotes for
audiences of the twenty-first century the attempt to manage and unify view-
ers’ experience of the film, rather than evoke the (nowadays suspect) patri-
otic theme. The film is “theatrical” in the sense that it does not attempt
toimitate the world. Instead, it has indeed gone back to the “worn-out
method” of mise-en-scène, in its original sense of staging in the theater, to
further the control of montage over the formless movement of pixels. The
total film is total because it seeks to replace the world. Moreover, it does so
in the pursuit of a mythologization of its themes that will remove them from
history and bring them into the repeatable present of projection. The func-
tion of control, then, is not control for its own sake, nor even in the service
of society, but to segment the rapture of the entranced gaze and to organize
these tranchesof attention semantically, to substitute for the image-for-itself
a regime of the image-for-others.
No longer grounded in dialogue with the audience, the vector becomes
a monologic address. The others of the frame as it is sliced off from flux can-
not be human: they are the other images with which the single frame com-
bines in the growing spiral of overtonal and vertical montage. Eisensteinian
society is thus a society of images. This is how misreading the vector as to-
tality evades the productivity of boundless paradigmatic substitutions and
instead produces a realized social ordering of common purpose: the total
image. The utopian society of frames, then, conjoined under the regime of
the image, is what addresses the audience. Eisenstein’s siding with the hu-
man in the human-mechanical dialectic of the cinematic apparatus here re-
veals another side. Replacing the society of people, the society of images
turns the film into an agent: the cyborg orator.
The typical form of the contemporary cyborg is not Robocop or the
Terminator but the transnational corporation, a planet-spanning hybrid of
human biochips, networked communication devices, and offshore factories.
In Eisenstein’s day, the nascent social cyborg took the form of the European
dictatorships. In tune with that political environment, his Stalinist-period
| 126 |
C
h
ap
te
r
5
|
films shape themselves as oratorical devices composed of both the authorial
subject working toward the creation of an experience for the audience and
of the society of images formed by the rhetoric of montage. By abstracting
the graphical from the pulse of pure movement, by musicalizing sound and
by harnessing the productivity of paradigmatic substitution to the wagon of
allegory and myth, Nevskyand total film achieve at one blow the otherwise
unreasonable demand for absolute unity and the demagogic requirement of
absolute clarity. This substitution of totality for infinity produces that ab-
solute knowledge which Levinas so feared, the obsessive certainty that all
too easily turns into terror.
The formal perfection of Nevsky’s rhetorical construction is precisely
what makes it at once so fearful and so attractive. In eradicating the world,
Nevskyremoves itself from worldly temporality. Set aside from history and
occupying a timeless time of myth, its formality only fails according to the
canons of representation because it succeeds in escaping them, forming in-
stead its own and total organic unity without the confines of depiction and
time. The image, in its Eisensteinian conceptualization, becomes sublime.
Stripped of the alibi of a world seen from outside in the eyes of God,
this secular sublime turns instead to the cyborg vision of a world stripped
also of process. In Nevskythere is scarcely ever a sense that a hair has been
left to fall out of its assigned place. Even the robust love of life signified by
Gavrilo, swinging a phallic bit of clothing, swigging from a bucket, roaring
and laughing, is a piece of the montage, a knight on the chessboard. The in-
tegration of sound and image in pursuit of a single formal unity, a single
thematic image and a single address to the audience, even in this secular
mode, attaches itself not to the historical world but to eternity, the eternal
present of Virilio’s (1996) landscape of events. What the total cinema offers
is a détournementof the vector toward the task of the cut: the production of
the diegesis as both an object in itself, separate from daily cares, and an ob-
jective account of that object. The cruel truth of the cyborg orator as total
knowledge is that it can no longer produce the social resolution of the di-
alectic between subject and object. Eisenstein himself left this account of
the problem:
An objective “presentation” may be realized only when the phenomenon can be
objectively “presented” to itself, that is, when it is possible to put it in front of
| 127 |
To
ta
l
F
ilm
: M
u
s
ic
|
itself, that is, having separated it from itself, that is, having put the phenomenon
separated from itself, and itself as an observer of itself—opposite each other.
Actually, even in the most common phenomenon, for example a totally “ob-
jective” relation to it is possible only under conditions of the removal of any “sub-
jective coloring” in relation to it, that is, any personal connection with it except
for a scholarly, unprejudiced interest as to an object or exterior phenomenon.
We certainly cannot put ourselves into these conditions that are necessary
for an objective discernment of the laws of movement of matter, in respect to
that matter that we compose (and that composes us!).
An orientation of our interest to an awareness of this movement through that
part of matter, which we ourselves are, which each one of us is, is inevitably pre-
destined to be inseparable from the subjectivity here completely dominating us.
Therefore such an orientation to ourselves (into ourselves) cannot produce
objective knowledge.
However, what does such a striving toward oneself give to someone turning
his thoughts in this direction?
It does not give objective knowledge (as we have already said), but... the
subjective experience of these laws. (Eisenstein 1987: 175, ellipsis in the original)
In the formal universe of the total film, objective knowledge is mirrored
by subjective experience: the one belonging to the film, capable of standing
to itself as its own object, the other to the audience, able only to experience
the laws of the object. Though Eisenstein in many passages embraces the
idea of becoming, change, and transience, the ephemeral is always allied
with experience and excluded from knowledge, which is knowledge of the
“laws” that, governing nature and psyche alike, produce the ecstatic pathos
at the core of his late thought. But the ecstatic, a “psychic” rather than psy-
chological state, does not belong to the formless world of Bergsonian flux
but rather “outside of a concrete connection with a definite system of im-
ages, the ‘special’ feeling cannot really be ‘materialized,’ cannot be embod-
ied in any way” (Eisenstein 1987: 182). Indeed, the ecstatic state that derives
from the contemplation of the sublime in the work of art exists only “as the
sense of participation in the laws governing the course of natural phenom-
ena” (ibid.: 168–169). Those laws themselves, embodied in the material of
the film, are both the knowledge and the object of that knowledge, and it is
in contemplating their completion and their absolute truth that we attain
the ecstatic moment of pathos.
| 128 |
C
h
ap
te
r
5
|
This sublime unification of knowledge and its objects, then, is both the
lure and the destructive power of total cinema and of the cinematic sublime
as it has developed over the years since Eisenstein hitched the discovery of
its laws to the obdurate historical necessities of 1939. The genie was out
ofthe bottle. Sixty years later, the montage of effects has become the mon-
tage of affects, and total cinema serves no longer the needs of the anti-Nazi
struggle, but the perverse desire for the simulacrum that permeates the con-
temporary blockbuster.
| 129 |
To
ta
l
F
ilm
: M
u
s
ic
|
6
REALIST FILM: SOUND
| |
Jean Renoir and the Reality Effect
Pity and mockery suggest some idea of Good.
—Thomas Kinsella1
Realism and Beauty
La Règle du jeu (see figs. 6.1–6.4) was a disaster on its first release. A clique of
reactionaries, alerted to Renoir’s growing popularity after La Grande Illusion,
dismayed by his espousal of leftist Popular Front politics in La Vie est à nous
and La Marseillaise(Fofi1972/1973), and aggrieved by his pro-German and
pro-Jewish sentiments in an increasingly xenophobic year, orchestrated dis-
turbances at the premier and hostile criticism in the press (see Guillaume-
Grimaud 1986: 161–164). La Règle du jeunose-dived at the box-office not
only in 1939 but again in 1945 and 1948 (according to Truffaut in Bazin
1973: 257).
Renoir’s film is one of the closest to formal perfection of all films—
surely the reason structuralist analysis proves so at home with it (see Lesage
1985). At the same time, it is a jarring mix of callow farce and polyphonic
symmetries. As a model of realism, its failure with the audience who best
knew the world it depicted cannot be recovered under the old lie that pos-
terity is the final and best arbiter. If we recognize something in the film its
contemporaries did not, it is scarcely that we know their period better than
they. It may be that historical distance makes us more open to the film’s for-
mal elegance, but that does not explain why the realist code, intended to re-
veal truth accessibly, was repudiated by those for whom it had been made,
the war-wary audience Renoir confidently expected would welcome the film.
We deal in this chapter then with the simultaneous success and failure of re-
alist film.
Bazin’s familiar take on Renoir is that his direction of actors, his use of
fluid camera work determined by their movements, his gaze captured and
guided by the flashing and ephemeral movements of the world, and his gen-
erous opening out of the mise-en-scène through staging in depth and deep
focus cinematography make him the master of the realism. But just as Eisen-
steinian montage is less a matter of cutting than of vectoral infinity rendered
as totality, so Renoir’s realism is not so much a rapturous surrender to the
light as it is an analytical gaze, and so a cinema of the cut. As every serious
realist must, Renoir multiplies distinctions and differentiations. Perhaps it
was this almost surgical sensitivity to the cleavages and ruptures in the world
that made the film so hard to view in 1939. At the same time, perhaps de-
spite itself and in part owing to its continuing status as a classic of world cin-
ema, the film has come to exemplify a distinctive cinematic norm (despite
Crisp’s misleading belief that the film is best read as an aberration from
Hollywood; see Crisp 1993: 395): a cinema whose achievement is the con-
struction of a sensation of reality among its spectators.
The compositing function of deep-focus and depth staging (Braudy
1972; Sesonske 1980) are the most obvious aspects of the cut. Space is dis-
continuous in Renoir’s film. It is a hallmark of a great filmmaker to use the
top and bottom of the frame for entrances and exits. Renoir uses them to es-
tablish communication between the parallel worlds above and below stairs.
But he also establishes discontinuities between the layers of the image cre-
ated by the mise-en-scène, for example, when Octave is trying to remove his
bearskin. Much the same effect is achieved in the bravura editing of the
| 131 |
R
ea
li
s
t
F
i
lm
:
S
ou
n
d
|
opening sequence, as Jurieu’s angry disappointment is shown at the airfield,
and then broadcast, to eclectic reactions, in a series of discrete spaces whose
interconnections only deepen the sense of division between them. In the
former case, space is organized in planes more or less parallel to the plane of
the screen, while in the latter it is arranged as discrete stage sets that, by the-
atrical convention, are distinguished in time as well as in space.
The film’s theatricality—from its credit sequence matted onto prosce-
nium curtains to Octave conducting his imaginary orchestra—and the tra-
ditions of farce both invite the use of depth staging as a way of layering one
action over another, as when Schumacher interrogates Lisette while Marceau
tries to tiptoe to the kitchen stairs behind him, or when Octave and La
Chesnaye react in dumbshow in the background to Christine’s welcome to
Jurieu. In both cases, attention skips from one action to another by a dis-
| 132 |
C
h
ap
te
r
6
|
| Figure 6.1 |
La regle du jeu:The kitchen set with Lisette, Marceau, and Schumacher staged in depth.
Courtesy BFI Collections.
junctive route, selecting either one or the other, but unable to encompass
both. In this sense the cut between layers constitutes the cinematic event as
object of the camera’s gaze. In both examples, the dialogue too assumes a
layered aspect, a polysemy determined according to which of the characters’
reactions we tend to isolate. Where Méliès’s use of layers was formed about
the construction of a single event, Renoir’s sound-era layering produces not
only multiple events, but the event as multiple, truth escaping the wit of
each protagonist and multiplying the positions from which the meanings of
the scene can be understood or interpreted among both the audience and
the protagonists.
Nor is the camera in a privileged position of absolute knowledge.
Rather, as Bazin notes, it is personified:
Throughout the entire last part of The Rules of the Gamethe camera acts like an
invisible guest, wandering about the salon and the corridors with a certain cu-
riosity, but without any more advantage than its invisibility. The camera is not
noticeably any more mobile than a man would be (if one grants that people run
about quite a bit in this château). And the camera even gets trapped in a corner,
where it is forced to watch the action from a fixed position, unable to move with-
out revealing its presence and inhibiting the protagonists.(Bazin 1973: 87)
This “half-amused, half-anxious way of observing the action” (ibid.) is a re-
sult of pure technique. Raymond Durgnat identifies this anthropomor-
phism of the technical machinery as “a Christian phenomenalist awareness
of the continuity between director, aesthetic set-up, illusion and spectator”
and counters that, after all, the film is not a single continuous shot or, like
The Lady in the Lake, filmed entirely from the point of view of a single char-
acter; he points out that “there are, after all, about 400 cuts in the film”
(Durgnat 1974: 194). What this statistic loses is the tremendous difference
in pace between the bulk of the film and the rapid cutting of the hunt se-
quence, which introduces a mathematical anomaly into the calculation of
average shot length.
More informative is Barry Salt’s diagram of the shot types in La Règle du
jeu(Salt 1983: 249), where medium, medium long, and long shots dominate,
with close-ups and medium close shots following behind. The diagram is
unusually level. Though there are unsurprisingly few big close-ups or very
long shots, the film covers the characters and their environment remarkably
| 133 |
R
ea
li
s
t
F
i
lm
:
S
ou
n
d
|
evenhandedly. The big close-up is a privileged access to the soul of a char-
acter, whereas the very long shot belongs to the class of shots (like very high
angles, crane and aerial shots) that give viewers the sense of a divine ab-
straction from the action. The anthropomorphism of the camera is thus also
a kind of humanism.
The problem of realism is usually stated as a problem of representa-
tion—of the relation between signifier and referent, or more generally be-
tween signification and world. If we consider it as a special effect of which
the cinema is capable, however, we can construe realism slightly differently.
In La Règle,first, the profilmic is constructed as layered and so as multiple,
and hence open to contradictory meanings and interpretations. At the same
time, the anthropomorphic camera suggests that the reality effect reunifies
a world that it has first multiplied, by establishing a cyborg relation between
the viewer and the camera, and hence with the projection of the film. Real-
ism’s differentiating gaze renders the world as multiple, but at the same time
it recognizes that its gaze is not only differentiating but differentiated, in
such a way that multiplicity can become its singular object.
Something similar holds of the soundtrack. “I regard dubbing, that is to
say, the addition of sound after the picture has been shot, as an outrage. If
we were living in the twelfth century, a period of lofty civilization, the prac-
titioners of dubbing would be burnt in the market-place for heresy. Dub-
bing is equivalent to a belief in the duality of the soul” (Renoir 1974: 106).
The reality effect that emerges from La Règle du jeu is as much a function of
the soundtrack as of the visual, a result of the privilege accorded to direct
recording of sound, postsynchronized sound being used only to generate
the accompaniment to the opening and closing credit sequences. Where ex-
tradiegetic music in narrative sequences tends to emphasize the presence of
an intelligence narrating the tale and commenting on it in musical form, the
emphasis on dialogue and sound effects proposes something else: a story
that tells itself. Toward the end of the meal in the servants’ hall, music gently
wells up in the background. It seems to be nondiegetic, but at a certain mo-
ment the chef turns off a radio until then unnoticed. Our anchorage in a mu-
sic that seemed to be instructing us in how to respond to the sequence has
been severed: now we understand that it is merely an accident of the diegetic
world, an interruption into the kitchens of other times, recorded and broad-
cast, and other places, synchronous but working to their own schedules. In
the opening sequence, the radio places us in a subjectivity dispersed across
| 134 |
C
h
ap
te
r
6
|
the characters and spaces of the film, a consciousness that hears around cor-
ners and links disparate sets through a foregrounded technology. Inhuman
or cyborg, the radio is a consciousness impassioned by the group psychol-
ogy of a community in disrepair, capable of eavesdropping but not of com-
prehension—a prefigurement of the misunderstanding of the spyglass. The
truth we overhear is not absolute but social, even when we are out in exte-
rior locations with wild-tracks of country noises.
Such truth is not single, and the consciousness that retails it to us is not
single either; but neither is it multiple. Quite the contrary—in the formal
symmetries that structure it visually and aurally, the film establishes a pow-
erful sense of unity. A multiple consciousness would have to provide us with
multiple points of view, yet the film rarely privileges a point of view shot ex-
cept to demonstrate the fallibility of vision. Like the radio, the film is not a
unitary subjectivity but a zero subject, one that is not identical to itself. As
we have seen, the nonidentical implies flux. Insofar as the nonidentical sub-
ject seeks truth, it must be self-abnegating to be receptive, but also unfixed,
and unstable, as is the world that it observes. So the crux can be understood
as the relation between a zero subject observing a numerable world. The
film, then, is not itself a machine but an account of one.
Take the famous close-up of La Chesnaye introducing his mechanical
organ at the height of the fête:
DALIO:I don’t know why I had such trouble standing in front of the camera just for a
few seconds. Perhaps, because I did not say one word... I had no dialogue to help me.
We actors, you know, we need some speech, and in this particular shot I had no words. I
had to appear, then react, and you weren’t satisfied with...
RENOIR: You had to appear modest and also vain... that’s not so easy... and
against you, you had the terrific music of the mechanical organ... which was
deafening.
DALIO:Well, I only got it right after two hours. I remember, you retook it...
RENOIR:But what a shot, eh?
DALIO:Yes, that’s what people often say to me.
RENOIR: As it is now... I think it’s the best shot I’ve done in my life. It’s fan-
tastic. The mixture of humility and pride, of success and doubt... I realise that
I was wrong about it at first, I thought it could be an improvised shot, but in fact
we had to work on it, shooting it again and again. (Renoir 1970: 12)
| 135 |
R
ea
li
s
t
F
i
lm
:
S
ou
n
d
|
The emphatic sense of work involved in creating a moment of reality—
a reality effect—emerges again in accounts of the hunt sequence. As
Cartier-Bresson recalls, “It was not very easy, because Dalio and the other
actors had no idea how to hold a gun, and I had to shoot the rabbits while
they were pretending!” (Cartier-Bresson 1994: 557). Durgnat notes the dif-
ficulties of directing dying rabbits, even though they were collected and
loosed in the best possible places for the shots required, as well as the diffi-
culties of protecting cameras and crew from ricochets: “As it was, the se-
quence took several men two months to shoot, the final solution being to
install camera and crew close to the rabbits, but in an armoured shed”
(Durgnat 1974: 186). The modern telephoto lens would seem to get around
this problem, but even telephoto is a means to a special effect, achieved by
a process of work and appreciated by audiences as effect.
“One starts with the environment to arrive at the self,” Renoir wrote late
in his career (Renoir 1974: 171). Thus in Madame Bovarythe sounds of low-
ing cattle and clattering horses, the clip-clop of hooves mixed with the chat-
ter of a brougham rolling over cobbles, build toward an understanding of
the peace of the Norman countryside and the desperation that quiet brings
to Emma. At the opposite end of the scale, and closer to Dalio’s experience
with the mechanical organ, lies the recording of trains in La Bête Humaine,
where the sound of La Lisonis that of the very train in which Gabin and
Carette ride, the noise of which forces them to communicate by gesture, and
which is carefully modulated as the train runs on open track, through tun-
nels or over bridges, distinguishing quite clearly between the haughty echo
of the engine hall at Le Havre and the far deader sound of the Gare St.
Lazare, and evoking in detail the singing of the rails after the train has
passed a small country station, or how its passage rings over the water when
heard from below a bridge. Such is the sound of the frogs in the marshes,
of the echoing gunfire and the shouts of the beaters in establishing the
Sologne, and its difference and distance from the crowd scene at the airport
with which the film begins.
Most of all, however, what we hear in La Règleis voices. It would not be
quite true to say that we hear dialogue, much of which is muffled by the sur-
rounding acoustic and especially by the overlapping layers of talk. The dia-
logue of La Règleis closer to what Chion calls “emanation speech” (Chion
1988: 92ff). Alan Williams notes Renoir’s fascination with the voice, dis-
tinguishing between the emotional interest of the later films and the social
| 136 |
C
h
ap
te
r
6
|
variety of speech in those films of the 1930s in which “he emphasized its
function as social marker (through confrontations of different accents and
word patterns)” (Williams 1992: 315).
Moreover, as Michel Marie observes,
what Renoir’s cinema rejects, from 1931 on, is a “neutral” French, the “zero de-
gree of spoken French” that in fact is only the speech of the Ile de France, and
more specifically that of the intellectual bourgeoisie; an ‘unmarked” speech be-
cause it determines the norm, the “standard of reference.” This anemic language
that is taught in the Conservatoires reigns unconditionally over the French cin-
ema today; it is the speech of dubbers. (Marie 1980: 220)
Marie notes Carette’s Parisian voice in La Bête Humaine, Dita Parlo’s “de-
lectable accent of the German Alps” in La Grande Illusion, and Nora Gré-
gor’s “foreign” accent as Christine. The association of normative accents
with dubbing and with a damnably theatrical style of expression of course
points toward the realist aspiration of the films. But it also indicates a spe-
cific job of work undertaken in casting and directing to establish the sound
of the voice as a critical technical device, as significant and sometimes more
so than the improvised dialogue it delivers. There is, then, a specific mean-
ing of the word “poetic” to apply to Renoir’s use of voices. In the rhetorical
framework, Renoir’s realism is a mode of elocutio,the choice and ordering of
words, but we have to add immediately that these words are selected as much
for their sound as for their sense (“is not the human voice the best means of
conveying the personality of a human being?” Renoir 1974: 103; “I started
to be interested not so much in words but in sounds. In the expressions of
the human being helped by the emission of sounds,” (Litle 1985: 312, citing
a 1954 interview of Renoir by James D. Pasternak). When, for example, the
general pronounces the word “rare,” the long a and rolling rs expose more
than either what the General intends by them or what we can read of the
film’s judgment on his intention: we hear also the sound itself as a marker of
class, just as we hear in Octave’s quickfire repartee or Jurieu’s hesitance their
outsider status at the château.
The spaces of La Règle, similarly, are not unified in a single gaze. Ex-
plicable neither as profilmic, empirical nor geometric, the stacked layers of
the action are incommensurate with one another. The same multiplication
of perspectives holds good of the voices. In several of Renoir’s films of
| 137 |
R
ea
li
s
t
F
i
lm
:
S
ou
n
d
|
the1930s, there is a protagonist—Lantier, Emma, Amédée Lange—whose
voice carries our attention as the focal point through which all the lines of
sound coagulate. Such is the scene in Le Crime de M. Langein which Amédée
enthusiastically yells out the story of his comic book, while the camera pans
around his room, leaving him behind as it inspects the map of Arizona and
the cowboy trappings of the down-at-heel cold-water flat in Paris. There the
fantasy carried by the voice is belied by the environment, but it is the voice
that persuades us—that the fantasy is better than the reality. In La Règle
there is no single voice to give us a similar centering. Indeed, as Michael
Litle observes, there are instead only the patterns of devices that separate
voice from the person—microphones, loudspeakers, telephones (Litle
1985: see also Chion 1999: 62).
The player piano that so fascinates the women around it in the danse
macabresequence gives us another model for the dialogue: that it is a rule-
governed system that plays itself. Like the visual spaces, the aural spaces de-
mand neither empirical nor absolute knowledge but a lexicon, exactly that
lexicon that Jurieu lacks. Visually but especially aurally, time in La Règle du
jeuis the duration between event and comprehension, a duration that ex-
tends into a gap and thence into a gulf of silence, like Octave’s inaudible or-
chestra. After Mozart’s “Danse Allemande” over the opening credits, we
must hear only what is in the world of the film—a small restriction that has
subsequently become almost a gospel for realists: the British television soap
opera EastEndershas maintained the same rule for two decades. The loss in
reality, and the commonsense belief today that “realist” means “depressing,”
arises from a misunderstanding of why Renoir introduced this tool for
verisimilitude. It was not to evince his hatred of the world that is but quite
the opposite: to love it better, and to convince us that it is worth loving, even
if those who inhabit it can neither see nor hear themselves or it. The tragic
tone arises not from an external judgment but from within that world which
cinema alone can recognize in its unique and vulnerable ephemerality. Its
sole error, perfectly understandable, and unfortunately the one lesson gen-
uinely repeated from the film’s aesthetic as a norm, is the unification of that
fleeting multiplicity around the mortal moment. This is what has allowed re-
alism to ally itself with the fatal nihilism of an artificially restricted sublime,
and to fail even in its self-proclaimed mission to reveal the world. Instead, as
ever, it has succeeded only in depicting an image. It was Renoir’s achieve-
ment to have made of that image an adequate if tragic response to theworld.
| 138 |
C
h
ap
te
r
6
|
Neither Cartesian nor mimetic, the layered, analyzed space of La Règle
is a special effect. The reality effect is never purely textual because it has to
exist as an effect for someone. Even if, as apparatus theory argues, “some-
one”—the subject of signification—exists only as an aporia and at the same
time a moment of excess in the signifying chain, nonetheless “someone” has
to occupy the position at which realism is effective. As Ien Ang (1985) dis-
covered in her pursuit of popular meanings of the 1970s soap opera Dallas,
“realism” can apply not only to formally realist and convincingly realistic
texts but to the perceived authenticity of depicted emotions. La Règle du jeu
is such an emotional portrait, or rather, in the melodramatic mode, a portrait
of emotions. To some extent the film is curiously unaffecting: we care rela-
tively little for any of the characters, who in turn often seem to care little
enough for themselves, declaring with wilting charm their boredom, their
fickleness, their trivial relationship with life. Rather what enchants is at once
the levity of the life shown and to some extent embraced by the film, and its
amoral wit, while we are nevertheless drawn to judge it; in short, the har-
mony between the dissection of the social game and the delight of playing it.
The Bachelor Machines
Apparatus theory posits “a sort of ‘common trunk’... the cinema-machine
itself envisaged in its conditions of possibility” (Metz 1982: 152), embrac-
ing industry and audience in the technological bases of cinema. Drawing on
Panofsky (1991) and Lacan’s relation of perspective to the Cartesian cogito
(Lacan 1973: 86), for apparatus theory the perspectival geometry of camera
and projector unify subjectivity, so constituting the individualist subject
required by modernity and capital: the subject of ideology. As Panofsky ar-
gued, perspective had been reviled before: by the German Expressionists for
its objectivism; by Botticelli for its subjectivism; by Plato for confusing ob-
jective and subjective. For Panofsky what remains constant throughout the
epochs of perspective is its mathematical nature, and that what it “mathe-
matizes” is, albeit in abstract form, the empirical field of natural vision
(Panofsky 1991: 74). So he is able to conclude that the triumph of Renais-
sance perspective was achieved through the negation of both magical and
symbolic spaces to bring the supernatural world of miracles within the am-
bit of direct perception, “in the sense that the supernatural events... erupt
into [the viewer’s] own, apparently natural, visual space and so permit him
to ‘internalize’ their supernaturalness” (ibid.: 75). For Panofsky this triumph
| 139 |
R
ea
li
s
t
F
i
lm
:
S
ou
n
d
|
announces the end of theocracy and the arrival of a world centered on the
human. Like Bazin, Panofsky believes that by bringing the (super)natural
within the pictorial field, perspectival or realist representation allows it to
erupt in all its strangeness into consciousness.
For apparatus theory, it is not humanism but the geometrical perspec-
tive normalized in the beaux arts tradition that is designed into camera
andprojector lenses. The cinematic apparatus encourages or enforces an
identification with the lens as both recipient and origin of the image. But
unlike both Panofsky and Bazin, apparatus theory suggests that the geome-
try of illusion promotes identification with the machine, not the world, and
that that is the source of anthropocentric individualism. But then we are al-
ready faced with a dual identification—with the apparatus and with the self.
Likewise for Panofsky: the perceiving self externalizes its visual perception
| 140 |
C
h
ap
te
r
6
|
| Figure 6.2 |
La regle du jeu:The Marquis and Jurieu: playing the game too well or not well enough.
Courtesy BFI Collections.
as field, then projects the field as object or as medium for a third element,
the irruption of strangeness into consciousness. This epiphany is the
sought-after realization of the world in consciousness, and it takes, in secu-
lar realism, the form of a sudden rending of the familiar veils of habit.
Assimilating the institutional, the technological, and the psychological,
the sole job of the apparatus is to renew itself through the circuit of ticket
purchase and investment in further production (Metz 1975: 19). At the same
time, “a society is only such in that it is driven by representation.If the social
machine manufactures representations, it also manufactures itselffrom rep-
resentations” (Comolli 1980: 121). As both economic and ideological, the
cinematic apparatus is purely homeostatic. Here, as in the conceptualization
of social “technologies” in Foucault, there appears an echo of the Cath-
olicsocial critic Jacques Ellul, for whom the term “technique” embraced
not only mechanical technologies but also the technologies of econom-
ics, organization, and those characteristically modern technologies, “from
medicine and genetics to propaganda” for which “man himself becomes
theobject of technique” (Ellul 1964: 22). In an assault that resonates with
Renoir’s mockery of the Count’s artificial music machines in La Règle du jeu,
Ellul believes that “The human being is delivered helpless, in respect to life’s
most important and most trivial affairs, to a power which is in no sense un-
der his control. For there can be no question today of a man’s controlling the
milk he drinks or the bread he eats, any more than of his controlling his gov-
ernment” (ibid.: 107). Apparatus theory links the critique of technology in
Mumford (1934) and Giedion (1948) to the pessimism of simulationists like
Baudrillard and Virilio. For apparatus theory, cinema is one more technique
evolved to separate the human from the world, to hand its subjects over
bound and gagged to a self-replicating system of pure representation.
Critical to the version proposed by Metz, Baudry (1976, 1985) and Co-
molli is the concept of a subject unified at the Cartesian vanishing point of
optical perspective, the point of convergence of all lines of vision focused
and refocused in the camera, the projector, and the architecture of the cin-
ema auditorium. Hubert Damisch’s critique of Panofsky (and also explicitly
of apparatus theory, Damisch 1994: xv–xvi) points out the centrality of in-
finity to the geometrical construction of the different forms of perspective
that, he is adamant, cannot be reduced to a single technique or a single ide-
ological system.
| 141 |
R
ea
li
s
t
F
i
lm
:
S
ou
n
d
|
As we have seen, La Règleis remarkably poor in those very long shots
that offer a view of the world from the standpoint of the infinite. Moreover,
both Damisch and Panofsky suggest, perspective itself is not a technique of
illusionism but a gateway to a mystical universe that appears precisely at that
vanishing point which Renoir’s layered and segmented vision does not open
up for us. Damisch’s argument is that Renaissance perspectival space is not
Cartesian, not least since Descartes’s own geometry, like that of the ancients,
was fundamentally two-dimensional. Eli Maor (1987: 109) makes a similar
point: geometrical perspective is a projective geometry whose goal is not
the definition of the “true,” absolute geometrical form of spheres and cubes,
but the transformations they undergo when projected: a science not of the
world but of its appearances. In effect, what perspective makes visible is not
the world but the gaze we turn on it. As such, it is as likely to produce a sense
of unreality, or rather a doubled sense of the marvel of appearance, a sense
of wonder that embraces both the appearance and the machinery that makes
it possible. In Panofsky’s description there is only the word “internalize” to
suggest that there is at stake a unification rather than a dispersal. Geomet-
ric perspective in general and the foreclosure of the mystical infinite in
Renoir in particular suggest that, paradoxically, we experience mediation
immediately—a double articulation that, as it were, encourages us to see the
window at the same time that we see through it, in the cinema assimilating
the depiction at the same time that we are awed at its production. We are
confronted, then, not with the achievement of unity in the apparatus—the
ideological theory of realism—but by a dialectical process that multiplies
and unifies at once.
This dialectical realism is further affected by the recorded nature of the
image. When apparatus theory privileges the camera and projector as key
elements of the institution of cinema, it elides the institutions of postpro-
duction so important to the study of special effects: the edit suite and the
laboratory. Emphasizing the mirrored roles of camera and projector, appa-
ratus theory spatializes the cinema, so colluding in the dehistoricizing pro-
cedures of the culture it so wishes to critique. Postproduction processes,
where the temporal dimension condenses, flag the role of the cinematic in-
stitution as a delay in communication, underpinning the duration of the film
itself with the separate but contributory temporality of the business of film-
making. To ignore postproduction is to ignore the time of mediation, and to
| 142 |
C
h
ap
te
r
6
|
subscribe to the perilous predestination of ideology’s success by misrecog-
nizing as immediate its temporal workings.
Both as a portrait of an ancien régime in decay and as a reworking of the
theater of Beaumarchais, Marivaux, and Musset, the film evokes and evoked
a certain archaism. Even at the time of its release, La Règle du jeuwas already
a document of a certain past, even though Renoir was still cutting after the
premier. By the time the current version was restored, it had become a his-
torical record not only of a class but of a mode of communication. Between
1939, the year of its first release, and 1952, the year of its first appearance in
the Sight and Sound lists, television, with its ability to transmit live, had
usurped the critical priority of cinema. As broadcasting usurped the docu-
mentary role of cinema, critical perception of La Règlechanged from urgent
depiction to contemplative formalism. It was perhaps this unwilled transi-
tion that informed apparatus theory’s crucial misunderstanding of the tem-
poral relationship between spectators and technologies of cinema.
The word “apparatus” translates two French words, appareil,or machin-
ery, and dispositif,which also has the sense of arrangement or disposition of
materials. Joan Copjec notes that dispositif refers to discourse rather than
technology, an institutional mode of signification in which “truths are in-
ternal to the signifying practices that construct them” (Copjec 1982: 57). In
the dispositif variant, since discourse is never over, unified subjectivity is
never achieved, least of all under the conditions of production of La Règle
dujeu.Drawing together the evidence of a number of biographers and crit-
ics, Wollen (1999) observes that Renoir’s crew on this film had worked to-
gether in various combinations throughout the 1930s, a familiarity that
explains Renoir’s repeated description of La Règleas his most improvised
film. Though it has become normative, it was not itself formulaic, and the
resulting subjectivity is not the result of anonymous serial manufacture
on the studio model of apparatus theory but the work of a community of
intimates. Rather than a preordained, stable, and centered effect that be-
lieves itself a cause, the subject of this apparatus is an unstable and dislo-
cated agency of signification that believes it is its product.
No one pretends that a film, least of all a fiction film, describes unam-
biguously or finally a world that preexists the filmmaking. This is a matter
not only of what is lost but of what is gained. In any film, the diegetic world
is often more cogent, more coherent than the everyday. When the film is a
| 143 |
R
ea
li
s
t
F
i
lm
:
S
ou
n
d
|
fiction, the diegesis will also be more symmetrical, more logical, and more
just than we know our world of experience to be. As a result, something rad-
ically unstable filters into realist narrative diegesis, a competition between
the demands of verisimilitude and those of formal elegance. For Copjec, the
“forms that discourses take are not expressionsof a last instance, a sovereignty
which maintains and reproduces itself through these discourses. To deter-
mine the conditions of existence of a particular discourse is not to reduce
these conditions to a monolithic discourse” (Copjec 1982: 58). The concept
of dispositif, Copjec believes, is just such a conflictual and open notion of
thework of film. The Althusserian “last-instance” determinism (Althusser
1971: 160) of the rival concept of appareil, is, she argues, an error that
“threatens to jettison the radical potential of the concept of the dispositifin
favor of the hypochondria of the unified male body image” (ibid.: 59). It is
not the cinema but this particular theory, fetishizing the technology in an
effort to avoid sexual difference, that is the true bachelor machine.
Far from exemplifying a patriarchal machinery of dominance in full
flood, La Règle du jeurather consciously embodies the idea of cinema as an
apparatus, as an institution that incorporates both the technological condi-
tions of production and the psychic connections and positionings that it en-
ables or determines, even the best part of four decades before the idea was
conceptualized. La Règle du jeuis itself a machine, in the sense captured by
Deleuze in a gloss on Foucault where he singles out the factory as the most
visible type of the “environments of enclosure” associated with surveillance
societies. The factory’s function, Deleuze notes, is “to concentrate; to dis-
tribute in space; to order in time; to compose a productive force within the
dimension of space-time whose effect will be greater than the sum total of
its component parts” (Deleuze 1997: 444)—a neat description of the ro-
mantic, organic artwork. Renoir’s plot machine, coupled with his vision ma-
chine, both articulated through his sound machine, exists to describe, as if
by analogy, the social machine that it depicts, a machine whose purpose, like
the machines of early cybernetic theory, is to control itself.
At the same time that La Règle presents itself reflexively as a machine,
however, it exists as a machine for depicting another machine—the para-
noid projection machine of the haute bourgeoisie embodied in the rules of
its games. Psychoanalysis defines paranoia as a defense against homosexu-
ality that invokes both a phantasmatic power to influence and a hypochon-
| 144 |
C
h
ap
te
r
6
|
driac state smitten by fantasies of persecution. This machine, fabricated
from constantly elaborated delusions, projects them outward as objects
that reverse direction and punish a subject whose “perverse” desire cannot
otherwise be acknowledged or enacted. The self-critical role of the filmic
machine in La Règleis critically visible in what otherwise the machinery of
paranoia exists to blot out—the unnamed but highly distinct homosexual
man. The film presents what is distinctively absent from the bachelor ma-
chine, the screen presence of homosexuality (“Well, have they or haven’t
they?” he asks of Jurieu and Christine in shot 106. When Charlotte replies
“They have,” his response is unambiguous: “What a shame... such a dis-
tinguished boy!” [Renoir 1970: 74]).
The rules of the haute-bourgeois game have not so much denied as dis-
avowed homosexuality in a movement that accepts the signs but not the ac-
tuality of desire. Perhaps it is possible to put this in a more responsible way,
in a language more empathetic to Renoir’s project. The bourgeois game
doesn’t disavow desire. It disavows love, the very love the film itself extends
toward them. The whole intelligence of the film—which I have been call-
ing “Renoir”—exists in this forgiveness it rains on the world it presents, a
forgiveness tinged with the tragic realization that it is necessary to love this
world because it is the only one. The film machine doubles the social ma-
chine to negate its lack of self-love, to fill the void in its heart, to be the pro-
jection of a love it denies itself.
Fantasies of Negation
Copjec contrasts dispositif,structured by absence and sexual difference, with
the paranoia of appareiland its ascription of deathly powers of influence to
an external projection of the self. Penley goes further, offering a theory of
fantasy: “to describe not only the subject’s desire for the filmic image and
itsreproduction, but also the structure of the phantasmatic relation to that
image, including the subject’s belief in its reality” (Penley 1989: 80). The
constant recombinations and reconfigurations of characters onscreen, for
example, correspond to the multiple and shifting subject positions open to
the spectator while still recognizing the centrality of the cinema’s institu-
tions to the production of meaning and engagement with the image. This
formulation, echoing Freud’s account in “A Child Is Being Beaten” (Freud
1979), suggests that there are multiple relations with the image, including
| 145 |
R
ea
li
s
t
F
i
lm
:
S
ou
n
d
|
faith, incredulity, negation, and disavowal (I believe, I don’t believe, I’m be-
ing lied to, I know it isn’t real but), each of which can be active separately,
sequentially, or simultaneously.
An ensemble piece like La Règle clearly invites multiple positioning:
coherence, likeness to material reality, probability, reversal, emotional au-
thenticity or psychological credibility, disbelief, willing suspension of dis-
belief, disavowed suspension of disbelief. La Règle du jeudoes not enforce
asingle unified subject position. Rather it enables a multiplicity of subjec-
tivities.2It is precisely this multiplicity that enables the sense of freedom
Bazin felt so deeply, and permits the audience to return to the film the feel-
ing of an unstill, many-layered, ephemeral world. Kracauer is thus quite
wrong to identify photography as antipathetic to fantasy, at least as Penley
defines it. Quite the contrary: fantasy is the multiple nature of our relation
to the world, most of all when it is depicted.
Deep staging, mobile camera, ensemble playing with no clear protago-
nist: these too played a part in the film’s failure, for exactly the reasons that
make them the norms of realist cinema today. The cut comes into play in a
further difficulty experienced by the film’s first audiences, a difficulty in the
editing. Durgnat notes that some critics had a problem with Renoir’s but-
terfly mind, his interest not only in the core action but in the environmen-
tal details, often apparently unrelated to the action, that catch the camera’s
look at odd moments in the film. “The difficulty which Renoir posed for the
critics,” he suggests, “was the way in which his interest was constantly flick-
ering from the obvious climax to some adjacent distraction or unemphatic
theme” (1974: 217).
La Règlecertainly benefits from the recasting and rewriting of char-
acters necessitated by unforeseen circumstances, producing a film that is
much less centered on a single character (Christine appears to have been the
protagonist at one point until Renoir seems to have fallen out of love with
Nora Grégor’s screen presence; see, e.g., Bertin 1991: 159–60; Bergan 1992:
201) and thus on character psychology. The result is a film that skips from
character to character, allowing us enough time to understand their moti-
vations and reactions, but fascinating us with the dynamic of their interplay
as a portrait of the group rather than as individuals.
Of a rather different order is the insert shot of a frog in the moat at shot
295, dropped suddenly into the dénouement of the film. It is possible to
accuse Renoir of emulating the free, distracted gaze of an interloper in the
| 146 |
C
h
ap
te
r
6
|
action rather than giving that freedom to the audience, but the sheer incon-
sequentiality of the shot baffles the viewer, and becomes a forgotten detail,
a self-erasing instant (I have found no mention of this shot in the extensive
literature on the film, though it would certainly be possible to embroider an
interpretation).3Unmotivated, the image does not determine either subjec-
tivity or sense, and indeed it creates the possibility that things don’t neces-
sarily have to mean anything at all in the film—that they can simply be there
and as such drag us out of our illusion of understanding, denying our deter-
mination by the film’s construction of meaning, refusing the monolithic ide-
ology effect propounded by the bachelor-machine version of apparatus
theory. Once again we find, as perhaps Bazin might have hoped, that real-
ism creates a form of freedom in the spectator, but circumscribes it with the
governing presence of a world that, however unmotivated, nonetheless is
signified though it does not signify. Because it does not signify, the depicted
world can retain its autonomy even from the processes of depiction on
which it depends.
The shot of the frog opens up the possibility of an encyclopaedic cata-
log of the ways that a world can be inhabited. But even if Renoir’s realism
ischaracteristically geometric or typological rather than narrative, there re-
mains a risk that the subjectivities set into motion by the realist film may
themselves be subject to some form of cataloging, and that the list of iden-
tifications and distancings suggested above is not an infinite series but a
matrix of possibilities carefully structured in relation to that agency which
Renoir calls the rules.
The concept of a rule-governed system lies at the starting point of ap-
paratus theory, Jacques-Alain Miller’s seminar on suture. Citing Frege’s ac-
count of the foundations of arithmetic (see chapter 4, note 1),4Miller argues
that number arises from the subsumption of a thing under the object, and
the object under a concept. To be numerable, a thing in the world has to be
identified with itself as an object, as occurs in the filmic cut. In this progres-
sion, what constitutes the object as such is its difference from the thing it
subsumes, “Whence you can see the disappearance of the thing which must
be effected in order for it to appear as object—which is the thing in so far as
it is one” (Miller 1977/1978, 27). Miller here describes hypostasis. The thing
must become unitary, countable as one, an object, when it offers itself for
signification. The thing-in-itself becomes an object-for-others. In the pro-
cess it must lose its nonidentity.
| 147 |
R
ea
li
s
t
F
i
lm
:
S
ou
n
d
|
A countable world is no longer the world as such, which in the Lacan-
ian vocabulary is the Real, that which is excluded from signification. Fore-
grounding the missing heart of his world, Renoir’s realism appears to
address exactly what is absent from the screen, devoting itself to analyzing
the multiplication of entities that ensues from the primary absence of the
world from the diegetic universe. The exclusion of the world is synonymous
with its signification. Like all signification, both the film and the strategies
of the game take the form of a system. In this instance, the system is para-
noid. The rules demand the disavowal of homosexuality, not because it is
intrinsically evil or unbelievable, but because disavowal is the film’s diegetic
procedure for assimilating difference into unitary homeostasis. Thus ho-
mogeneity legitimates itself by containing what would otherwise be its
excluded other. Difference must be included, if only under the sign of era-
sure or marked as negative. Disavowal is the key to the system.
In Miller’s account, Frege’s nonidentical zero is the necessary basis of
any logical system, including the logic of signification. Like Lacanian “lack,”
this nonidentical generates signification and is therefore a formative prin-
ciple of subjectivity. But why should the construction of subjectivity reside
on the “negativity” of zero? Although Lacan had elsewhere at times pro-
posed –1 as the numerical designation of the subject in keeping with Miller’s
suggestion of a “pure negative” (see Heath 1978/1979: 52), in the important
seminar on vision of 1964 he was designating it as “rien” (see e.g., Lacan
1973: 171). Negativity is not zero, which sits between positive and negative.
Miller’s construction of pure negativity instead produces a new and fantas-
matic subjectivity as the reversal of the infinite—a negative infinite that,
since it is a component of every other number, is ubiquitous. This makes
Miller’s case for the primacy of signification, but places all change, all his-
tory, as well as all significance exclusively on the side of the subject, while
condemning it to an infinity of dissatisfaction.
Here the distinction between nonidentity and negativity is vital: zero is
not void. In the realist norm, however, there is a negative, but on the other
side of the equation: the world is lacking, excluded from the rules of the
game as its absent heart. The nonidentical is not a function of the Symbolic:
it is the nature of the Real. It is the world that is not identical with itself, the
Real moving image too, which is also, as far as the spectator is concerned, a
sensory datum before it can become either an object of perception or a
| 148 |
C
h
ap
te
r
6
|
meaningful sign. The realist image—like the random frog—belongs first to
Firstness. It is not the subject but the object that lacks. Nonidentity belongs
to the world, not the subject. Far from a unified image generating a unified
subject, the nonidentity of the world engenders the fantasmatic multiplica-
tion of identities. However, once realist dialectics of depiction and form are
embraced as normative conventions, realism finds itself returning in an at-
tempt to reconcile the nonidentical and identity so that it can reunify the
world, a unification it identifies in the mystical moment of epiphany.
Epiphany and Mortality
As Thompson (1988: 231–233) points out, a great deal of effort has gone
into the artificial construction of a diegetic world of La Règle in such a way
that it both resembles the everyday and articulates optimally with the
requirements of the apparatus, so closely indeed as to become part of the
apparatus itself. Yet, to the degree that it articulates (with) the bachelor
machine onscreen, the filmic system also begins to betray traits proper to
the machine it depicts, proliferating and elaborating systems of viewing and
hearing in the interests of a final reunification that is in the end not merely
pessimistic but nearly nihilistic. The lure of the epiphany is that it seems to
offer a still point at which fantasmatic subject and nonidentical world can be
unified. But there is a price. That moment, which both entices with its vi-
sionary power to unify and repels with its revelation that there is no mean-
ing in that union, is the sublime.
So realism runs between two risks. On one side lies the sublimity of auni-
fied vision that can take us out of meaning and therefore out of that history
which it is realism’s mission to bring us into. This is the moment captured in
Bazin’s citation from Mallarmé’s sonnet on Edgar Allen Poe: realism is “con-
cerned to make cinema the asymptote of reality—but in order that it should
ultimately be life itself that becomes spectacle, in order that life might in this
perfect mirror be poetry, be the self into which film finally changes it” (Bazin
1971: 82). On the other side lies the peril of conventionalism: the realization
that “realism in art can only be achieved in one way—through artifice” (ibid.:
26), a “necessary illusion,” but one that “quickly induces a loss of awareness
of the reality itself, which becomes identified in the mind of the spectator
with its cinematographic expression” (ibid.: 27), at which point the filmmaker
is no longer in control, but the dupe of her own technique. To escape one peril
| 149 |
R
ea
li
s
t
F
i
lm
:
S
ou
n
d
|
is to propel yourself toward the other. Between the autonomous logic of the
system of technique and the pure negative of the sublime, the pursuit of the
world in film seems doomed to the Freudian dialectic of desire and thanatos,
the endless pursuit of the object of desire down the chains of signification, or
the nirvana principle, the death instinct, the sublime moment at which mean-
ing and subjectivity are extinguished together.
The genius of La Règle du jeuis that it understands exactly these perils.
The film depicts a society for which the world has become void in the tri-
umph of signification. In its place are only the illusions produced by the sys-
tem itself—the farewell misunderstood as passion through the spyglass, the
coat and cloak taken as markers of identity in the mistaken amours in the
greenhouse. Against these the film juxtaposes a sense of the world as full,
crammed with lives the characters themselves cannot perceive. But Renoir,
despite his inventions and improvisations, his pirouettes and backflips of
technique designed to trick the world into revealing itself by willful twist-
ing of filmic conventions, nonetheless gives the lie to the fullness of the
world himself by entering into a doomed tryst with death. The fullness
ofthe world that emanates, almost as a scent, from the unfinished Partie de
campagne,the conceptualization of the world’s zero not as negative but as an
unstill fullness, is belied by the importance conceded to death as a guar-
antor of meaning and reality. The system engendered in the film (filmic
system as opposed to social code) depends on death as a negation of the ne-
gation—only thus do the lovers achieve an identity. Otherwise merely the
cyphers of a signifying system that incorporates and embodies but at the
same time annihilates subjectivity, they would remain, along with the illu-
sory world conjured by cinematic technique, unable to engender the reality
effect, since their “identity” would be only negative. Negating the negation
by killing what has no existence produces the positive effect the film de-
mands as a signifying system, even as it points to the opposite, the vacuity at
the heart of the excess of signification in the depicted social game.
So La Règle,and realist film more generally, depends on death, but only
because it believes that the instigating zero that sets the system running is a
void. However, as we saw in chapter 1, zero is not empty but null. The sys-
tem constructed by La Règle du jeuconfuses nullity with negativity, demand-
ing a double negation—once in the epiphanic moment such as the shot of
the frog, and once more in the apotheosis of death, a death that also, like ca-
tastrophe in television discourse, proves the veracity of the discourse itself
| 150 |
C
h
ap
te
r
6
|
(Doane 1990)—so casting the filmic and diegetic discourses at odds with
each other, a necessary precondition of fantasy.
La Règle’s gift is to emphasize this condition. But at the same time the
film abstracts nonidentity from the ephemerality of the world, because it
loses its grip on the plenitude of nonidentity (the fullness of zero). Hence
ephemerality is displaced from the world’s fullness to the subject’s empti-
ness, in such a way that the proper expression of emptiness—death as a con-
dition of worldliness—comes to define their relation. Ephemerality is no
longer the condition of perception shared by subject and object, a product
of the way the world “gives itself” to human vision, Caillois’s (1968) donné-
à-voir(see also Silverman 2000). Instead, centrally in the figure of the death-
defying and death-courting Jurieu, ephemerality is determined solely by the
mortality of the subject: because we die, the world is ephemeral. Death
makes beauty possible.
At one extreme the film as depiction proposes an epiphanic realism
thatanchors fullness in an extrahistorical moment of unity and so denies
ephemerality by transcending it. At the other, we find a narrative cinema of
“thanatic” realism that anchors history itself, as the experience of time and
hence the ground of ephemerality, in the exit of the subject from history at the
founding moment of death. So time, ephemerality, and history are each guar-
anteed by a loss that, unlike the usual psychoanalytic model of biology and
memory as destiny, is governed not by the past but by the ineluctible future.
Renoir’s film, as so often in his films of the later 1930s, is structured by
the shadow of a tainted future. As in Heidegger, the promise of mortality
drives us into the present, producing a Being always haunted by its future
demise, the being-toward-death (Heidegger 1962: 279–311). This taint
draws (rather than drives) signification toward it. And finally, as we recog-
nize that the illusion under which the whole apparatus of the film has been
working is in fact the truth of the film, the two modes of realism coalesce
into a single thought: the sublime moment of death as a sinking out of time
that instigates the experience of time, not as life but as mere duration: Mar-
ceau trying a few odds and ends, Octave trying to get by.The effort to pro-
duce a full world has ended up producing only a desperately empty one.
And here is the genius of the cinema, for this film emerged at the one mo-
ment in history when just getting by might have been the truest description
of its failure and the best possible way of surviving or even derailing the im-
pending crisis.
| 151 |
R
ea
li
s
t
F
i
lm
:
S
ou
n
d
|
Something similar is true of the hunt scene, shot on exterior locations
by Renoir’s second assistant, the distinguished photographer Henri Cartier-
Bresson. The landscape of the Sologne was selected consciously to evoke
and frame an atmosphere, the birch woods and marshy flatlands giving a
mournful, cool humidity to the tragic farce whose terms are being finalized
during the sequence (see Renoir 1974: 169–170, where he intimates that the
idea of filming the landscape antedated the idea of the film). The land-
scape—insofar as it is one, that is, insofar as it is both unified (“the Sologne”)
and generic—is itself a cinematic event. So too are the narratemes, the frag-
ments of gesture, dialogue, and interaction that constitute the activities of
the human and animal figures in it. That these events are logically prior to
narrative is apparent even in narrative theory, where, for example, “In con-
structing a fabula, the perceiver defines some phenomena as events” (Bord-
| 152 |
C
h
ap
te
r
6
|
| Figure 6.3 |
La regle du jeu:Marceau as a poacher, before and after the country house weekend. Courtesy BFI Collections.
well 1985: 51). But the term “narrateme,” denoting the smallest fragment of
narrative, preempts discussion of the ways in which films articulate events.
It is by no means clear that narrative is the first or most natural way of or-
ganizing events into larger systems—one thinks immediately of those
“American montage” sequences that show a series of views to establish the
scene of the ensuing action as the Sologne, Sydney, orSan Francisco. So
Bordwell is correct when he concludes his sentence on perceivers defining
phenomena as events, “while constructing relations between them.”
However, he is wrong to continue “These relations are primarily causal
ones” (Bordwell 1985: 51). What makes this film so unusual is the lack of
causal relations even between events occurring within the same shot. Ges-
tures and glances in La Règle du jeuare in many instances more significant
than the narrative of which they are the precondition. Apparently motive-
less events arise without prior causative structures, and attempts to recon-
struct a causal chain in retrospect are largely fruitless. More assemblage of
evidence than moral fable, La Règle du jeuworks by symmetries, transla-
tions, rotations, a whole geometry that reassembles rather than resembles
the world as manifold. A collocation of disparate and discrete phenomena
ordered spatially and temporally as a series of events forms a taxonomy in
the service of “les convenances,” the conventions that explain the moves,
passes, and parries of the plot. La Règleis more clearly legible as typology
than as a psychologically convincing or realistically plausible story. After all,
the farcical devices (disguises, elaborate deceptions, multiple infidelities
characteristic of eighteenth-century French comedy) do not construct a vi-
able narration of causes and effects. And the concluding death is instigated
by misunderstanding and misrecognition rather than by destiny or moral
flaw, the characteristic narrative engines of classical and Renaissance trag-
edy. What then makes it realist, in the narrow sense of bearing a resem-
blance to life, is the accident itself.
By definition, no accident is the effect of a cause. The sheer, blunder-
ing stupidity of the event strikes true, precisely because it is not justified by
its position in a causal chain. That Jurieu’s death in La Règleismeaningless,
compared to the deaths in Antigoneor Hamlet, makes it even more appro-
priately modern, even more appropriately catastrophic, even more appropri-
ately verisimilitudinous. As Saint-Aubin says in response to La Chesnaye’s
announcement of the death, “A new definition of the word ACCIDENT!”—
as indeed it is, a prefiguring of Virilio’s thesis of the general accident
| 153 |
R
ea
li
s
t
F
i
lm
:
S
ou
n
d
|
(Virilio1997: 132). The “accident” embraces the death of the hero who
knew neither how to play the game of popular heroism (as Octave tells
him, Renoir 1970: 42), nor the game of the château, nor,finally, the game
of love (when he tells Christine to wait while he obeys the rules of hospi-
tality by informing La Chesnaye that they are eloping).5
But the accident also embraces the multiple failures of the characters,
unifying them into a single catastrophe to which the General alone seems
blind, perhaps because, within months of the film’s release, his caste’s fail-
ure would be the most disastrous of all. Though previous scenes set up the
random mistake—the coats lent by Lisette to Christine and by Octave to
Jurieu—and so we are privy to the artifice of plotting that permits it, still it
remains random: explicable, but still a bolt out of the blue, arresting the
| 154 |
C
h
ap
te
r
6
|
| Figure 6.4 |
La regle du jeu:A ruling class without the will to rule, a working class without scruple.
Courtesy BFI Collections.
farce in midflight, like a child falling in the middle of an overexcited game.
Rather than tie up and explain what has gone before, as in the well-made
plot, and without providing the previous actions with a deeper significance,
as in the great tragedies of the past, the death simply underlines the chaotic
state of the world underlying the systems and structures by which we seek
tolive in it. At the same time, it brings the signifying chain to an abrupt
end.Three desultory scenes tidy up after the death. The rest is silence and
muddling through.
Here the film points up a core tenet of realism: that there is an end of
signification; that its stoppage stands at the place where signification ends
and the Real begins. Jurieu’s death at the end of La Règle du jeuproves the
truth-content of the film that precedes it by completing the taxonomy as its
summum. To signify that it is realism, then, the realist cinema deploys death
as the end of signification. In Heidegger, the anticipation of mortality is the
condition of individuation: by posing the possibility of nonbeing, it makes
the human creature cling even more to its self (Heidegger 1962: 310). With-
out death and the individuation it enforces, there would be no imperative
toward socialization and discourse. Heideggerian speech seeks to put off, to
evade, or, most especially, to speak against death. In Renoir’s film death func-
tions as the final silencing that completes by annihilating, and so demon-
strates the actuality of what it destroys.
Dying brings the world to heel. The careening aristos are brought to a
hierarchical finale, and all the scattered thoughts alight on a single point—
the point at which all thought, all signification, stops. Because it starts from
a negation of the world, realism’s double negation ends where it should be-
gin, in equilibrium, committed to the perfect present of Being, which, how-
ever, is always at the point of vanishing.
The Universal
The fatal moment in the narrative is the end of illusion: the moment of truth
is the instant of mortality. But though fatal, that is the epiphanic moment in
which the world reveals its mendacity as appearance. The world is not as it
appears—in fancy dress or through a looking glass. But nonetheless it is,
and in half-truths it reveals as epiphany its own desire: that the world yearns
for us to recognize it in its trickery, longs for us to recognize not that it is
other than it appears, but that it appears. Appearance, in other words, is the
world, as the “given-to-sight.” This insight allows us to consider, at least in
| 155 |
R
ea
li
s
t
F
i
lm
:
S
ou
n
d
|
the case of La Règle du jeu,an answer to Aumont’s (1996) query, à quoi pensent
les films?—what do films think about?
The film is beautiful in that it celebrates the ephemerality of appear-
ances, but it is also aesthetic in that it advances a historical theory of ap-
pearance, one tied particularly to the moment of modernity. As Bloch says
of Heidegger, La Règleis an accurate portrait of the anxiety of a class in the
process of disintegration (Bloch 1986: I, 110); it is also a study of an emer-
gent culture. Specifically, the film speaks of the loss of locality, the emergent
internationalization of modernity, adumbrating the abolition of the local
inpostwar globalization. In a number of writings and interviews, Renoir
stresses the horizontal nature of social relationships: aristocracy seeks aris-
tocracy, just as farmers seek farmers, regardless of language or nationality.
Locality remains a mere trace—we are treated to a disquisition on the na-
ture of aristocratic style by the chef, for whom ethnicity, nationality, even
noble blood have nothing to do with the culture of the gentleman.
By contrast, the two central characters in the servants’ hall, Marceau
and Schumacher, are powerfully linked to their locales—the Sologne and
Alsace. Schumacher and Marceau do not fit in and are ejected from the
château, while both the Jewish Marquis and his Austrian wife are at home in
the transnation of their class (see Appadurai 1996). There is already at work
that anonymization of place which will eradicate the parochial loyalties of
those characters. In Renoir’s film, the character Octave—Renoir himself,
asread by William Rothman (1987)—is alone in recognizing this deracina-
tion and in feeling it as an artist who cannot find his dreamt-of audience. In
La Grande Illusionthe “de” and “von” of Boeldieu and Rauffenstein gesture
toward both the landed estates from which the aristocratic names derive,
and their distance from them, not least since both are aviators. The relation-
ship of French marquis and German count sketches the way anonymization
and endocolonialism have implicated their subjects into a subjectless ma-
chine of global finance capital. What Renoir traces in La Règleis the fit be-
tween this machine and the machinery that a class and a community erect
for themselves.
Death before dishonor: the concept of fantasy allows us to read, within
and simultaneously with this noble sentiment, its reverse: dishonor before
death. The fear of dishonor is at the same time a fascination with it. The no-
bility’s obsession with distinction is at the same time an emblem of their fas-
cination with the indistinct, the amorphous, the unformed, the indifferent.
| 156 |
C
h
ap
te
r
6
|
But it would be wrong therefore to read the paranoid machines of defense
against homosexuality as masks for a “real” longing for it, most of all in a
film that foregrounds its anonymous homosexual character and his desire.
Instead what the disavowal of homosexuality holds for us to apprehend is
not an aspiration to same-sex desire but its sublimation as an unnameable
yearning for democracy, envisioned as a loss of distinction and an embrace
of the vulgar, longed for as much as it is held at bay. In this way the simulta-
neous acceptance and disavowal of gay love enacts not so much a fear of
homosexuality as a horror of indifferentiation, a loss of difference that looks
forward to the anonymity of a far more powerful paranoid machine—global
capital. Unnamed, his desire at once remarked and erased in a critical act of
forgetting, the homosexual is as near as 1939 would permit to a depiction of
the universal subject of ideology.
To construct a reality does not entail abandoning the world. It is to ac-
cept the necessity of construction and nonetheless to seize the opportunity
to construct. Just as the work of cultural production must, under existing
circumstances, pass through a stage of individualist subjectivity, so any ac-
count of the world, under existing conditions, must go through a stage of
rendering it as object, even at the cost of objectifying it, even at the cost of
the kind of objectification suffered by Fanon (1968: 77), the “objection” that
precedes the abjection of the other. To stay at the level of objection is to re-
main in the domain of hate. Its opposite, construction, demands movement
through that phase, even if it will always be marked by it. “Men make their
own history... not under circumstances they themselves have chosen but
under the given and inherited circumstances with which they are directly
confronted” (Marx 1973: 146). This, after all, is the only realistic way to
proceed. To do so with honesty and honor, the conditions under which art
or history is made must be acknowledged. What is essential is that objecti-
fication and construction are avowed, as they are in Renoir’s film, especially
through the avowal of the disavowed homosexual desire that fuels the homo-
social rules as well as the consequent despair (Christine), banality (Mme. de
La Bruyère), and triviality (Lisette) of the women trapped in them. With
avowal comes Zizek’s admonition that we should throw out the baby to in-
spect the dirty bath water, jettison the purity of identity to understand the
phantasmatic symptoms and fantasia that support it (Zizek 1997: 38). At the
same time, Zizek is adamant, symptoms are often enough exactly what they
say they are: that behind the invitation to dinner may lurk a secret wish to
| 157 |
R
ea
li
s
t
F
i
lm
:
S
ou
n
d
|
share a meal. As Keith Reader observes, La Règle du jeu’s ending represents
“Not so much a conspiracy of silence as a conspiracy to take events at their
face value” (Reader 1981: 137).
In other words, the world may reveal itself to us precisely by allowing
us to see that it hides a secret, although the secret of that secret is that there
is no secret. Such is the condition, Zizek argues, of the universality of global
capital: “The horror is not the (particular living) ghost in the (dead, univer-
sal) machine, but the (dead, universal) machine in the very heart of each
(particular, living) ghost” (Zizek 1997: 45–46). Even prior to objectification,
at the moment of perception and Peircean firstness, we rely on the visibility
of the world and its audibility, the way it gives itself to us to be perceived.
What it gives, however, we also take. Realism does speak to and of the world,
and as a mode of cinema it shares with sociological, geographical, and tech-
nical discourses of the world the self-consciousness that it is a construction.
Likewise La Règle du jeuattempts not truth but adequacy. Hollywood’s (or
Dallas’s) supposed “realism” is nothing of the kind and is mistakenly so named,
for example, by MacCabe (1974; see Williams 2000). On the other hand, it
is important for the argument of this chapter and of the book as a whole that
cinema is neither debarred from acknowledging and critiquing the world
nor bound to the choice between negation and escapism. On the contrary:
that reality is an effect opens up the possibility that effects can be “real.”
The problem of cinematic realism is, on this perspective, the problem
of universality. On Hegel’s account, civil society, the object par excellence
of realism, seeks to universalize the association of human beings through
their needs; yet at the same time,
the specializationand limitationof particular work also increase, as do likewise the
dependenceand wantof the class which is tied to such work; this in turn leads to
an inability to feel and enjoy the wider freedoms, and particularly the spiritual
advantages, of civil society.... this shows that despite an excess of wealth, civil
society is not wealthy enough—i.e. its own distinct resources are not suffi-
cient—to prevent an excess of poverty and the formation of a rabble. (Hegel
1991: ¶243: 266, ¶245: 267)
It is in reference to this sense of the ineluctable dialectic of civil society that
Zizek proposes “the leftist gesture par excellence” (Zizek 1997: 50) that
questions and attacks the existing universal on behalf of its symptom, the
| 158 |
C
h
ap
te
r
6
|
ego on behalf of the unconscious, or civil society on behalf of the degraded,
oppressed, and repressed. For Renoir we might enumerate these symptoms
as art, love, homosexuality, and the local, each of which is shown to be im-
possible to maintain in the face of the rules that function here as the visible
form of the universal.
As Dudley Andrew points out, this apparently liberal set of concerns
emerged from Renoir’s and the French cinema’s disillusionment with the
leftist Popular Front (Andrew 1995: 304–317), when, with films like Les Bas-
Fondsand Toni,Renoir had worked from naturalist models in scripts worked
up respectively from Gorky and a newspaper story. The immediate so-
cial and specifically proletarian concerns of those films gave way first to a
darker prognostication in La Bête Humaine,and then to far more pessimis-
tichandling of wider, “human” themes in La Grande Illusionand La Règle.
Nonetheless, even though these marginalized symptoms are less socially
specific, they are still historically particular, and as with Eisenstein, we have
to recognize the importance of the date. The year 1939 was not a good one
for optimism, revolutionary or humanist. If Eisenstein was correct to warn
against Nazi invasion, surely Renoir was right to warn against fatalism and
collaborationism on the eve of Vichy.
The question remains, what perspective might make it possible to speak
in this way? What position—political, ethical, aesthetic—authorizes a dis-
course of emancipation? Zizek’s answer is that the necessity of emancipa-
tion can be spoken only from the position of its realization, that is, from the
position of another universal, but one that does not yet exist. For Renoir, af-
ter the failure of the Popular Front and the defeat of Spain, alert to the
readiness of the French governing classes to accede to fascist rule, that par-
ticular universal could not be trusted. In films of the Popular Front period,
Renoir did indeed appeal to that not-yet universal emancipation, for
instance, as the justification for the murder in Le Crime de M. Lange. The
tragedy of La Règle derives from the way in which emancipation has lost its
credibility, and in its place the final standpoint of ethics is situated instead
inthat other indefinitely postponed but ineluctable truth, mortality.
| 159 |
R
ea
li
s
t
F
i
lm
:
S
ou
n
d
|
There is much less than meets the eye.
—Martha Wolfenstein and Nathan Leites1
Evolution as Norm
Nevsky’s simultaneous evocation and denial of infinity and La Règle’s attempt
to unify a fragmenting world under the empty sign of death were both made
in the shadow of war. In the United States, interventionist economic policy
after the stock market crash of 1929 and a steadily tightening grasp on Pacific
trade seemed to foreshadow the country’s future wealth and power. Rather
than Eisenstein’s project of national unity or Renoir’s pained account of so-
cial stagnation, Hollywood was trying, in the later 1930s, to image success.
At its apogee, success was the official ideology that powered such ex-
travagant carnivals of technological optimism as the 1939 New York World’s
Fair. Far from consolidating the techniques of the 1920s, the studio system,
more powerful and more stable than ever, proliferated stylistic responses to
the new conditions. Some studios did achieve something akin to a stable
house style. The characteristic sound libraries built up by individual studios
clearly marked their products with an authorial stamp. But whereas Warn-
ers’ low-key lighting, Spartan contemporary mise-en-scènes, and hard-
boiled scripts might unify the studio’s product, there is no confusing the last
scenes of their Little Caesarand Dames.Though RKO is often pointed out
as uncharacteristic in that there was no single genre or stylistic language that
singled out its product, its lack of house style and apparent disinterest in
searching for one is typical of classicism. Aside from the Astaire-Rodgers
musicals and the Val Lewton horror cycle, the studio that opened the decade
7
CLASSICAL FILM: DIALOGUE
Sound, Image, and Effects at RKO
| |
with Oscars for the epic western Cimarronand kicked off the next with Cit-
izen Kanewould leave behind a catalog of disparate, apparently incompat-
ible films. Yet if no formulaic norm is palpable across all genres through the
decade, nonetheless there is a strange attractor around which the films of
RKO gravitate. The films examined here should be taken as exemplary of a
centripetal but never centralized stylistic corpus, in a process of evolution
but without a teleological goal.
Classicism is curiously less stable than realism or total film. It does not
“emerge from” and “move toward,” but restlessly adapts to real and imag-
ined environmental changes, lacking the sense of mission that guided the
development of total and realist cinema. The challenge of the classical norm
is to trace the evolution of an object that seems to have no history. Though
there are clear changes from the early to the late 1930s, some later films
maintain techniques of staging, dialogue, cutting, and sound recording from
the earliest years, while others reach backward into the silent era (most ob-
viously Chaplin’s late silent features, but also the curiously wooden direction
of Mae West’s films for Paramount), forward to postwar styles (one thinks
here of the cinematographers James Wong Howe and Greg Toland), and
outward to the arthouse movies of Europe (not surprising among émigrés
like Lubitsch and Sternberg). Nor should we be distracted by the apparent
formal perfection of some of the finest films of the decade, which represent
only momentary crystallizations of the flux.
If, as Tynianov argues, “social life enters into correlation with literature
above all through its verbal aspect” (Tynianov 1965: 131), then it enters into
the moving image media under a triple aspect: the visual, the aural, and the
written. Films enact rather than depict social change, especially the swift
| 161 |
C
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
D
ia
lo
gu
e
|
evolution of media and communications technologies. By the time the sync-
sound film arrived in the late 1920s, it had to mark its position not simply in
relation to silent film, nor to a by now nostalgically reconstructed “natural”
hearing, but to recorded sound, telephony, and radio. Indeed the social his-
tory of sound in the cinema can be charted primarily not by its relationship
to a unified and hypostatized sense of hearing, but by its relationships to
other aural media. As Benjamin (1969) suggested, Zielinski (1999) argues,
and Crafton (1997) demonstrates, the mature classical sound film of the
North American studio system is the product of the first dramatic synthesis
of electronic and photomechanical industries. Brought on by the crisis of
the Wall Street Crash, itself partly precipitated by the overvaluation of radio
stocks, the standardized, industrialized sound film, we could say, is the prod-
uct of the first media-inspired global economic crisis, and one that intro-
duces media crisis as a permanent state of affairs, from the instigating role
of cinema in King Kongto the threat of printing in The Hunchback of Notre
Dameand the vulnerability of the telegraph in Gunga Din.It is this sense of
crisis that informs the concept of criticism in the 1930s and provides us with
a means for entering the critical spaces of the classical film, and for under-
standing their ongoing crisis as the basis not of a static norm but of a forced
evolution.
RKO’s task in the 1930s was to make new objects, to be ahead of the
crowd while still in touch with them. It wanted to change cinema, not the
world. RKO, like Hollywood in general, inherited a rapidly evolving con-
sumer in the wake of the Jazz Age and the Depression, but it was happier fol-
lowing trends than assuming ideological leadership. Sharing Shklovsky’s
attack on habitual perception (Shklovsky 1965: 83) but without his revolu-
tionism, RKO entrusted the aesthetic object with the task of freeing an oth-
erwise unaltered subject for the enjoyment of new perceptual routines.
Shklovsky associated shock with revolution: RKO associated it with inno-
vation, the normal functioning of cultural capitalism. Neither Shklovsky nor
RKO sought return to primal firstness: both wanted to create something
new, Shklovsky a future, RKO a present marked as modern by its difference
from the past.
The evolution of the classical norm in Hollywood, its constant recon-
figuration around the ideologically and technologically new, is not without
a teleology. Turned to face toward the vanishing past from which it must, as
innovative, distinguish itself, what it specifically lacks is an eschatology, a
| 162 |
C
h
ap
te
r
7
|
principle of hope. Evolution in the classical norm is homeostatic: it seeks an
impossible equilibrium. The unformed forms of RKO are exceptionally re-
vealing of the flexibility, the purposiveness, and the final lack of ambition
that characterize classicism in the cinema.
A Superficial Cinema
By 1931, as Wesley Ruggles’s Cimarrondemonstrates, Hollywood’s sound
films were already capable of a richness and power equal to that of the late
silents. Sync sound came not as an adjunct to the naturalistic creation of
fictional worlds but as a technological spectacle, so it is no surprise to find
other spectacular techniques associated with it. Formed out of the combined
strengths of the Film Booking Office (a small studio established by Joseph
Kennedy) together with RCA (the radio division of General Electric) and
the Keith-Albee-Orpheum chain, prime sites for film release in major cities,
Radio-Keith-Orpheum had interests in telephones and telegraphy, music
publishing and recording, the vaudeville circuit, and the NBC chain of radio
stations. Not surprisingly, the company turned to the musical.2
Flying Down to Riois now mainly remembered by buffs as the first screen
pairing of Fred Astaire and Ginger Rogers, and by historians of style for the
extraordinarily elaborate wipes—designed by house optical-printing expert
Linwood Dunn—that punctuate the film. Both the wipes and the airborne
finale testify to the association of recorded sound with spectacle, an associ-
ation that extends beyond the musical genre to the soundtrack of the studio’s
big hit of the 1933 season, King Kong.Flying’s most elaborate dance number
is the Carioca, and one can imagine RKO’s flagship theater, the 6200-seat
Radio City Music Hall, opened in 1932, encouraging visitors to take it up
as the latest dance craze. So unafraid is the film of cross-publicizing the cor-
porations’ products that two lengthy shots hold, in full frame, telegraph
forms marked “RCA Communications Radiogram—Worldwide Radio” for
the audience to memorize. The clarity and technological achievement of
the Photophone system of variable-area sound-on-film recording unique to
RCA/RKO was a further enticement to respect the corporation’s other
products, associated throughout, from the radio tower logo to the aerobatic
visuals and the streamlined architecture of the Rio de Janeiro sets, with all
that is most modern.
What after all was more modern than the latest Hollywood film? And yet
nothing could be so idiosyncratic. Take for example the famed symmetries
| 163 |
C
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
D
ia
lo
gu
e
|
of classicism; the gunfighter who rides into town in scene one and rides out
in the final shot; the door that opens under the titles and closes under the
credits (Bellour 1975a). Or the economy of means: the gun in the drawer is
always fired, and the gangster dies mumbling the catchphrase with which he
first introduced himself. Moreover, classical Hollywood is, as David Bord-
well points out, “an excessively obvious cinema” (Bordwell, Staiger, and
Thompson 1985: 3). Never overestimating its audience, the classical film
tells us everything three times at least (image, sound effect, dialogue). It is
obvious also in the sense that it withholds nothing. With the end of the silent
era, the secret voices of the stars were no longer locked in the inner ears of
their fans: radio and synchronization brought them out of the realms of mys-
tery. In the crisis year of 1929, which for Jean Baudrillard (1994) marks the
day on which history’s door closes and the era of simulation begins, the con-
version of sound into light through the miracle of electricity ends the depth
model of classicism, and a new art of the surface emerges.
The comedians, especially stone-faced Buster Keaton, had already un-
derstood that genuine silence, rather than the absence of sound, produced
the pure presence of the gag. The double negation that abolished the silent
voice was intended to generate the absolute presence of the film to itself and
thus to its audiences. No longer required to fill the gaps, the spectator be-
come audience would henceforth be saturated in film. For once the word
film lived up to its second, chemical meaning. Rather than produce a cin-
ema of depth and rounded presence, the economic imperatives of the De-
pression ensured that the classical film would come to its apogee without
fullness, a cinema of the superficial. The cost of speed—in production, in
distribution, most of all in consumption—was that the film itself would be
so superficial that it could not remain in circulation, but must flitter off the
screen to make way for the next production, and the next. Today, films take
on postcinematic lives on television, cable, video, and DVD, and so live
longer than the time it takes to make them, with important implications for
their stylistics. But in the heyday of the Hollywood system, production was
long and distribution mercilessly short. To exist in the arc light for those few
burning hours lent the films something of their passionate innocence, their
innocent criminality, the ease with which they evoked and dismissed pov-
erty, disease, prostitution, addiction, and shame. Where Eisenstein sought
to rouse in the name of the nation and Renoir bowed to the preeminence of
the world, Hollywood had nothing to present but its own illusion. Its only
| 164 |
C
h
ap
te
r
7
|
value, the ground of its existence, was entertainment. Hence the mayfly bril-
liance of its films; hence their mayfly-brief life.
Given the pressures of a system designed to convert loans into product
and product into profit on the shortest possible turnaround, and given the
demands of “feeding the maw of exhibition” (Balio 1995: 73), to the pro-
ducers and craftspeople of RKO, production schedules must have seemed at
once incredibly rushed and yet unbearably slow. The need to ensure rea-
sonable quality in at least a proportion of the studio’s output was essential to
give RKO a decent brand identity on the intensely competitive screens of
the domestic market. Scripts were the guiding structural implement in pro-
duction schedules. Not only the source of narrative (and the book of the
musicals of their songs and dances), they were the key tool in allocating re-
sources, finance, and studio time to productions. Moreover, alongside the
visual cues deployed to keep the star in the center of attention, the clarity of
their dialogue was perceived as crucial in getting and keeping the audience’s
attention.
The classical soundtrack thus redoubles common characteristics of the
classical system. Voices, singing or speaking, are directed toward the reve-
lation of character and the furtherance of a causally based narrative. Natu-
ralism is subordinated to clarity, as when music is reduced in volume to allow
us to eavesdrop on conversations. Except for ensemble singing and general
crowd noise, there are never two voices raised at the same time. Continuity
errors resulting from the use of multiple camera setups (for example, in the
Carioca sequence in Flying Down to Rio, when we can see the bandleader
climbing up steps in the background that we have already seen him climb in
the previous shot) are carried by the continuity of the music. As McLuhan
observes, “The movie audience, like the book reader, accepts mere sequence
as rational” (McLuhan 1964: 304). Shot/reverse shot structures respect the
rule that the camera stays on the speaker rather than the listener. Occasion-
ally, earlier techniques are audible, for example, the voices in a long shot of
the chorus line at the airfield that grow louder on the cut to midshot (added
reverberation had already become the more frequent option for suggesting
distance).
But the film is also vividly artificial, as in so many classical films where
naturalism is subordinated to drama. In The Public Enemy, Wyler was cut-
ting on sound cues and using exaggerated amplification to gain effective
shocks from the gunfire that kills Cagney/Tom Powers: the film is as much
| 165 |
C
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
D
ia
lo
gu
e
|
melodrama as gangster film in its reliance on heightened emotional effect
in addition to the documentary realism of the opening montage. King Kong
was to do something similar with the famous screams of Fay Wray (perhaps
also showing off the response of the Photophone system in the problematic
high frequency range). For the duet “Orchids in the Moonlight” in Flying,
the back projection (again a hot property at RKO that year) goes into over-
drive, racing through a montage of landscapes as the (soon to be ex-) lovers
croon, the shots separated by flamboyant wipes. The back projection in
many shots in the aerial “Flying Down to Rio” finale is, in a similar way, un-
done by the unlikely audibility of the music from the wings of the aircraft
carrying the chorus line while the planes’ motors remain dim murmurs for
the onscreen as well as the offscreen audience.
It is unlikely that the film is deliberately poorly made, or that the RKO
crews were incapable of a more exacting verisimilitude. The film rejoices in
its artifice, celebrates the technology of sound as it does those of aviation
and process camera work, enjoying and humanizing the technological pro-
gress on which corporate wealth and the expected emergence of the U.S.
economy from the Depression was to ride. Much of its period charm derives
from this faith in technological solutions and in its constant efforts to
(hetero)eroticize the airplane. Less lovable is the triumph of Hollywood
modernity over Brazilian tradition (posed as true love versus arranged mar-
riage, freewheeling Yanks versus stuffy authoritarians) and its echo in the vic-
tory of jazz over Latin music. But even these reservations falter before the
power of the classical paradigm, in which music is used to overwhelm any
problems of narration, continuity, probability, naturalism—or imperialism.
The triumph of music so frequent in song-and-dance films (not only
Astaire but the Brazilian police can’t help tapping their feet and swaying to
the band) is an apt allegory for the way in which the soundtrack, far from
being a “mere” supplement to the cinema’s primary visual focus, is an or-
chestration of dialogue, ambience, sound effects, music, song and silence,
and not uniquely in the musical. Altman (1992) and Williams (1980) both
argue that recorded sound doesn’t reproduce a real world: it represents it.
But the Hollywood soundtrack doesn’t even represent the world: it orches-
trates a diegesis. The difference is that between the semiotic manipulation
of recording that nonetheless is grounded in an autonomous world, and the
construction or composition of a sound world that exists autonomously of
| 166 |
C
h
ap
te
r
7
|
any profilmic world. The classical soundtrack is as self-consciously fictional
and artificial as back-projection and optical mattes.
Some critics (among them Baudry 1976; Doane 1980a,b; Neale 1985)
argue that the classical soundtrack exists to reinforce an “ideology of pres-
ence.” Matching recorded dialogue to lip-movements, sound effects to their
apparent causes, is intended to give an audience the most powerful possible
illusion of the “real” presence of the characters, or possibly the stars who
play them. It is also the guarantee of the fullness of the filmic world, per-
suading us of the completeness and coherence of the fiction. And finally, it
fulfills the fantastic desire of audiences to enter into that world as transcen-
dental subjects, given, for the duration, a subjective position rendered ab-
solute in its synchronization with the married sound and image. As Altman
(1980) argues, sound completes the illusion begun by the vision track, their
interaction hiding the fact that both are artificial constructs. I would argue
that this tells only part of the story. When Astaire walks through the Avia-
tors’ Club expecting to be thrown out at any minute, his monologue is as
clearly directed at the audience as any Shakespearian soliloquy, and punc-
tures as rapidly any sense of the autonomy of the fictional world from the
audience’s (see Lastra 2000: 214–215). This is one more example of the clas-
sical norm’s relationship with the social: not representational but relational.
Voice-over and on-camera direct address, soundtrack gags using effects or
signature tunes, nightclub sequences and ironic commentary by the sound
on the image (and vice versa) are as common in thrillers, westerns, and
women’s films as they are in the full-blown musical. The classical paradigm
succeeds not simply by commitment to the illusion of presence, but by play-
ing on the techniques that make that illusion possible. Because it not only is
spectacular but needs to advertise itself as spectacle, what distinguishes clas-
sical from total and realist cinema is its construction of a brilliant but depth-
less surface.
The triumph of self-proclaiming illusion over the ethical claims of real-
ist and total cinema is not without its repercussions on the nature of the il-
lusion itself. As RKO’s set and prop designers, optical effects technicians,
animators, and performers strove to foreground the techniques of illusion
while propagating a fictive diegesis, the first effect of the effects work is that
of making the illusion obvious. What RKO’s A features present is not absence
so much as surfaces; but where the surfaces are themselves foregrounded
| 167 |
C
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
D
ia
lo
gu
e
|
effects, they become signifiers of illusion rather than illusory. Thus the mo-
bilization of fantasy in the classical cinema does not depend on the absent
object of desire but on the present signifier of fantasy. In this way fantasy
itself approaches the symbolic, embodied there as the flashing feet, the roar-
ing beast, the hunchback swinging on his bells between horror and melo-
drama, a signifier with, at best, only a fantastic relation to its signified.
The question of being cannot therefore be posed directly of classical
film, nor can it be rephrased as a dialectical or deconstructive reversal be-
tween presence and absence. As spectacle, the classical film is literally a
surface, a border between presence and absence. Without either a concept
(Eisenstein’s “idea”) or a world to act as referent, classicism cannot pose it-
self as the heir of an object that is absent. Since its only external referent is
the script, and since it so boldly proclaims itself as fantasy, the classical film
cannot lay claim to presence either. The power of classical cinema to evoke
fantasy derives from this ambivalent position. To understand its ramifica-
tions, we need to ask: whose is this fantasy?
Distinguishing between cinematic and electronic images, Vivian
Sobchack writes that there is no point of view in the cinema, but that instead
films provide concrete “situations of viewing” in which the subjective nature
of visuality and the objective nature of visibility are brought into synthesis.
“Cinematic presence,” she writes,
is multiply located—simultaneously displacing itself in the There of past and
future situations yet orienting these displacements from the Here where the
body at present is. That is, as the multiplicity and discontinuity of time are syn-
thesized and centered and cohere as the experienceof a specific lived-body, so are
multiple and discontiguous spaces synopsized and located in the spatial synthe-
sis of a particular material body. Articulated as separate shots and scenes, dis-
contiguous spaces and discontinuous times are synthetically gathered together
in a coherence that is the cinematic lived-body: the camera is its perceptive
organ, the projector its expressive organ, the screen its discreet and material
center. (1994: 99)
Sobchack’s task, in this (1994) essay, is to define the cinematic over against
the electronic image, and her tactic is to emphasize the analogical nature of
the filmic image, its transmission as whole frames (rather than atomized pix-
els), its wholeness. In the phenomenological tradition, she emphasizes the
| 168 |
C
h
ap
te
r
7
|
relation between film, perception, and the lived body of human experience.
What distinguishes cinematic from unmediated perception for her is the
machine ensemble that shifts us from point of view to situated, synthesized
experience. Film theory frequently takes for granted that point-of-view shots
are points of identification, in which the camera, by taking the position of a
protagonist, can offer us the opportunity of seeing with their eyes. Sob-
chack’s point, or a part of it, is that we never see with any other than ourown
eyes save when we see through the eyes of the cinematic apparatus itself.
Writing from Metz’s “upstream” position, Sobchack does not need
todistinguish between modes of film and the consequent constitution of
differential lived-bodies. In distinguishing the normative cinemas of the
1930s, what is at stake are modes of wholeness. Eisenstein constructs a cy-
borg whose central constitutive factor is the semantic concept, whereas
Renoir’s wholeness is brought about through the unification of multiplicity
under the sign of mortality. Classicism, bereft of these means, has only the
wholeness of its illusion. Thus the importance to classicism of the seamless
fabric, the integral surface, of film’s body, the body without orifices. There
is no body here to penetrate, no reality to be laid bare, no concept to reveal
itself, but only an ideal glassy smoothness, the gaze of a lens rather than an
eye, the sheen of the screen rather than a Cartesian space.
Cary Grant’s sergeant in Gunga Din(fig. 7.1)has been captured by the
thugees while trying to steal their gold. His two comrades in arms (Victor
McLaglen, Douglas Fairbanks, Jr.), accompanied by Gunga Din (Sam Jaffe),
rescue him. Din accompanies Grant from the torture dungeon to the top of
the temple tower where the other sergeants are secluded with their prisoner,
the evil guru of the thugees (Eduardo Cianelli). The interior set is lit from
below, without obvious explanation—the light would have to come from
the snake pit. Shot two shows an exterior set under Californian sunlight.
Shots ring out and Grant dives for cover. The third shot of the sequence is
a reaction shot to an as yet unseen spectacle, revealed in the next shot: the
golden bas-reliefs of vaguely Hindu deities cladding the temple’s central
pagoda. The following shot returns to Grant’s reaction, reframing as he
stands and strides over to the gold. Shot five reprises shot two as the others
warn him to get down; shot six reprises the last framing of shot four, with
Grant declaring that “one golden hand is worth three thousand quid.” As
shots ring out, Grant dives off-frame left. We cut to a reprise of shots two
and five as the three sergeants, Din, and the guru fade to black. The next
| 169 |
C
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
D
ia
lo
gu
e
|
shot is a long shot of the temple set at night. Cross fade to the guru in lotus
position, frowning. Cross fade to the three sergeants in midshot, slumped
against the parapet. Cross fade to dawn rising in a reverse view from the top
of the temple, looking down into the valley where the next sequence will be
focused.
The sequence pushes the narrative one step further along (our heroes
once again in peril) but the theme of the sequence is waiting. The three ser-
geants form a unit already familiar not only from the source material, Kip-
ling’s poems and short stories, but from Ford’s cavalry films and especially
McLaglen’s well-established persona. But here the dynamic of the sergeants’
narrative (keeping Fairbanks in the army by fair means or foul) is in abey-
ance (he has been tricked into remaining). The sergeants are stranded, but
the guru is meditative in the stereotypically evil way available only to actors
in blackface. Din’s reaction is notably lacking, since he must perform the
self-sacrifice called for by the film’s evocation of Kipling in the next act. The
| 170 |
C
h
ap
te
r
7
|
| Figure 7.1 |
Gunga Din:heroic bonding of the white male, Gunga Din almost literally underfoot. Courtesy BFI Collections.
continuity editing system unifies the manifestly separate spaces of interior
set, exterior set, and miniature of the temple in its landscape. The edits work
not by cutting but by elision, most obviously in the cross-fades signifying
time ellipses. The gaze that is incited here is not invited to work its way into
the temple or into the experience of tedium and anticipation, but to move,
almost like Eisenstein’s graphical vector, horizontally, glossing over the in-
terstices, spatial and temporal, slipping along the narrative axis, evacuat-
ing space and bracketing time. The film has to produce the knowledge of
boredom—the awareness of time passing—without producing it as affect.
Repetition stands in for duration, and the ability to wait is associated with
the antagonist. Spatial and temporal difference, then, substitute for diegetic
continuity and spatial depth.
The camera perceives action fragmented in space and time. Among the
RKO films we are dealing with, that fragmentation also occurs within single
frames, as during wipes or in complex matte, rear-projection, and model-
animation sequences. Nonetheless, Sobchack is correct to say that these
images come across as whole, since they are the objects of a synthesizing
process of camera, projector, and screen (and also optical printers, effects
studios and editing desks, music, sync and dubbed sound recording, mixing
and editing). This whole machinery exists to synthesize, prior to the mo-
ment of reception. To some extent, then, we can argue that any answer to
the question “whose fantasy?” would have to include the response that it
belongs to that articulating system of perception which is the studio, and
which we have been generalizing as the cinematic apparatus.
We can infer from the multiplying elements making up the apparatus
that this fantasy is, however, not immediate. The act of perception under-
taken by the cinematic machine, in this instance the RKO studio, takes time
because it is synthetic. Mechanical perception may be imagined as instanta-
neous in a society whose dominant medium is the clock and whose concep-
tion of time is one of a succession of discrete instants. But in the 1930s, when
time is beginning to be thought of as a dimension, the sense of the moving
image as a time-based experience and a time-consuming perception is far
more familiar. We have therefore to ask a supplementary question: when is
the fantasy? Answering will evoke the familiar paradox of loss: fantasy is
present only as a retrospective gestalt after the experience itself is over, mov-
ing us directly to the idea of cinema as becoming. The specific, material cir-
cumstances of RKO classicism in the 1930s, consonant with Sobchack’s
| 171 |
C
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
D
ia
lo
gu
e
|
insistence on the specificity and materiality of experience, suggests that it is
in the cinema building that the films achieve their one moment of presence,
and that that presence depends on the audience not just economically but
for its very being (or its very becoming).
An audience is an audience only by dint of attending the screening, an
activity that implies an isomorphism between projection and “audiencing,”
at the very least in terms of the time taken, but in the case of successful films,
one presumes, also in terms of the relation between physical stages of the
audiovisual performance and physiological-psychological states of the audi-
ence. The cinematic signifier is present only on condition that it is tempo-
rary. Films mutate before our eyes and ears. They become other. And it is
this state of restless instability that tells us we are in the presence of a film—
the fact that it synthesizes through such nonnatural processes as editing
makes it clear we are not replicating a mooted presocial perception. On the
contrary, we are actively involved in the synthesis, ourselves elements of the
cinematic machine. The bizarre dialectic of classicism has to do not with ab-
sence but with the attempt to square the circle of being and becoming. The
question “when is fantasy?” opens the question as to whether the distinction
between being and becoming is adequate to classicism, and it sends the mes-
sage that what is distinctive is not the relation to being—since we are deal-
ing with fantasy—but the way in which the classical cinema produces as its
result neither meaning (idea, image) nor reference, Peircean thirdness or
secondness, but firstness, a contrahistorical regression that is not quite the
presubjective moment of identification noted by Mulvey (1976), but the
preobjective proper to a fantasmagoric cinema, a cinema of surface.
The Event Horizon
Among his Weimar period essays, we find Siegfried Kracauer noting conti-
guities between the Hollywood dream factory and the Ufa studio system.
“Here [the Ufa Studios at Neubabelsberg, near Berlin, 1926] all objects are
only what they are supposed to represent at the moment: they know no de-
velopment over time” (“Calico-World,” Kracauer 1995: 283). He completes
the thought two years later: “Lack of substance is the decisive trait of the
totality of established film production” (“Film 1928,” ibid.: 319). “It almost
seems as if, with the increasing perfection of photographic technique, the
object that this medium is meant to convey disappears,” he argues in the
| 172 |
C
h
ap
te
r
7
|
same essay (ibid.: 314). Prefiguring the author’s later New York–period faith
in the mission of cinema to redeem reality, it is the objectthat is in danger of
disappearance, rather than the world as such, the object that loses its depth,
its substance, and specifically its temporality in the established cinema. The
art of the propmaker and set designer has overtaken the candid account of
nature and therefore fails to give a radical account of the objectivity of so-
cial reality. Key to the mastery over nature by the erasure of nature, and thus
to the ideological functioning of films, is the symptomatic inability of com-
mercial cinema and its institutional dependents in art and documentary to
confront objects in their temporality, that temporality that gives them a
place in the world and a meaning.
For Kracauer, Hollywood in the 1930s successfully constructs a zone
outside of time. The films made at RKO attempt to make cinema an atem-
poral field but, contra Kracauer, the effort is never wholly achieved. The
scene analysis from Gunga Dinindicates a negotiation with time, not its
complete erasure. Like Flying Down to Rio, the film struggles to raise and
dispel the specter of change, historicity, and difference, on the one hand by
nominating the atemporal as specifically modern, on the other by displac-
ing modernity into the future as a goal to be achieved. Classicism must ne-
gotiate with the disjuncture between achieved and wished-for resolutions,
between the present as eternal and the fact that the actually existing present
is not that eternity, but a trajectory toward it. The gap between what classi-
cism longs for and what it actually delivers makes classicism aspirational. It
is a machine that acts systemically to reflect and reproduce the desire of its
audience and its makers. Yet it is not simply a passive channel communicat-
ing between makers and audiences: it is an active participant in the processes
of mediation. It is itself a desiring agent.
When Deleuze addresses “the intense world of differences,” he invites
us to prize open the relation of difference in the spirit of “a superior em-
piricism” (Deleuze 1994: 57). This empiricism is of a rather unfamiliar
brand. Film theorists of the 1970s argued that empiricism failed to recog-
nize the ideological constitution of facts. But in the late 1960s, empirical
philosophy was exploring just this nexus. Like Willard Van Orman Quine,3
Deleuze envisages an empiricism that confronts the world not through the
imposition of categorical thinking and the philosophy of identity that under-
pins nineteenth-century empiricism, but in a mood that might almost be
| 173 |
C
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
D
ia
lo
gu
e
|
called subjunctive: a frame of reference that does not presuppose that the
world exists as object or objects, nor that objects and their behaviors can be
constituted as facts, but in which facticity depends on differentiation.
In the cinema, the relation of difference is clearly one of mediation, the
material in which difference signifies, the material relation between people
that takes on the form of the film. A near contemporary of Deleuze, Quine
quotes approvingly Dewey’s (1925) statement: “Language is specifically a
mode of interaction of at least two beings, a speaker and a hearer; it presup-
poses an organized group to which these creatures belong and from whom
they have acquired their habits of speech. It is therefore a relationship.” How
much more true this is of the Hollywood studio cinema of the 1930s, a ma-
teriality of communication, a mediation, in which hundreds were involved
in both production and reception. The “unimagined pattern beyond indi-
viduation” (Quine 1969: 24) is the dominant special effect of classical cin-
ema in the 1930s. It disarranges the categorical and even the one-to-one
ethical aesthetics of communication as previously conceived, and as practi-
cally effected in the telegraph, telephone, book, magazine, domestic photo-
graph, peep show, and phonograph parlor. The mass entertainments of the
sound cinema in North America realized the new empiricist conception of
socialized, nonobjective communication thirty years before the oddly syn-
chronous statements of Quine and Deleuze.
Deleuze’s philosophy departs from North American empiricism, how-
ever, in foregrounding the politics of desire. This concept drives him toward
prioritizing pleasures, intensities of sensation. What should surprise us is
not that we have had to wait so long for such an insight, but that this is the
very mythos of King Kong, Schoedsack and Cooper’s noble savage. Kong’s
microsexuality, to borrow another of Deleuze’s terms, is a parable of desire
and its fatality, the fatality of beauty. Kong after all is a dark and savage god
on a despotic island translated by special effects (and the alibi of the fantas-
tic journey) into the libidinal economy of Manhattan. His sex organs are his
hands (fig. 7.2), a threatening rewriting of the alluring, elegant gestures
of Astaire’s slim, white fingers. These hands are themselves the artifacts
andthe signifiers of the craftsman-engineer whose fingers have formed and
fondled the otherwise incomprehensibly ruffling fur, trace of the man-
handling the Kong model has undergone in the paws of his makers (Gold-
ner and Turner 1975) and which they have made him express in the sensual
| 174 |
C
h
ap
te
r
7
|
image of Fay Wray cupped in his palm (Gottesman and Geduld 1976; Wray
1989). The lasting delight in King Kong, the wealth of pop-cultural appro-
priations and vanguardist art expropriations the film has spawned (see Erb
1998), hang on this sublimation. After all it is Kong who wrecks the phallic
train, Kong who out-tops the pointed Pelion of the Empire State Building,
and the sublimation is therefore the product of the very opposite of repres-
sion. It is the picture of how desire finds its forbidden image in a Puritan cul-
ture, in the “African” exotic superstud who, however, has the whole world
not in his sexual possession but in his hands.
Like the meaningless clatter of Astaire’s taps, the meaningless “hubba
hubba” of the “natives” mimes the failure of repression to achieve its only
| 175 |
C
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
D
ia
lo
gu
e
|
| Figure 7.2 |
King Kong:hands as sexual organs. Courtesy BFI Collections.
task, to repress. Kong celebrates as it disavows not repression but the subli-
mation, the rendering sublime, of desire in the form of spectacle, the only
form in which the Deleuzean plentitude of desire can exist as commodity.
In Méliès, that form would present itself as void; in classicism, it begins to
present itself as plenum. At RKO in the 1930s, the fullness of desire replaces
the model of desire as lack. The yearning of the last colonial epoch changes
to become the imagined fullness of an achieved world in which the com-
modity becomes fully spectacular in the special effect, and the world’s most
powerful economy turns its back on the world to revel in its own transition
from poverty to wealth. Deleuze’s insistence on the “microhistorical,” em-
pirical specificity of individual events gives us access to a dimension that
Kracauer’s (and Metz’s) “upstream” positions disallow.4 Most of all, the
microhistorical gives us a way of understanding how not just cinema but
specific films can become desiring machines. It can also help us understand
that the desire of a machine is as historical as the desire of a human being.
For Kracauer, cinema “wants” to reveal objects in their fullness, but current
productions are merely superficial. What Deleuze allows us to conceptual-
ize is that these films of the 1930s “want,” desire, the surface, want exactly
the film, the sheen, the meniscus that lies between fullness and nonexis-
tence. They have their own desire, and it is fundamentally fetishistic, not
least because these films usher in the era of the commodity as spectacle.
In the Hollywood spectacular of the 1930s, the microhistories of cine-
matic desire run permutations of the spectacle as the specific, material me-
diation of the commodity sublime in the form of visualized desire. In a brief,
powerful analysis, Roger Dadoun captures the chronology of the fetish in
King Kong: the stolen apple of the opening scene a focus for interaction;
thecommoditized scream aboard ship; the islanders’ fetishization of Kong,
mirrored in the bourgeois audience’s fetishization of the spectacle in the
New York theater; and the final sequence proclaiming that “the Beast, fear
and fantasy cannot with impunity be treated as things” (Dadoun 1989: 46).
That spectacle should be articulated with the powers of artifice, especially
the handcraft of special effects, is part of that history. Hands—Kong’s gentle-
ness, Astaire’s long fingers and suave gesturing, Laughton’s hunchback ca-
ressing Esmeralda’s face with his knuckles—dominate this articulation of
the patriarch. This sense of touch as a stroking movement that is never a
grasp onto solidity evokes once more the sensuality of the superficial, the
commodity fetish as spectacle. Given this context, it is almost miraculous
| 176 |
C
h
ap
te
r
7
|
that Kong is male. His tiny beloved, we can only surmise, is female accord-
ing to the patriarchal logic that renders the female body as icon of the phal-
lus, signifier of male desire.
Kong has become an art deco artifact. Stripped of his gargantuan power
to mediate by the very multiplication of his admirers’ acts of symbolization,
Kong has become the merest signifier. We feel no fear or awe in his pres-
ence now, but only recognize that he “means” fearfulness and awe. Because
his massive darkness was so evocative of sexuality at the time, it has become
of necessity childlike to us now: a doll holding a doll. Astaire, by contrast,
still evokes the sensuous embodiment for which the incorporeal cinematic
machine yearns. His ethereal gestures, thin face, high voice, and ability to
move on the tips of his toes between earth and air make of him an andro-
gyne in whom all desire can be rendered fantastically immaterial. His is a
sexuality not only without organs but without bodies. As we watch the tran-
sition into the “Cheek to Cheek” routine in Top Hat(fig. 7.3),Astaire sheds
in turn the act he is putting on for the narrative, the acting he is doing as star,
and the narrative functions of the dance (to resolve the relationship with
Ginger Rogers). What remains is not the truth, not, at least, some solid naked
nub of emotion or sensuality, but the pure surface denuded of its narrative
trappings and the obligatory heterosexuality of the storyline. Like Zizek’s
symptom, everything is on display: there is no repressed act hidden behind
the dance. The duration of the takes (despite the fact that Ginger kept in-
haling the feathers from her dress) and Astaire’s insistence on being filmed
full-length permit no obscuration. The desire of Top Hatis for sublimation
of the sexual act, not at all the “absent” act of love itself, which, like the
lonely hour of the last instance, never occurs. We do not want to see Fred
Astaire mount Ginger: we have come to see them dance. This sublimation
makes a cyborg of the dancers, a compound of the cinema longing for em-
bodiment, Fred and Ginger leaping to escape it.
Hereinafter, the question is no longer one of a demiurgic reality other
than the film itself, since there is no absence, nothing missing, from the full-
ness of desire in its presentation on screen. The film as spectacle is itself: it
does not require external validation. In this way, the classical cinema is
closer to the cinema of the Lumières than to that of Méliès: it seeks the sur-
face, the pure difference of movement. But the dialectic of nonidentity that
persists in destabilizing the equilibrium produces a further desire in the clas-
sical apparatus, the desire for a teleology that, as responsive to notoriously
| 177 |
C
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
D
ia
lo
gu
e
|
| 178 |
C
h
ap
te
r
7
|
| Figure 7.3 |
Top Hat:the cinema longing for embodiment, Fred and Ginger leaping to escape it. Courtesy BFI Collections.
fickle and unpredictable customers, it does not possess. In place of that goal,
and indeed in place of hope, the Hollywood machine instead displaces its
desire toward the framing and organizing of chaos. In this pursuit it turns
from depiction to narration, the ancient art of taming the difference out of
which its desire emerges. Thus in the soundtrack, the core work of the nar-
rative is to build meaning from the babble of King Kong’s islanders, Gunga
Din’s thugees, the pattering of Astaire’s taps, the roar of the aircraft in Fly-
ing Down to Rio,or the babble of the crowds in The Hunchback of Notre Dame.
The microhistory of these films, then, concerns the problem of order in
desire, and in this there does appear an externality. Where for Eisenstein
that external agency was the Idea, and for Renoir the world, at RKO it was,
as it was for all the Hollywood studios, the agency that brought order to the
narrative and accountability to the films’ production: the script. To listen
toRKO’s films of the 1930s is to hear the dialogue, illustrated by songs, il-
luminated with sound effects, underpinned with nondiegetic scores, but
nonetheless assimilated to the realization of the script as the basic function-
ing of the dialogue. Dialogue is even more important than the timbre of the
voice, especially notable in Astaire’s reedy tenor. This alone explains why,
over at Paramount, Sternberg would return to the leaden Englishman of
Blonde Venus, Herbert Marshall, for the lead male role in Shanghai Express,
as if the very lack of distinguishable vocal quality were a value worth pursu-
ing along with the lack of verisimilitude in that clipped, tight-lipped drone
of a voice.
This quality of dialogue in turn is why the monsters so affect us. Per-
haps it is Quasimodo’s deafness that most sharply delineates the centrality
of dialogue, even more than Kong’s muteness, his nonverbal expressions not
only of the throat but the pounded chest, again a language of the hands.
Clattering taps, pounding fists: the language of desire gets as far as the door-
way leading out of the prison of the script, instrument of the production of-
fice, only to emerge as the articulation of the order of the script itself, the
unvocalizable speaking of the body, antirational efflorescence of the final
and complete Word, breath and body united in the unspeakable truth of the
script’s logorrohea. Far from revealing the internal contradictions of cine-
matic modernity (Comolli and Narboni 1977: 7), these roars, syncopations,
batterings, and whimpers reveal its core—the abject as the highest aspira-
tion of the commodity form. Where Fred and Ginger’s routines establish
the classical sublime, beautiful beyond expression, Kong’s roaring establishes
| 179 |
C
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
D
ia
lo
gu
e
|
its abject, vile beyond words. The two meet in their escape from language,
and in escaping language, their position outside history.
At the opposite extreme from the sublimation of the dance, the suzer-
ainty of the inarticulate is the obvious secret of the classical cinema, the Pur-
loined Letter that never fails to reach its destination. Classical narrative
exists to mediate between the two poles of sublimity and abjection, deploy-
ing their extrahistorical, extralinguistic, nonnegotiable certainty to ensure
the stilling of turbulence. We arrive, in classicism, at cinema’s event hori-
zon, the mythic surface of a black hole where time stands still. The surface
of eternity is itself eternally superficial. The spectacular image, the spectac-
ularization of the commodity as image, and behind them the disappearance
of money into pure communication are countenanced in classicism in the
figure of the surface.
Born from the failure of the image to transcend the commodity, spec-
tacle is the triumphal imaging of the commodity as transcendent. The gro-
tesque and the irrational, the excessive, the unnecessary, the hedonistic, and,
within the lights of the time, the vile and the disgusting are evoked and even
demonstrated. They are celebrated not as qualities of the world but of the
image’s simultaneous presence and absence, and in the unreality of the
diegetic world it images. Realism anchors this spectrum of sensations within
the dialectic of presence and absence, capture and loss of the fleeting mo-
ment, that constitutes the image as effect. The total film makes poignant the
effort to realize—to make real—the Image, the idea of which each shot is a
fragmentary intuition, and the immense difficulty of that realization. But in
one thing alone the classical cinema at RKO was consistent: the lack of di-
alectic. There difference is enshrined as the unnameable, embodied exclu-
sively as image and decisively divorced from either the public sphere of
nation and people or the recovered natural perception of an external and
preexistent world. Classicism instead mobilizes fantasy, but does so in order
to satisfy it. It evokes desire to display it, to mirror desire back onto itself
and in that reflection to complete desire as a closed and narcissistic loop.
This desire is, it scarcely needs repeating, historically specific. For ex-
ample, classicism thrives on the displaced dialectic of apartheid America—
Kong, gypsy girl, hunchback. Astaire’s assimilation of African-American
vernacular dance for a Europeanized white-tie-and-tails ballet is the type
ofthe fantastic desire to overcome difference, the aspirational utopianism
annulled in the spectacular commodity. The sound-image assemblage of
| 180 |
C
h
ap
te
r
7
|
1930s Hollywood is ready at exactly the right moment to become commod-
ity capitalism’s medium of choice for at its heart lie undialectical, natural-
ized dualisms of sublime and abject, absent presence and present absence.
The sublimation of the natural into its image, and the tailoring of the image
as white, is premised on an identification of the African-American body with
nature, such that the noncinematic—nature, the body, natural perception—
can be overcome in the same political moment as the subsumption of the
“racial” other.
The commodity’s triumph is that it recruited the sync-sound movie ma-
chine of the late 1920s to its economic requirements. At the same time, the
evidence points toward a double-cross. While capital investment and con-
ventions for the management of innovation held good, the result was not
somuch the commodification of the image as the “image-ification” of the
commodity.
Bounded Energy
In tracing the post-Depression remaking of the commodity as image we
must keep in mind the bare truth that the world’s population confronted in
1929: the underpinning structure of the commodity was itself a ghostly
thing. Britain’s abandonment of the gold standard in 1926, like that of the
United States in 1981, proved that money was unanchored, reliant on the
unadministrable mass behavior of the stock markets, motivated by nothing
more tangible than confidence.
But what is confidence if not the faith that things will continue? It is the
obverse of hope, since it is in effect the belief that nothing changes. Yet
clearly, in 1929, things did change. The apparent object nature of the cen-
tral commodity, money, was unpicked, and its inner turbulence revealed in
terrible splendor. Though most accounts of the 1930s describe it as a period
of reconstruction, the Crash and the subsequent restructuring of the global
economy revealed that money was a mode of communication. If the com-
munication world is made up of all those materialities that allow us to enter
into relationships with one another, then money is a crude but massively in-
fectious communications medium, second only to weaponry in simplicity,
brutality, and effectivity. The 1930s witnessed a movement in the global
stock markets toward increasing fluidity and rapidity of trade. War too would
change into blitzkrieg, dependent on short-wave radio and reconnaissance
photography. War and finance would share a strategy in the adoption of the
| 181 |
C
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
D
ia
lo
gu
e
|
blockade as the key to victory. Stopping flows would become the key to
stabilizing situations, to bringing them under control, to a return to confi-
dence—to the minimization of change.
Meanwhile, the commodity evolved. The trade in immaterial goods,
notably radio’s trade in audiences, rose to the forefront. Itself an ephemeral
and intangible good, the cinema was at the heart of this trend, not least be-
cause of its strategic position, at RKO especially, as a node in proliferating
networks of interconnected businesses. No longer necessarily material, the
commodity was becoming an image. Brand identities, industrial design,
proliferating consumer choices, the rising use of catalog shopping all con-
tributed to the way in which commodities were becoming images of them-
selves. But the more image-based or image-conscious commodities became,
the more communicative value replaced use-value, the more they opened
themselves to the randomizing effects of the communicative environment,
in which meaning can never be fixed. The rapid growth of the advertising
industry was consequent on attempts to minimize this effect and to estab-
lish and maintain a stable identity for the image-commodity. But advertis-
ing is also mute tribute to the necessity of stabilizing and identifying, over
and over again, the flux to which all meanings and identities are subject in
this new era.
The classical system likewise seeks to remove the dialectic of presence
and absence, and so the possibility of change, by capturing the difference
between the two in a perpetual recursivity that assimilates otherness into
homeostasis. The ethic of entertainment adds the imperative to mutate in
each recursion through the pressures of innovation required by the new
commodity form. Through the structuring agency of the script, the enter-
tainment ethic services a desire characterized by circularity, fullness, and
sublimation rather than the linearity, lack, or repression of other-oriented
desire. This perpetually renewed, full desire fetishizes its newly stabilized
binaries as spectacle, sheer surface. Classicism’s commodity aesthetic is thus
fantastic, in the sense of multiple, simultaneous, and contradictory identifi-
cations across many possible gender, sexual, and subject relations (Freud
1979). Twenty-five years earlier, in Méliès’s day, the commodity form con-
cealed an emptiness. Now in the mid-1930s it embraced a plenum, but one
defined by the seamlessness of its spectacular image. Bataille’s (1988) pro-
motion of the economics of excess is itself a description of this change in the
nature of the commodity, not at all a contradiction of or an alternative to it.
| 182 |
C
h
ap
te
r
7
|
Spectacular consumption, in the form of the consumption of spectacle, is
central to the commodity aesthetic of cinematic classicism, as is the conti-
nuity between the sublime and the abject. Both serve the task of equilibrium.
Bellour’s (1974/1975, 1975b, 1977) observations of the symmetries typ-
ical of classicism are based on qualities specific to a mathematical consider-
ation of time. Narrative events can be symmetrical when they are repeated
(translated) or reflected. This is not true, however, of nonnarrative events
like walking or rain falling. Cosmology tells us that perfect symmetry ex-
isted only momentarily in the Big Bang and that evolution, causality, and
entropy depend on the broken symmetries of the first instants of the uni-
verse’s existence. In the perfectly symmetrical universe, rain rises as well as
falls (Stewart 1995: 87). In a perfectly symmetrical film, every frame is iden-
tical. Narrative depends on symmetry-breaking: ultimately, there is narra-
tive because the universe is expanding.
The Lumières’ films accept the monodirectional, asymmetric nature of
time as it exists in the actual universe, but in focusing on the nonidentical
nature of successive images, they bring us to a sense of time as pure dif-
ference. The Lumières synthesize movement. Limited to the bilateral sym-
metry of its object, animal locomotion, the earlier chronophotographers
analyzed movement into immobility: the burden of Zeno’s paradox. The
Lumières’ synthetic movement allowed them to make films of astonishing
symmetry, since they open out from the dynamic equilibrium of perpetual,
if indistinguishable, change and becoming. When classical Hollywood de-
velops this synthetic approach, what Bellour observes as symmetries are in-
stead effects of symmetry-breaking, periodic oscillations, repetitions and
reflections of space-time events. By stressing the repetition rather than the
difference, the nested symmetries of scenes, sequences, and narrative bring
difference under control by establishing patterns of movement away from
and back to equilibrium. The broken symmetry of Hollywood’s narrative
desire counters the primal difference of raw becoming with the endless rep-
etition of distinction and differentiation. Through these distinctions and
differentiations established by breaking the pure symmetry of zero, the
chaos of becoming can be bound into stability.
The fantastic in classicism is thus a moment of asymmetry, a movement
out of equilibrium that allows equilibrium not only to restate itself but also
to assert the absolute nature of its rule. In this sense narrative is a data struc-
ture. Not so much a linear curve, classical narrative is a three-dimensional
| 183 |
C
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
D
ia
lo
gu
e
|
array of space-time events. The symmetries produced by the script, and
by framing, composition, editing, and postproduction, allow us to analyze
these events three-dimensionally from a constellation of viewpoints. Spe-
cific takes and their ordering are then parsed in postproduction through a
series of reflections and translations to produce the phenomenon of the lin-
ear film. Fantasy, the multiple possible series of roles entertained in the re-
lation with the narrated events, synthesizes these permutations as either a
reconstruction of the same series of constellated viewpoints or a deconstruc-
tion that multiplies them exponentially. Though we experience the curve of
narrative inside the linear dimension of time, in the moment of the ending
when we experience it again as gestalt, we experience it as a stable data set
whose function is to ensure that all movement, and especially that of fantasy,
is finally grounded within the ontology of difference and repetition.
This suggests something akin to Eisenstein’s Image, the conceptual
structure of whose vibrations every temporal structure of the total film is an
expression. Yet there is a significant difference. The script, as the framing
and structuring form of classical cinema, is not a concept, although it may,
in some examples, mobilize a concept—as happens in King Kong.But con-
cepts themselves are assimilated within the stabilizing structuration of the
script as matrix. Thus the concept of liberty in The Hunchback of Notre Dame
is bounded by the binarisms of beauty and ugliness, repression and saintli-
ness, and presented as an achievement of the book (and by extension the
film) that is already in the audience’s past. The persuasive power, the rhetor-
ical and dialogical structure, of liberty is contained within a systemic sym-
metry that holds it in stasis, depriving it of both purposiveness and vectoral
openness. What then is the nature of time at RKO during the 1930s? What
is this containment of difference?
Difference, nonidentity, is as much a historical category as is being. To
make a loose analogy, the Lumières’ cinema is Bergsonian. It thrives on the
élan vital,the energy and the rhythms of life. But RKO is closer to the mode
of difference mooted by both Deleuze (1994) and Derrida (1976) in 1968.
For Derrida there is not Being but difference (or différance), the elemental
failure of things to be identical with themselves. As a result, objects repeat
themselves, vibrating about their internal difference, and forming a trace of
their process. For Deleuze the same process holds, but in reverse: repetition
is primordial, and things or events repeat themselves as ever-renewed copies
of an original that does not exist: the vibration of simulacra produces differ-
| 184 |
C
h
ap
te
r
7
|
ence as such and especially those differences that are presented in the Anti
Oedipus as the rhythmic pulsions of life acting on and through the body
without organs (Deleuze and Guattari 1972). Vattimo points out that
both theses, despite their avowed goal of going beyond metaphysics, are
metaphysical, not least because both depend on the metaphysical category
ofeternity—the eternal return in Deleuze, the categorical statement that
“difference is not in history” for Derrida (Vattimo 1993: 144). Vattimo’s
complaint is that the two French philosophers attempted to remove the
ontological ground of philosophical metaphysics, but ended up replacing it
with a new one: eternal repetition or eternal difference. Neither difference
nor repetition responds to history, to a specific historical conjuncture, to the
moment of classical Hollywood.
In Guy Debord’s exploration, spectacle can be seen from within as that
social regime in which images of things replace the things themselves, in the
way that brand images overtake the use-value of the things they advertise.
Seen from the outside, spectacle takes over from Marx’s production-era def-
inition of the commodity form in which human relations assume “the fan-
tastic form of a relation between things” (Marx 1976 [1867]: 164–165).
Relations between people have now taken the form of relations between im-
ages (Debord 1977: paras. 4 and 36). In the classical norm, spectacle treats
difference as if it were primordial nonidentity. It organizes it through repe-
tition—Bellour’s symmetries—into structures that provide difference with
a unified identity. Specifically, it identifies the identity of difference as non-
identity. This is the secret of the present-absence of the image. Spectacle is
the name of the nonidentical, and the image is its typical form. By imaging
it, spectacle orders nonidentity, and through repetition structures and con-
trols it as narrative and entertainment. Thus the similarity with Eisenstein’s
image: spectacle raises the nonidentical to the level of a concept. But such
aconcept cannot have a direction or a purpose, a perfect solution for the
demands of permanent innovation within the rigorous confines of the
commodity form. Moreover, this new post-1929 variant of commodifica-
tion replaces the emptiness of exchange value with the plenum of perpetual
movement. Like Bataille’s concept of the economy of excess, the Deleuze–
Derrida conception of repetition and difference does not define an alterna-
tive to the commodity form: it describes a stage in its development. Once
again, the philosophers arrive with a critical description decades after its
practical realization.
| 185 |
C
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
D
ia
lo
gu
e
|
RKO, of course, had no use for ontology. But it did produce a series of
films distinguished by the meeting of extremes, the cycling of repetitions
and symmetries, the elaboration of permutations in single scripts and across
series, and perhaps most of all by predestination and stability. The classical
narrative is linear in the sense of the broken symmetry discussed here, but
the line itself will return on itself to complete the shimmering surface of the
spectacular commodity. The pixel returns, but now governed by circularity,
a perfectly rounded zero whose perfection is an impenetrable barrier lying
between being and nonbeing, the nonidentical as the skin of the film beyond
which neither vision, desire, nor analysis will penetrate.
The normative cinemas of the 1930s are not static. If they were, they
would never have been so successful or so long-lived. Rather they offer tem-
plates into which a variety of contents can be poured, but which bound and
shape those contents in distinctive fashions. Each points to something ex-
ternal to cinema as its alibi. To some extent, the classical film is the most
purely cinematic, which is why it embraces with such conviction the aes-
thetics of the surface. Yet at the same time, it too has an allegiance beyond
itself. On the one hand, it responds with microscopic adjustments to the
fluctuating form of the commodity, of which it is itself not merely an ex-
ample but, in the 1930s, the archetype. But it is also a fantastic desiring ma-
chine, and one that operates at its peak only when it manages to reach out to
the desires of its audiences and activate them within its bounded circle of
repetition. If Eisenstein’s master is the state, and Renoir’s mistress is society,
RKO classicism is the slave of culture.
Culture is a notoriously slippery term. Since Herder, it has been shaped
by the plural form, cultures: a culture is always proper to a distinct group,
responsible for unifying them under the sign of identity. What distinguishes
the concept of culture for classicism is that it is governed not by identity but
by difference. Long before the advent of neoracism (Balibar and Waller-
stein 1991), RKO’s output in the 1930s addresses a culture marked by its in-
clusiveness, even if that inclusiveness was a matter of aspiration rather than
reality. Nonetheless, everyone is invited, though each is treated differently.
Not only the economic demand to maximize audiences and so never to
alienate a major section of them, but the aesthetic of the spectacular com-
modity addresses each audience member as discrete, distinct, individual.
We know we are addressed by a mass medium, but the medium speaks so in-
| 186 |
C
h
ap
te
r
7
|
timately that culture becomes a matter of the personal link between the
filmgoer and the screen, as if we witnessed in the cinema after 1929 a secu-
lar repetition of the arrival of protestantism, in which the mediation of the
Church was no longer needed, and the worshipers could address themselves
directly and personally to God.
The moment in which classicism individuates its audience is the mo-
ment of address. It works in quite the opposite direction to realism. Unlike
La Règle du jeu,where mortality is the leveling commonality that nonethe-
less each of us must face alone, and which thereby guarantees our individu-
ality, the spectacular mode of address at RKO speaks to us in the language
of the intimate, of dreams and desires, to persuade us to a cultural conform-
ity that otherwise has no reality. But it shares with realism, and with total
cinema, with all cinema that aspires to normativity, a specific albeit varied
temporality. The cost of becoming a norm is the sacrifice of change. In to-
tal cinema, the vector’s infinite dimensions are rendered as totality, and
inthat assumption of completion to the work of film, the dynamic is frozen
into conceptual presence. Realism seizes on ephemerality, but where the
logic of the cut once led to the endless multiplication of objects, the realist
must gather that manifold into a single presence, that of the world which,
even if it remains external to the film, alone guarantees its claim to truth.
The spectacle acts differently again. Commodity relations propose to
us that we relate to one another only through objects. The era of the spec-
tacle renews that as a relationship between images. Those images, however,
in classicism are the insubstantial dividing line between the irreconcilable
dimensions of the commodity, its presence and its absence. To achieve this
equilibrium, classicism must place all its production into the past. Most of
all, the moment of gestalt, in which the structuring of narrative time is ren-
dered retrospectively, places all the past under the sign of erasure, propelling
us into a pastless present just as it drives us to a depthless surface. This is the
magic that brings about the governance of that flux—of innovation, of fash-
ion, of desire—on which consumer capitalism and specifically the recon-
struction of the global economy of the 1930s was based. Now the apparently
irreconcilable claims of stability and change can be brought to resolution.
In each instance, as the table summarizing this section is intended to
show, the normative cinemas that crystallized in the 1930s govern time by
drawing it into the present.
| 187 |
C
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
ilm
:
D
ia
lo
gu
e
|
TOTAL FILM REALIST FILM CLASSICAL FILM
Rhetoric Reality Spectacle
State Society Culture
Inventio Elocutio Dispositio/pronunciato
Image Depiction Entertainment
Music Sound Dialogue
Idea World Script
Sublime Beautiful Spectacular
Realized present Debarred future Irretrievable past
Totalization of infinity Unification of multiplicity Equilibration of flux
During the 1940s, the powers of the studios collapsed but the unstable
classical norm remained, as did the realist and total norms. The aesthetic re-
sources of all three became available for all the others, not only fluid and
adaptable, but also porous—so much so that it makes little sense to speak of
other films as aberrations from them. Already in the 1940s, other films—
Gainsborough melodramas, for example, or the colonial cinema of India—
intermingled realist, total, and classical norms alongside other national
structuring devices. These norms, then, are neither exclusive nor absolute,
but typical of a movement through which cinema passes. Normative cine-
mas, of every kind, share the production of the present as a special effect
proper to the art. In the decades that followed, that norm of norms would
be challenged and, from the 1970s onward, begin to make way for new
modes of cinema and new temporal dimensions.
| 188 |
C
h
ap
te
r
7
|
| Part III |
Post Cinema
Slow Motion, Angel of the Odd
It is an immorality that IS America.
—William Carlos Williams1
Nostalgia for the Cinema
Peckinpah’s Westerns—The Wild Bunchand Pat Garrett and Billy the Kid
especially—are barbaric elegies, the only form of poetry available after
Auschwitz (Adorno 1967: 34), in this instance songs for a vanishing world.
The fly-blown air of heat and boredom as the films’ protagonists wait for
death is a rhapsodic portrait of the justified at a moment when not only is
the frontier closed, but the last of those who remember it are dying. In a
single lifetime, the open ranges will become tract housing, and the epic and
epochal scale of cinema will be replaced by the corrupt and dishonorable
codes of television, where Peckinpah cut his professional teeth (Simmons
1998: 27–34).
The films’ inevitable failure to capture loss at the moment of loss is the
source of their beauty, and of their sadness. The characters of The Wild
Bunchregret losing the Old West of Pat Garrettwhose characters regret the
passing of an even older way. The Old West was never more than a state of
mind, and one always unrecoverably prior to whatever present we attempt
to inhabit. The world of Peckinpah’s West is always a fallen one. The Uru-
guayan critic Angel Rama observes of early twentieth-century cultural re-
vivals in Latin America, “The living popular culture of the moment was not
the conservative, declining folk heritage of the countryside that urban intel-
lectuals admired for its picturesque local color. It was the vital, vulgar cul-
ture of the urban masses, who drew on rural folk traditions as the natural
8
NEOCLASSICAL FILM
| |
matrix of their own creativity but did so without a nostalgic urge to con-
serve” (Rama 1996: 103). The classical Western worked in the same way, but
for Peckinpah it was that urban legend of the West that had become the lost
Eden. Not historical but fictional, what had gone was not just the Old West
but the Old Hollywood: the prewar world of John Ford. Peckinpah’s is an
antitechnological universe: the six-gun and the movie camera are the only
true, the only authentic machines. All other devices, from Garrett’s Win-
chester to the printing press Alias walks away from, are substitutes for liv-
ing. Only cinema and the code of the shoot-out have the smack of truth, the
phenomenology of visceral presence. And both are caught at the moment of
their fading.
Seydor (1997: 180) notes the proximity of the destruction of the bridge
in The Wild Bunchto one of Peckinpah’s favorite films, The Bridge on the River
Kwai.Even closer is the Western cycle of Sergio Leone, who once observed
in a BBC interview that “My bridges have a tendency to blow up.” More ger-
mane than these European movies to the nostalgia of Peckinpah’s set-ups,
however, is the reference to the great bridge sequence in Buster Keaton’s The
General,a film that marked the high point of the authorial director in Hol-
lywood. Peckinpah’s well-documented battles with producers over direc-
torial control are significant contributions to the myth of the Hollywood
auteur. Creative freedom is, in Peckinpah, the mythic freedom of the Old
West, and both are dying. The Paramount Decrees severing production and
distribution from exhibition had changed the economic landscape of North
American filmmaking forever. Meanwhile, the new domestic pleasures of
suburbia had emasculated television. Though Hollywood turned toward a
more mature subject matter for a period when its key demographic appeared
| 191 |
N
eo
c
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
to be the adult audience dissatisfied with the child- and teen-oriented safety
of television programming, economic conservatism still ruled.
Peckinpah is an early proponent of neoclassicism, whose aesthetic key
is a movement away from narrative toward diegesis as the core of the film.
We do not need to believe, with Kitses, that “The Wild Bunchis America”
(Kitses 1969: 168), or to accept the political allegory proposed by Brauer
(1974) to grasp this shift, although it relates obliquely and tortuously to a
reorientation of conceptions of national identity in the era of the Vietnam
War, a thesis shared by Sharrett (1999) and Cook (1996: 928–930). With
Peckinpah, dialogue- and story-driven classicism embraced a realist obses-
sion with the creation of a world. The rapid development of soundscaping
(Schreger 1985) and the impact of widescreen (Carr and Hayes 1988; Bel-
ton 1992) helped this devaluation of dialogue in favor of mime and acceler-
ated the classical Western’s fascination with landscape, the world conjured
up in the structural analyses of Cawelti (1985) and Wright (1975). The myth
of the West had become international property over the years: we can refer
to M. Lange’s Arizona Jim in Le Crime de M. Langefor a sense of its signifi-
cance in popular culture throughout Europe. With Leone’s 1960s Western
cycle (A Fistful of Dollars, For a Few Dollars More, The Good, the Bad, and the
Ugly, Once Upon a Time in the West), the European vision returned to the U.S.
market in hybrid form: an Italian film based on a Japanese original made
inSpain with German money and a Californian star. Moreover, the Leone
films paved the way for a more historicized sense of the Old West as a com-
plex political economy in which the railroad and the cattle-barons play an
ineluctable part. And of course Leone introduced that dilated sense of time
passing that would become the raw material of cinema in The Wild Bunch
and Pat Garrett.
Ugliness and the Exit Wound
Every myth of origin of the nation-state, from The Aeneidto King Arthur or
Robin Hood, from the Chanson de Rolandto The New Zealand Wars(Perrott
2002), requires two factors. The first is heroism; the second betrayal. In the
homosocial worlds of the national epic, difference is reduced to its absolute:
the hero and his other, or more particularly the heroic socius and its betrayer.
Its archetypal statement is the Last Supper, still echoing around Mapache’s
high table with its machine-gun monstrance in the square at Aguaverde.
History begins with betrayal and is given its enduring quality, its endurance
| 192 |
C
h
ap
te
r
8
|
indeed, by the suffering of the hero. Conservative folklore has the sovereign
betrayed by his subjects—King Arthur, Victorian source of legitimacy, Lin-
coln in Capra’s populist Republicanism. Popular history revolves around or
assumes the betrayal of the people by the monarch—King John in the Robin
Hood legend—or abandoned by rulers and forced to invent justice. In the
neoclassical cinema, the law is entirely external: an arbitrary means to ex-
ploitation. In its place, justice is grounded in revenge for betrayal by the law.
History is invented by the protagonists on behalf of the diegetic world. The
gap between classicism and neoclassicism is the gap between nationalism
and postnationalism in the era of globalization, whose first experience came
home to Hollywood in the form of the Vietnam War.
Ford’s Westerns inhabit this scale of national myth as much as the Ser-
bian epics, but do so in the mode Rama identified as conservative. The hero-
ism of Stagecoach’s Ringo Kid is permanently available as resource, and the
nation’s destiny resides in its truth to those values that lie at its roots. Peck-
inpah, however, belongs to the second mode, not so much because he repre-
sents the urban—he was intensely concerned to foster a biography grounded
in the California high country—as because, when compared with those of
his peers, his Westerns are ready to hybridize. It is not only that folk tradi-
tions are his raw material, his “natural matrix.” When Peckinpah looks into
the Old West, he sees not the purist homogeneity of a monocultural Volkbut
mestizaje,the mixing of Hispanic, European, and Indian cultures at the point
of origin. Like Bernal’s Athens, meeting place of Asia and Africa (Bernal
1987), or like the music of the Afro-Celt Sound System, grounded in musi-
cal and linguistic affinities between Celtic and West African languages,
Peckinpah’s myth of origin is a legend of cultural mixing, not one of racial
purity. Those who attempt to import European monocultural values—the
temperance preachers, for example—are the enemy. In a move that extends
the careless innovation of the tango in the 1910s and ’20s, Peckinpah’s films
do not mix what was originally pure: they insist that there is no purity at the
wellspring, and that our “identity” has always been multiple.
From this hybrid standpoint, it is the pure that is ornery. When the rail-
road boss Harrigan declares that he is always right and represents the law, it
is a claim to such purity of identity. The same claim is implicit in the Ger-
man commandant, eminence griseof Mapache’s camp, for whom the machine
gun must be mounted on a tripod, not fired off at random. The mechanical
placed against the chaotic is a dialectic of the pure and the hybrid, with the
| 193 |
N
eo
c
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
film’s heart firmly planted in the mestizosoil of the borderlands. Thus Peck-
inpah abandons the purity of the epic in favor of the border ballad, elegy
being the appropriate mode for a film practice whose central motif is the
suffering of the hero who cannot blame his betrayal on another.
Not only suffering but violence derives from betrayal. In The Wild
Bunch(figs. 8.1, 8.2),that betrayal is multiple, as emblematized in the open-
ing scene of children torturing scorpions by placing them on an ants’ nest.
“One supposes that the scorpions stand for the professionals,” notes Noël
Carroll (1998: 57), while the ants stand for the little people, the children
who punish Angel as he is dragged behind the Ford ModelT, or perhaps the
westward expansion of the small-minded civilization that Peckinpah’s he-
roes so despise. Then again, perhaps the scorpions are the big businesses,
and the scene prefigures Fanonian revolutionary cruelty. The power of such
emblematic shots derives not from their unambiguous allegory but from
| 194 |
C
h
ap
te
r
8
|
| Figure 8.1 |
The Wild Bunch:predestination as the only freedom. Courtesy BFI Collections.
their opacity and ambivalence—one reason that this sequence works rather
better than similar ones in other films. Most of all, the sequence radiates a
quality that will be essential to the film, and indeed to the new Western as a
whole: the sense of the ugly. Ugliness is not the same as the vile or the ab-
ject. As Leone’s title suggests, it exists in a relation between the good and the
bad: the ugly is an ethical category.
Peckinpah wants—or wanted in his early career—to go beyond the
pointless, painless amorality of the television Western.
Look, you know what this is? That’s a .45-calibre, 240-grain hunk of lead that
can splatter your brains out like a jumped on squash. You ever seen a bullet hole?
I mean up close. Oh, it goes in little enough, but when it comes out, that’s if
| 195 |
N
eo
c
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
| Figure 8.2 |
The Wild Bunch:from the montage of the falling cadaver: killing as ethical aesthetic. Courtesy BFI Collections.
you’re lucky and it comes out, it leaves a hole about like that. Now a gun ain’t
something to play with, it’s to kill people with, and you don’t reach for it unless
you’re going to shoot, and you don’t shoot unless you’re going to kill. You un-
derstand? (“Hand on the Gun” episode of The Westerner,scripted and directed
by Peckinpah; Seydor 1997: 17)
It is not the anodyne and formulaic that must be shattered, but the belief
thatlife can be taken without consequence: a belief still enshrined in the
language of “surgical strikes,” “collateral damage,” “friendly fire.” Death in
Peckinpah is ugly because it is a moral event. But it is beautiful on the same
basis, a truth already exploited by Arthur Penn two years earlier in Bonnie
and Clyde,a film that reinvented the gangster by removing him from the city
into the dusty countryside of the Depression, a scant twenty-five years after
the Bunch rode over Mexican border.
Penn’s film made extensive use of squibs, small explosive charges packed
under an actor’s clothes next to a small bag of prop blood and detonated
electronically. Early cinema gunfire was provided by real weapons; wounds
were simulated by firing ink-soaked sponges from small pistols. With sync
sound, a more realistic effect could be gotten either by firing live ammo, es-
pecially for machine-gun fire, or by firing gelatine capsules filled with imi-
tation blood from air-rifles. The squib was a new invention in the 1960s.
Peckinpah’s stunts department added to the effect by placing charges at the
exit wound side of the body, an effect toyed with in a single shot of Bonnie
and Clydewhen a fragment of “skull” is shown being blown out of C.W.’s
head in the final shoot-out.
Peckinpah used the effect extensively, adding scraps of meat to the squib
to emphasize the trauma, and ensuring that the explosions were strong
enough to give the actors a hefty jolt. The sheer number of exploding squibs
in the finale demanded multiple takes, as well as a fantastically large popu-
lation for a small outpost. In the making of the final shoot-out in The Wild
Bunch, the props master had only 350 Mexican uniforms. The shoot even-
tually called for something in the region of 6000 wounds. A production line
was set up to patch the exploded jackets with tape, paint them khaki, and
plant fresh squibs in them. One critical effect of the meat in the squibs was
to suggest the smell of the carnage, a connotation rarely even mentioned in
dialogue in earlier films, with the exception of some B Westerns. Angel’s
death was originally accomplished with the aid of a carbonated syrup
| 196 |
C
h
ap
te
r
8
|
stashed inside a pressurized prosthetic skin over the actor’s throat, an effect
borrowed from Kurosawa’s Sanjuro:the shot was excised from the final cut
with Peckinpah’s blessing—the effect had got a laugh, possibly of embarrass-
ment, at previews, perhaps because of the cartoon effect of violence raised
beyond the socially tolerable.
Despite Dixon’s claim that “One could hardly imagine the song ‘Rain-
drops Keep Falling on My Head’ being incorporated into Peckinpah’s vision
of the West, as it was in Butch Cassidy” (Dixon 1999: 156), Peckinpah was ca-
pable of sentimentality, as witness the saccharine “Butterfly Mornings” se-
quence in The Ballad of Cable Hogue. As primarily sentimental—enjoyment
without incurring responsibility—that sequence and to some extent that
whole film abandon responsibility for the actions of the characters and for
their fates—the crude irony of Hogue’s death, for instance, under the wheels
of his lover’s car. One might say the same of the decision to reduce the
slitthroat to the passing of a knife and a reaction shot. Given the generous
brutality of the sequence, the only stumbling block was that laughter in the
preview theater. Tragedy requires pity and terror, emotions proper to empa-
thy and identification and thus to ethics. In the original cut, pity for Angel
issentimental and the terror fatalistic, neither evoking an ethical commit-
ment. Without responsibility, the sentimental becomes sublime or, as here,
its opposite—disgusting. The vile is by definition asocial, debarring itself
from communication and therefore from ethics. Beauty is ethical because it
is social—historically grounded fruit of common taste and shared stan-
dards. Like beauty, ugliness is a matter of debate. It is speakable, and when
we speak of it, or argue what is or isn’t ugly, we take responsibility in ways
we cannot when confronted with the unspeakably awesome or the unutter-
ably vile.
In the existing cut of The Wild Bunch,we are in the field of beauty and
ugliness, not of sublimity and the vile. The fountain of carotid blood is vile,
inappropriate to the context of beauty and ugliness, and comical for that
reason. Even if it had not raised a laugh, confronting the audience with the
abject would, as counterpoint, reposition the deaths of the gunmen as sub-
lime and tragic, rather than historical and elegaic. This dividing line distin-
guishes The Wild Bunchfrom many subsequent films, including several of
Peckinpah’s own. In the splatter genre of horror, for example, the vile is
erected as an extrahistorical category, an inverted Ideal Form according to
which evil is the perpetual and unchanging antithesis of life. Too often,
| 197 |
N
eo
c
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
sequences aimed at establishing disgust function purely to reinforce them-
selves, and to remove the film from the critical categories of social discourse
that anchor meaning in time. They present their shocks in simple para-
doxes: the commonest form of the vile is the inside-out, in which the wet,
glistening, soft viscera are on display while the epidermis, if nothing else
waterproof, is peeled back to reveal an undead and ahistorical interior both
porous and invasive.
What makes The Wild Buncha finer film than such is that it demands
that we meet and understand not individuals, nor principles, but a landscape
of action. Yet despite the claims made for it, The Wild Bunchis not a flawless
film. Its political reason for being lies in the political violence of North
America in the late 1960s, and the discovery of the My Lai massacre, which
had a dramatic impact on Peckinpah, as evidenced by a letter of his read by
Jason Robards in the BBC’s Moving Pictures documentary Sam Peckinpah:
Man of Iron, comparing the violence in the film with that visited on the
people of Vietnam. To see the film as radical is overstating the case. Alle-
gorically, Pancho Villa should stand for Ho Chi Minh, but Villa’s forces re-
main as faceless as the Viet Cong in Hollywood (with the honorable but
financially negligible exception of Oliver Stone’s Heaven and Earth).
In any case, the Bunch’s self-destruction has little to do with revolution,
everything to do with a final act of camaraderie in the closing moments of
their time in history. The reprise of the visit to Angel’s village under the final
credits reveals that sequence’s tendency to the maudlin: its mute dialogue of
shared thoughts and experiences that need no vocalization (and therefore no
translations), its infantilization of the psychopathic Gorch brothers, its Tex-
Mex reworking of the dance from My Darling Clementinewithout the dance
having been earned. “It ain’t like it used to be... but it’ll do”: the film’s last
line of dialogue allows the Bunch a grandeur that, in fact, they have not de-
served. Thornton’s smile is relaxed and happy because, after all, he has not
had to change. In this sense alone The Wild Bunchis sentimental, in a way
that, with all its flaws, Pat Garrett and Billy the Kidis not.
Anecdote of the Jar
Pat Garrett and Billy the Kid(figs. 8.3, 8.4)sports two incompatible protago-
nists. Billy is the last outlaw, the last free man, in a world that is turning
legitimate. Garrett is not so much a turncoat and traitor as a fatalist, seized
| 198 |
C
h
ap
te
r
8
|
by the idea that the weight of history is too much for a man on his own to
change. Across a landscape of dusty sunlight the two will circle each other
through a picaresque of killings, brawls, drinking sessions, and brothels,
constantly shadowed by the knowledge we have, from the outset, that the
end of the story is already sealed, that Garrett will shoot Billy and will in his
turn be brought down by anonymous gunmen. The film is heavily weighted
toward the self-consciously aging and disillusioned Garrett with his sense
ofanger and doom. Cursory, psychologically undeveloped, the character of
Billy is emblematic of a mythical freedom. Garrett will age, swept along by
times not of his making: the Kid confronts destiny as event, as the moment
where legend intersects with history.
The film recalls, in a more macho and violent mode, the anaesthetic of
Wallace Stevens’s (1955) “Anecdote of the Jar,” about a jar the poet places ona
hill in Tennessee, which “made the slovenly wilderness surround that hill.”
| 199 |
N
eo
c
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
| Figure 8.3 |
Pat Garrett and Billy the Kid:Bob Dylan as Alias—star as actor as character at the margin of the narrative
and the center of the score. Courtesy BFI Stills, Posters, and Designs.
The orderly thing arrests the landscape, brings it to order, but the jar “did
notgive of bird or bush/Like nothing else in Tennessee”: its order is as
sterileasamule. Against the life force embodied in Billy—free-loving, free-
living, free-drinking, open-hearted, and on his way to a tryst with history—
Garrett is haunted by his own demons, torn between loyalty and security,
between an old code of honor he knows he will betray and a new code of
business he despises but to which he submits. In the shadow of Vietnam and
the Watergate scandal, the film presented itself as an account of law gone
toruin, with the Santa Fe Ring of Chisum’s landowners in the role of the
military-industrial system, embroiled in a vicious pacification of the land-
scape and sterilization of its freedoms (see Weddle 1994: 489–491; for Ci-
mino’s version see Bach 1985). The political scenario is acted out on the
scarred prairie of Coburn’s face, haunted by a duty in which he does not be-
lieve. That betrayal is the core of the film, while Billy’s smooth skin and wide
eyes provide its mythic counterpoint. The film, its narrative, its narration, its
most detailed characterizations, take place in this dirty political world of half-
| 200 |
C
h
ap
te
r
8
|
| Figure 8.4 |
Pat Garrett and Billy the Kid:age, cunning, and resignation against youth, beauty, and fate.
Courtesy BFI Stills, Posters, and Designs.
truths and unwelcome promises: the myth is there only as foil. Yet Dylan’s
score will take the opposite road. If the film is Garrett’s, the music is Billy’s.
The vocal track first enters as Billy escapes from jail in Lincoln. As the
lyric reaches the line “Up to Boot Hill they’d like to send ya,” there is a cut
to Alias, who turns from the camera, taking off his apron as he goes, and with
a look of decision on his face. This is only the ninth shot of Alias, none of
them with dialogue. Indeed, we have to wait for the next scene before we
hear his voice, responding to Garrett’s query, “Who are you?” with the curt
and cryptic response, “That’s a good question.” The audience could be ex-
pected to identify the singer on screen, singled out by medium close-ups
and midshots from the rest of the townsfolk. But given Dylan’s fame and sig-
nificance in the marketing of the film, the singer is more identifiable than
the protagonist, a role that, in any case, Dylan had rejected and Alias never
achieves. Strangely marginal to the narrative, although Alias looks, no other
character looks back at him, leaving him unplaced in the series of reverse
angle shots that dominate the scene. At the same time, the spatial organiza-
tion, clear enough on analysis, isn’t immediately apparent in normal view-
ing: we have to infer his position from the shots of the other players. In
filmic terms, as unobserved observer, Dylan is external to the action and in
that sense occupies the role of proxy for the audience. Yet the star charisma
that allows us to identify him as Dylan tends to militate, in the special cir-
cumstance in which he is also the asynchronous, extradiegetic voice of the
soundtrack song, against the ordinary identification we might have with a
movie star in the role.
In his activity as a well-known public figure undertaking the work of an
actor on screen, Dylan performs a curious work of suture in the world of the
film. Until this shot, Dylan is clearly an outsider to the action: in shot 26 he
turns into a participant in the narrative. This coincides with the lyric “Billy
don’t you turn your back....” It is the nearest we get to mickey-mousing in
the scene. Typically, mickey-mousing brings together image and sound into
a single unified effect. Here it draws together five disparate elements:
•Dylan as star,
•Dylan as performer of the soundtrack,
•the first-person narrator of the soundtrack song,
•the actor Bob Dylan, and
•the character of Alias,
| 201 |
N
eo
c
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
not all of which are in synch. Until now, Alias has not addressed Billy at all,
yet in the song, the first-person address to Billy is in the character of some-
one who has known him for years, that is, in the character of Alias in the
relationship he will have with Billy by the end of the film. Our apparent
synchronization now seems to conceal some temporal glitches. Visually—
and this will be reinforced in subsequent shots—Alias’s turn is a decision to
leave the construction of the diegesis and join in the construction of the nar-
rative. But it is executed in terms of a complex association with the lyrics of
the song, in which, while he warns Billy “don’t turn your back,” he turns his
own. This striking synchronization might even be seen as a rare moment of
crudity in the editing comparable to the heavily signaled ironies of children
playing on the gallows earlier, but less blatant given the transposition of ref-
erence from one character to another and the temporal displacement of the
symmetry that is in the process of being established between Dylan on the
soundtrack and Billy in the visuals.
The shot draws the singing voice into a curious hinterland between
diegetic and extradiegetic, and between commentary on the action in this
specific scene and on the film as a whole. Here, at the moment of synchro-
nization, the voice has an ambiguous role as motivated by onscreen action,
despite being laid in as commentary in every previous shot. The status of
both the song and the singer alter with the moment of synchronization, per-
mitting not only the recruitment of Dylan into the narration, but the re-
organization of the song’s relation to the image. Until this point, the song
was extradiegetic commentary on the action; now it is diegetic and com-
ments from within on the world of the film. And so we have a further para-
dox: the singer on the soundtrack is now implicated in the linear structure
of the narration, while the song appears to have been freed from linear con-
straints to address the global themes of destiny and freedom to which the
film is oriented. Dylan/Alias’s dual position, both inside and outside the die-
gesis, both subject to and agents of linear narration (Dylan as balladeer,
Alias as chronicler), is what allows the image-sound relation in Pat Garrett
and Billy the Kidto be so mythopoeic, but at the same time to break the clas-
sical symmetries. As in the allegorical relation between Alias and Billy, mi-
nor asymmetries creep in as the classical system is asked to provide semantic
structures—specifically dialectical structures—of which it is incapable.
To that extent, the relation between Billy and Alias remains cryptic and
unmotivated throughout. The hermetic aura in which Dylan folded himself
| 202 |
C
h
ap
te
r
8
|
in public and in his songs from the mid-1960s on defines freedom as a re-
fusal to be identified and interpreted. The ideological dialectic of the ne-
cessity and impossibility of freedom from identity chimes with the diegetic
of the disintegration and dishonoring of the West. When Alias turns decid-
edly, we can wonder whether the narrative motivation is the spark of under-
standing between Billy and the Mexican, an act of solidarity with the Other
entirely in keeping with Dylan’s personae in songs and public statements
since his earliest successes. Alternatively, Alias’s decision might be derived
from Billy’s ride out under the gallows he escapes. In this case, “don’t turn
your back on me” would give the first person of the soundtrack vocal the
added overtone of the death that Billy has refused, and would further explain
the nonlinear temporality that the song takes on at this moment.
A third possibility comes in the next shot, in which the most misogy-
nistic of the verses accompanies a pan that moves from Billy in long shot to
a man shoveling coal into a forge in medium shot, the darkness and flames,
whose roar intersects with the music, accompanying a line that, in Dylan’s
modulations, could be heard as either “Into her dark hallway she will lead ya”
or “Into her dark hole where she will lead ya.” Even discounting the crude
Freudianism, there is an apparent collapsing of femininity and death here,
which the extended lyric’s implied narrative also dwells upon. Is Alias’s de-
cision also motivated by this dark elision of sexuality and mortality? In ei-
ther case, the fiery furnace aligns sex and mortality with the fires of hell,
taking us in the opposite direction to the Christlike pose of the surrender at
the shack and the degradation by Ollinger that illustrates the album cover.
The Manichean universe implied here is symptomatic of the struggle to-
ward and failure to secure a dialectical structure to the film, a failure that en-
forces the allegorical tenor of Billy and Alias’s characterizations.
The song “Billy” bares its own internal dialectics in the stretch between
notes at the top of Dylan’s vocal range, the reach for the tertiary rhyme, the
sense of foreboding and of nostalgia, its doubling of cyclical form with nar-
rative impulse, the clash between blues and waltz rhythms, and the lived-in
timbre of Dylan’s singing. It also reaches a kind of point de capiton by linking
soundtrack and image into a single troubled and ambivalent but nonethe-
less organized and recognizable whole. On the cut before the end of the line
“Billy don’t you turn your back...,” by the time we hear its close, “... on
me,” Billy is riding out of town seen from the vantage point of the forge. If
the former shot has persuaded us that Dylan (visually) is Alias, in the latter
| 203 |
N
eo
c
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
Dylan (audibly) is Billy. Since the film in general is characterized, like the
song, by omniscient narration, there is no difficulty in our assimilating the
presence of the anonymous foundryman into the sculpture of the film: his
failure to look gives us instead a sense, like Auden’s “Musée des Beaux Arts”
(1966: 123–124), that life goes on in its uninterrupted round despite the fall
of Icarus.
The role of observation is overrated, the film suggests: the depiction of
great events is simply a way of narrativizing the ordinariness of the every-
day, a theme picked up in the “Duck of Death” sequence in Eastwood’s Un-
forgiven. And although the song is suitably ambiguous in warning that the
reason for not turning your back is not to get shot as much as it is a plea that
Billy take note of the song’s forebodings, it heralds in the carriage of the line
over the edit between shots the way the foundryman turns his back on all
ofthis, the roar of his flames allied with the darkness of the mortal, sensual
hallway, the Hell at the end of the road on which Billy rides. After Billy is
carefully, even clumsily Christianized in the shots of his surrender to Gar-
rett at the shack, and more subtly in the framing of his scenes with the Mex-
ican, this extension of the Christian symbology as iconographic subtext
functions to ground Billy in a religious past and the song in the film as a
prophesying. The fade-out under the following scene, which is dominated
by Garrett, can then be read as the fading of mythic history under the geo-
graphical imperative of the Santa Fe ring, itself marked at the end of the
Garrett sequence by the sweetening of the ambient sounds with the chim-
ing of church bells over an image of Garrett arriving at the picket fence of
his already suburban home.
There follows a montage sequence covered by the remaining two verses
of “Billy,” in which the song resumes its metacommentary function and Billy
is remythologized as an emanation of the landscape prior to the narrative se-
quence in which Garrett visits the Governor’s residence. The film maintains
this cycling between mythopoiesis and a realism almost Zolaesque in its
bleakness and predestinarianism, while in the new context of film score, the
song can now be read as far less ambivalent or dialectical in itself and far
more dialectical in its relation with the image.
Michel Chion is adamant that film music does not exist “in itself and as
such” (en tant que tel): there is only music in film. All musics in cinema are
integral to the film: there is no special art of film music differentiable from
either other musics that might be cinematically applied, or from the inte-
| 204 |
C
h
ap
te
r
8
|
gration of sound and image that forms the audiovisual (Chion 1992: 39–40).
Listening to Dylan’s score bears this out: the song works differently as album
track and as integral to the editing and narrational-diegetic dialectic of the
film. As score, its internal dialectic is subordinated to the film’s central con-
tradictions. Moreover, in the film, both dialogue lines and sound effects of
clinking horse brasses, Billy’s fall, and the furnace roar are integrated into the
song. In the hands of a Korngold or a Rosza, this might have implied the mu-
sicalization of the sound effects. But in this instance, the mix draws the mu-
sic entirely, and the singing partially, into the diegetic world of the film, as
sound effect, as the soundtrack not to the film but to the man at the center
of the sequence, Billy the Kid. Both the first-person persona of the vocal and
Billy inhabit a freedom whose essence is that its price is mortality, that is, a
definitionally circumscribed freedom. Moreover, though both song and ac-
tion are encompassed in the present tense, both inhabit the past, since both
are recordings (a point emphasized by Dylan’s double presence in visual and
audio mode) and both are framed by the narration’s flashback structure.
The proto-sunshine-noir of the movie belongs to that long elegy for
history which is still being written in the contemporary cinema of North
America. Billy lives in historical time, a time in which events matter, deci-
sions are life-and-death, and lives pass into legend. This too is the temporal
mode of the song “Billy” in the scenes I have been analyzing. Moreover, the
film, made on the wane of Peckinpah’s great period, revels in what it reveals:
the decay of a talent at the moment of ripeness, disintegrating into its own
madness, like Jerry Lee Lewis living out in his biography the contradictions
of his culture (see Tosches 1982): the libertarian fundamentalism, the com-
pulsive anarchy, the terrible beauty of a shocking self-destruction that we
expect to characterize Billy but instead accrue to Pat. In choosing life, Gar-
rett condemns himself to the mere inhabitance of space. Nonetheless he
must fulfill the logic of the history from which he is endeavoring to escape,
and for his last historical act, refusing to die, he must kill and finally be killed.
Here stands the famous shot in which Garrett, after killing Billy, shoots
his own image in the mirror: what he kills there is his last moment in the leg-
endary universe, his role as avenging angel. From henceforth he will inhabit
only empty extension, the spatial world of a diegesis deprived of the histor-
ical impetus of narrative. One might see in the image of Garrett’s impotent,
imaginary suicide the inspiration for Wenders’s Himmel Über Berlin(Wings
of Desire), the abjuring of angelic status in order to live; but where Wenders’s
| 205 |
N
eo
c
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
angel revels in his senses, Garrett becomes their prisoner, a character to
whom nothing else will ever happen. In the wonderful “Beans” dialogue
scene, Alias will provide, at gunpoint and instructed by Garrett, an absurdist
commentary on the carnage and the transformation of legendary time into
directionless space in the endless litany of commodities.
Situated at that plane of legend outside quotidian psychology, time, and
space where the soundtrack vocal moves between diegesis and narration, the
only free position in the film, Dylan is a Heideggerian angel, announcer of
the fading of presence that the late Heidegger would associate specifically
with television: “What is happening here when, as a result of the abolition
of great distances, everything is equally far and equally near? What is this
uniformity in which everything is neither far nor near—is, as it were, with-
out distance?” (Heidegger 1971: 165–166). Alive and mortal, Billy endures
the presence of things and their nearness as he endures the nearness of his
own mortality. Garrett, however, with his fenced-in house, his technologi-
cal buggy removed from the immediacy of riding, his refusal of death, in-
habits the distanceless with a lack of presence, haunted by representations,
subject to his objects. And Dylan moves across this distressed frontier be-
tween the modernizing of the United States and the underdeveloping of
Mexico, the enigmatic angel who inhabits both space and time, whose fall is
inscribed in the turn away from the camera in shot 26, his only narrative mo-
ment, and who carries news of the two worlds across the boundary between
them, always strange, in Lacan’s pun the étrangethat is always être ange,“to be
angel,” or in Buci-Glucksmann’s gloss (1994: 43–45), the angel of the odd.
Our transcendence is marked by the real: by an authenticity that we
have begun to yield in the realization that everything is mediated, even our
most direct perceptions. The world as it exists before the camera, before it
gathers itself together to be photographed, is forever separated from the
world of the film by the temporal act of recording that removes its image
from the flow of time, not disappearing but forever marked off from the pic-
turesque with which we view it subsequently. To speak of boundaries is to
speak of angels, whose natural domain is the liminal, who personify the
threshold, and whose spectral alienation is the otherness of the Other. That
one moment of mickey-mousing, that lapse in taste, that one synchroniza-
tion of sound and image, is the moment of passage from one world to the
next, from representation to experience, a backward and undoable step, an
election to live in the past, where reality exists prior to recording; a step out
| 206 |
C
h
ap
te
r
8
|
of cinema, not into the profilmic simultaneity of realism, but into the an-
gelic memory of present things before their presence faded.
After the Event
Unlike the freeze frame, which is achieved by repetitive step-printing of a
single frame in the optical printer, slow motion is a camera effect. It belongs
to the domain of Benjamin’s “unconscious optics” (Benjamin 1969: 237), the
revelation of a world whose timescales are too small for human perception.
Speeding up the filmstrip to extend the duration of an action, especially
aneveryday human action like falling, brushes the familiar with an aura of
unfamiliarity.
But Benjamin’s phrase also suggests the surrealist sense of a Freudian
unconscious. The question is, whose unconscious might be being enacted
on the screen in the middle of a Peckinpah shoot-out? For whom does the
body of the dead soldier drop so slowly from the cliffs after the ambush of
the rifle wagon in The Wild Bunch?The soldier himself has taken two bul-
lets: is this temporality the unconsciousness of dying? Does it reveal, as in
Prince’s argument, the “metaphysical paradox of the body’s enhanced cine-
matic reactions during a moment of diminished or extinguished conscious-
ness” (Prince 1998: 60)? Or, as Paul Seydor argues, does it operate in a
double paradox, where the slow motion “distances us from the action by aes-
theticising it” (Seydor 1997: 190) while nevertheless “the slow-motion
shots are almost always held to a particular, often subjective, point of view
that is clearly, if implicitly, identified as such in and by the film” (ibid.: 191)?
Aestheticizing, in this context, would represent the removal of the action
from the embodied senses—of pain, of empathy, of anger or disgust—and
its sublimation as vision, optically stripping the event of consciousness.
Subjectivizing, by contrast, reanchors the shock of violence, but in the body
of an onlooker.
The effect remains ambiguous in our instance, as if the (un)conscious-
ness experiencing the fall in slow motion is smeared across the victim,
theonlookers, and the audience. This begins to resemble the “triangle of
looks” proposed in Laura Mulvey’s (1975) thesis concerning the domi-
nance of amale gaze in the construction of femininity in classical Holly-
wood. The male equivalent to the fetishistic mise-en-scène of the female
song-and-dance routine is the ritual violence of fistfights. This is so en-
trenched in contemporary understandings of film as to be parodied in
| 207 |
N
eo
c
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
Fight Club, where the first bare-knuckle bout in the car park is followed by
aparodically postcoital sequence of the guys smoking. A psychoanalytic-
biographical critique might emphasize Peckinpah’s notorious personal and
cinematic mistreatment of women, his fear of them, and some kind of as-
cription of repressed homosexuality.2
This approach would only add to the uncertainty of the place of un-
consciousness in the slow-motion gloss on killing in The Wild Bunch. Al-
though many of the close-up inserts drag us into the agony of a hit from a
rifle slug, this image of the falling cadaver, cut before it reaches the ground,
is filmed in extreme long shot. On the command “¡Mate lo!” we see in quick
succession the victim looking up at his comrades, cutting to a medium shot
of the first soldier to shoot, seen as it were from Mapache’s lieutenant’s per-
spective, but far closer, more like the distance between rifleman and victim.
The next cut brings in that soldier’s perspective on the victim receiving the
first bullet, then the victim’s perspective of the second shooter. However,
the victim is not looking up at this point, but slumping back against the walls
of the mesa with his face turned down. Who then faces the rifle as it fires
into the camera? We cut to the victim as he falls toward the bottom of the
frame, seen from a position we know to be impossible for any subject, in the
air before the cliff face. Here we cut to a close up of Dutch turning to see
the action, then the extreme long shot of the body in slow-motion fall, ac-
companied by a distant, echoing cry, cutting back to the same framing of
Dutch as he turns to Pike and nods, with a suggestion of a wink, confirming
that the Bunch are in a controlling position in the standoff that frames this
piece of business.
In classical continuity cutting, we would be armed with a response: the
consciousness of the film itself holds the action in an almost metaphysical
eye. But in Peckinpah, that omnivoyant camera is reduced to a role on a par
with that of the characters, and the point-of-view shots are scattered fairly
democratically among protagonists, speaking parts, and anonymous extras
including children and at certain stages possibly animals. A clue comes from
Benjamin’s continuation of his argument. Auratic art—painting, classical
poetry—was an art of asocial contemplation. Film is at once a “ballistic” art
of shock and a social art of distraction. Dadaism had wrapped this shock ef-
fect in a blanket of moral outrage. In the popular cinema, shock became
physical, its “distracting element... primarily tactile, being based on
changes of place and focus which periodically assail the spectator” (Ben-
| 208 |
C
h
ap
te
r
8
|
jamin 1969: 238). In the cutting of The Wild Bunch,which at over 3,600 shots
is one of the fastest-paced edits in color films with an average shot length of
only 2.3 seconds,3 the periodicity of movement between points of view,
flagged and unflagged, motivated by characters or by omniscient vision, has
the effect of dispersing our attention. At various points, slow-motion inserts
may anchor us in a body-in-pain or in the eye of an onlooker, or again in the
disembodied position of a spectator alert only to the choreography of vio-
lence disconnected from pain or responsibility.
Seydor gives a third reading of the slow-motion shots: that they are con-
sequential on the relation between maximum energy and minimum space, so
that “time itself is forced to take up the slack, which it does by expanding to
contain the violent energies released in collision” (Seydor 1997: 201). He
adds, however, as befits his humanist and biographical reading of Peckinpah’s
oeuvre, that the expansion is not of time itself but of the perception of time.
David Cook notes the impact of one instance of slow motion in another
medium: the NBC live coverage of Jack Ruby’s assassination of Lee Harvey
Oswald (Cook 1999: 140). Within minutes of the shooting, CBS was rolling
videotaped footage and that evening was showing it in slow motion. “In-
stead of the impressive form of an athlete in competition,” notes Mary Ann
Watson, “an actual murder was captured and elongated in what was de-
scribed as a ‘grotesque ballet’” (Watson 1994: 220). Like Peckinpah’s “slow-
motion leap” (Fine 1991: 142), the action replay of the Oswald murder
becomes choreography by the power of technology to unearth the grace
within the graceless, the unconscious beauty lurking in even the most des-
picable of acts.
The slow-motion ballet, then, points us in two directions at once. On
the one hand, it points forward to the “bullet time” of John Gaeta’s effects
for The Matrix.On the other, the reference to the Oswald killing points us
toward the public status of death in the era of mass mediation. The one
places us in the time of the bullet itself, a world slowed to the duration of the
bullet’s flight from weapon to target, its perception not that of the humans
involved but of technologies, cinematic and ballistic. The other renders the
viewing subject as the apparatus of television news, that is, of the ideologi-
cal machine par excellence of the late twentieth century.
Slow motion abstracts the action depicted, but only to a level at which
incomprehension becomes, in Chomsky’s phrase, manufactured consent.
This is not to subscribe to Chomsky’s hypodermic theory of news media,
| 209 |
N
eo
c
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
but to agree that, in becoming media spectacle, death loses its subjectivity
to become merely a datum, one that belongs no longer to the unique expe-
rience of killers and killed. Such a datum, selected in the same way in which
a critical tackle or critical goal is chosen, presented in slow motion, occu-
pies a moment in which the privileged instance loses its particularity to
someone in order to gain it for everyone—the moment, therefore, in which
a death becomes historic. It is this delay, this stoppage of time, that brings
the epic dimension into fiction, extracting the squalid murders of The Wild
Bunchand Pat Garrettfrom their menial contexts to render them in the same
fabric as the tapestry of history. Slow motion is monumental sculpture. Like
the statue in the Lincoln Memorial, it holds a moment in time as public
memory, its grandeur the product of the paradoxical combination of silence
and magniloquence.
In this light, Seydor’s third reading of slow motion as a perception of en-
ergy that is slowed down because it has only time but not space to expand
insuggests one reason death should be the beneficiary of this technique. An
event like the Oswald killing is unrepeatable, and the chance of filming or
taping it is extremely slight. Perhaps the most famous of all news footage,
the Zapruder film of the Kennedy assassination, shown on North American
television for the first time only in 1973, is exemplary. No longer news, it
hadalready become talismanic. Slowed down, blown up, and most of all re-
peated, the Zapruder film stands head and shoulders above similar moments,
like the footage of the Rodney King beating, not because the event was more
spectacular or significant, but because its meanings remain so profoundly
uncertain. The film is evidence, but despite its forensic standing, itis incon-
clusive. It is an event without a narrative, or rather with an excess of narra-
tives. As Hayden White puts it, “It is the anomalous nature of modernist
events—their resistance to inherited categories and conventions for assign-
ing them meanings—that undermines not only the status of facts inrelation
to events but also the status of the event in general” (White 1996: 21). In
slow motion or by repetition, the image expands the time of the eventto fill
the confines of television, a space not so much finite as already full. Desper-
ately seeking completion, it finds only the plenum of a spatial expansion.
Likewise the slow-motion shots—and they are never whole sequences—
in Peckinpah. In its competition with television, its pursuit of adult themes
and expanded horizons, greater explicitation and more persuasive spectacle,
cinema in the 1960s abandoned classical restraint in favor of a televisualiza-
| 210 |
C
h
ap
te
r
8
|
tion of the profilmic. This is how time is metamorphosed in the new Holly-
wood, in accordance with its rival, sister medium. Televisual flow (Williams
1974), segmented flow (Feuer 1983), as phenomenological artifact becomes
increasingly self-referential, to the point of total enclosure (White 1986).
This is the temporality into which Peckinpah’s slow motion brings us, a
televisual mode where, as Richard Dienst argues, “time is the substance of
television’s visuality, the ground of its ontology, and the currency of its econ-
omy” (Dienst 1995: 159). Dienst goes on to argue, however, that as well as
a temporal plenum (“the automatic image”), TV is capable of a fragment-
ing and exploding (“the still image”). Slow-motion corresponds to the au-
tomatic: it fills the scene with itself to such an extent that its pure presence
overtakes any meaning it might have. This is the aesthetic moment in The
Wild Bunch, but a moment that is always temporary, defined by its brevity
and by the rapid intercutting that surrounds it.
Peckinpah’s West is Einsteinian rather than Eisensteinian. As Mauro
Dorato puts it, “After all, as Einstein’s definition of simultaneity for distant
events shows, we do not have privileged epistemic access to allevents hap-
pening in the present” (Dorato 1997: 72). From where I stand, events that
happen remotely are future events, because I cannot perceive them until
their light reaches me. The obverse is also true: my present is the past of an
observer who, simultaneous with me, cannot know what happens to me un-
til after it has happened. Not time as such, but the relativist concept of the
present is a spatial concept, dependent on distance and the speed of light.
The present moment is dispersed. The possibility that the present of an
event persists, its perception in the past or future depending on the ob-
server—the victim or the distant Dutch in the shooting in the arroyo—
persuades us of the realism of Peckinpah’s montage. There is no death in
Peckinpah, only the extended present of dying. Dying takes time. It must
settle into the landscape like the rolling echo of gunfire falling back into the
ancient silence of the rocks.
Flash-forwards are rare in cinema because the future either has already
been written—the script preexists the film—or, bluntly, does not exist. Do-
rato has a name for this latter position, “the empty view of the future”: “the
essence of a present event is, not that it precedes future events, but that there
is quite literally nothingto which it has a relation of precedence” (Dorato
1997: 74), and he notes that this is the view best suited to mind-independent
theories of becoming. Thus the nonexistent future and the prescripted
| 211 |
N
eo
c
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
future are the same in this quality at least: they are independent of the ac-
tions of protagonists. Future events cannot be thought, much less displayed,
without betraying the secret of narrative cinema: that everything is either
predetermined (the film plays to its end) or nonexistent (the film breaks
down in projection), in either case removing motivation from the diegesis.
Flashbacks, however, are always motivated from inside the filmic world
(Turim 1989). The final flashback of The Wild Bunch, property of no one
character (they are all already dead) offers a montage of the old life, espe-
cially the “why not?”—the acceptance of death as a final bond of unity and
fidelity, that justifies the world of the film from within. Michael Bliss adds,
in a footnote, that this final montage emphasizes at the end that the film is
“a crafted, storytelling vehicle that creates, and fosters the continuation of,
the Bunch’s myth,” an effect doubled by reducing the final anamorphic
image within the frame as the words “The End” appear. The film, he con-
cludes, “is a mnemonic device” (Bliss 1993: 322). As machine for remem-
bering, The Wild Bunchentertains its past in flashbacks and renders itself as
gestalt in flashback, because it inhabits a world with no future.
The past exists simultaneously with the present because the present is
in the process of becoming legend. The diegetic present is not only past as
an object of perception for audiences: it presents itself as a fading into the
past of the filmic present. In that moment, a sort of event-horizon, the event
can be experienced in its full duration, savored in all its freshness, in ways,
it is implied, that subsequent lifestyles will no longer permit. Peckinpah
conveys this fullness not only by selecting the act of killing as his emblem of
the fullest moment of being, but by extracting from death the last drop, the
finest vintage, of sensibility. It is to his credit that it is killing, not death, that
focuses his attention, for unlike Heideggerian being-toward-death, killing
is an act undertaken in the films as a conscious decision and in full knowl-
edge of the responsibilities it brings. This is what makes the flashbacks func-
tion: each flashback takes us to a memento mori, and each functions as a
present simultaneous with the diegetic present of the main narrative, but
one that is being perceived in that present as a past. The flashbacks, like the
slow-motion shots, are part of an extended present with roots deep in the
past, but whose future is only a memory.
Unlike televisual frames, which can be repeated by pausing at the mix-
ing desk or on the beta-cart, and so can be considered live performance at
the moment of transmission, and also unlike the photograph, which holds
| 212 |
C
h
ap
te
r
8
|
one instant outside of its own time, the cinematic freeze is a temporal pro-
cess executed in the optical printer, after the moment of exposure and be-
fore the film arrives at projection. The cinematic freeze is not a photograph,
because it has a definite duration. When Baudrillard writes, in a phrase that
seems to evoke Peckinpah’s long sequences of journeys in the Western films,
that “The unfolding of the desert is infinitely close to the timelessness of
film” (Baudrillard 1988: 1), he is incorrect, in that film, unlike the photo-
graphic art that Baudrillard practices, is a durational art. Bazin comes far
closer when he writes “It is easy to say that because the cinema is movement
the western is the cinema par excellence” (Bazin 1971: 141). Movement of
sound and image is what makes time in the film: arresting that movement
does not expose its putatively constitutive static elements—the still image,
the photograph, the photogram, the moment of timelessness—but the tra-
jectory of movement.
In the title sequence for The Wild Bunch, the freezes might be read as
the arrest of a vector in a way that exposes the underlying algorithm. Per-
haps the theme of the film can be retraced to William Carlos Williams’s
summing of previous American history in the apparent contradiction be-
tween President Lincoln’s popular appeal and his assassination. “The bru-
talizing desolation of America up to that time,” he suggests, arises out of a
kind of psychic amputation: “Failing of relief or expression, the place tor-
mented itself into a convulsion of bewilderment and pain” (Williams 1956:
235). For the Williams of “In the American Grain,” the vice (or “immor-
ality” in the phrase cited as epigraph for this chapter) that underlies the
violence of American history from the first conquistadors to Lincoln’s as-
sassination was Puritanism, a refusal of joy, which, coupled with the terror
it nurtured among its devotees toward the country itself, brought about that
peculiar combination of sentimentality and bewildered, tragic aggression
that scars the characters of Peckinpah’s West. The filmmaker’s theme might
be read as the anguished pursuit of a joy unavailable to the psychic forma-
tion of his characters—the still dissatisfied satiation, that glut of the wrong
pleasures, in Mapache’s face as he feasts before the final shoot-out. But the
theme is not the vector, rather a perspective on it. The vector, here, is com-
bined of the southward-tending geography of the diegesis, the narrative
momentum, and the circular (and no longer, as in Eisenstein, spiraling) spa-
tialization achieved through the films’ extension of American montage into
the assemblage of points of view and temporalities.
| 213 |
N
eo
c
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
But at the close of Pat Garrett and Billy the Kid,where Garrett’s assassi-
nation ends in a freeze-frame, the dynamic has changed. Both sequences
bleach out their moments, but the ending of Pat Garrettis a defeated one for
sure. Dukore believes that “the independent spirit of Billy symbolically de-
stroys the dependent, emotionally drained man that Garrett, by killing him,
has become” (Dukore 1999: 138). But it is Poe, the hired hand of the Santa
Fe ring, who orchestrates Garrett’s death, and he does so after Garrett has
threatened to break a contract and damn the law. It is legality that drains,
and legality that sanctions, the deaths of both protagonists. There is no free-
dom left. So the freeze-frame has nothing to do with the analysis of the
vector, and everything to do with its arrest. The two sequences stand at op-
posite poles of the analytic of the vector in neoclassicism. In The Wild Bunch,
we observe the conditions under which motion becomes possible, or more
precisely necessary. In the closure of Pat Garrett and Billy the Kid,we are in-
vited as witnesses to the conditions under which motion is no longer pos-
sible. To Peckinpah’s credit, those conditions are not causally determined by
death but by the loss of freedom between 1881 and 1909, the two dates iden-
tified in the film’s opening montage. Freedom exists as a historical franchise,
never as a personal possession. Freedom is a quality of a society, until the so-
ciety turns its back on freedom in favor of the law. It is a thoroughly Amer-
ican ideology, and one that excludes equally the outlaw and the lawman.
It is also a mythic account of the moment at which the open frontier be-
comes the bounded nation. Here time becomes a closed totality, premised
on a finality that is ultimately void. The infinite must always be social. The
sublime, by contrast, being asocial, has only the nameless heart of the con-
temporary to address, and it must address it as at once monumental and ab-
sent. The unwitnessed moment of Ground Zero, center of the Hiroshima
blast, is that terminal instant of deafening silence and blinding light that
gives the annihilating fullness of the posthistorical an image, however ob-
scure. Only one form can mediate the incommunicable and communicate
immediately. Refusing at once historicity and futurity, the posthistorical
commodity is simultaneously full and empty, universal and particular. Peck-
inpah, with his Old West, antitechnological, anti–big business ethos, will
not accept that logic, and as a result cannot function within the emergent
“postmodern sublime.”
Instead, Peckinpah investigates the expansion of simultaneity as a par-
adoxical moment, the event as expanding, to all intents and purposes end-
| 214 |
C
h
ap
te
r
8
|
lessly, but within a loosely but nonetheless unmoveably circumscribed pe-
riod of time. If we were convinced by the notion of Peckinpah as Heideg-
gerian—in the sense that he is interested at once in the fading of presence
and the being-toward-death—we would nonetheless need to acknowledge
that cinema is for him the means by which the fading moment is brought
back, through artful engineering, into the present that has abandoned it.
Thus he retains the sensibility of loss, because he understands that this faded
fullness is still perceptible in cinema. At the same time, loss in Peckinpah
also and with familiar abruptness turns into frenzy, a frenzy of violence that
arises from enclosure. There is an early foreshadowing of Peckinpah’s melo-
dramatic direction of actors in the cupboard scene in Broken Blossoms,when
Lillian Gish screamed so loudly in rehearsals that the police were called
(Gish 1969: 221). For Gish’s character, there is no escape, no future, and the
inevitable psychological result is frenzy. When futurity is written out of pos-
sibility, the result is a self-destructive violence: the only freedom left when
there is no hope.
Bazin’s dictum—that the cinema, the Western, and movement are of
one essence—is true only of a cinema in which stasis is not a constant state
and underlying possibility. The random, unmotivated freezes of Pat Garrett
and Billy the Kid’sopening minutes are significant in their randomness: they
threaten all action with sudden stillness, the end of life, activity, movement,
and cinema all together in the demise of the West. In its classical phase, the
Western was the privileged site for the vector as its own reward. Hence its
utopian function in Le Crime de M. Lange.But when it confronts the end of
westward expansion and the consolidation of nationhood and commerce,
the space in which the vector might operate shrinks to the scale of its human
protagonists, and more especially to the scale of their shrinking horizons. In
Peckinpah, the vector shifts from the macroscopic, universalist spiral of
Eisenstein toward a microscopic dissection of the impossibility of freedom.
In these films, the vector becomes an exploration of closed space and
shrunken time, circular in The Wild Bunch,a vortex in Pat Garrett and Billy
the Kid.In the movement from finite mobility in total space to infinite mo-
bility in enclosed space, the vector becomes infinitesimal, at first an im-
plosion of auto-destruction, and thence, in the later film, a black hole into
which time disappears, drained in the same way color is drained out of the
world between 1889 and 1909. Confronted with the collapse of the Amer-
ica he dreamed of, or rather with the fact that it had already collapsed before
| 215 |
N
eo
c
la
s
s
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
he could even grasp it, Peckinpah arranges a new mode of cinema, a spiral
inward in which all instances of authentic being are constantly swallowed
up. The surface of the film is the event horizon of this maelstrom, which ex-
plains the fluctuating gravity of time, the tides and surges we feel as we move
from temporality to temporality, within and between events. So Peckinpah’s
neoclassicism confronts the possibility of the sublime with the actuality of
killing, and in so doing preserves the only time that remains available, a
present that is neither perpetual nor unchanging, but which holds itself to-
gether, like a bubble supported by the forces of its own collapse.
Perhaps The Wild Bunchis overrated. Its mawkish presentation of the
buddy system is as crass as the worst of Hawks, and the flashbacks both tor-
tuous and obvious. Pat Garrett and Billy the Kidis the greater film, in poten-
tial at least, for it will be forever incomplete, because, despite the clumsiness
of the cutting and much of Dylan’s score, despite the overly overt symbol-
ism and the thin direction of Kristofferson, it has the courage of its own de-
spair at a moment at which no other response was adequate. In the end it was
neither the Vietnam War nor the defeat in Vietnam that destroyed Peckin-
pah’s longed-for America, the perceived theme of The Wild Bunchat the time
of its release: it was the fact that in the long term neither of them mattered.
By 1973, the whole distressing conflict was reduced to the amnesia of polit-
ical memoir, and even the righteous anger of The Wild Bunchwould by then
have been a melodramatic response. The dull cycling around of the unwill-
ing hunter and the unmoving game in ever decreasing circles with less and
less freedom to choose: this is a great and lasting tribute to the North Amer-
ica of Gerald Ford.
At this juncture, Peckinpah’s greatest special effect was to maintain the
illusion that it might still be possible to make a political film in Hollywood.
His greatest moral achievement was to have done so without descending into
the nihilism of his characters, a sin he would reserve for his later films. There
is no tragedy in the lack of a final, definitive cut of the two films discussed
here. On the contrary, that they are, in Duchamp’s phrase, “definitively un-
finished” is intrinsic to the aesthetic of the vortex, the vector condemned to
an inward spiral, to the exploration of infinitesimal durations.
| 216 |
C
h
ap
te
r
8
|
Hollywood Baroque: The Steadicam Years
If I could just create the kind of world I’d really like to live in... I
wouldn’t be there.
—Robert Creeley1
Illusion, Delusion, Collusion
More and more it seems possible to descry a lynchpin moment of new Amer-
ican cinema in Purple Rain.Not only does Prince’s film bring the nightmare
Oedipal dialectic of Charles Burnett’s Killer of Sheepto the entertainment
media; not only does it render the incoherent, fractured narrative of Haile
Gerima’s Harvest 3000in popular form; but it gathers the forces of film
about its moments of spectacle, subordinating an already picaresque narra-
tive to the sudden coherence of sound and image in sublime moments of
performance, to recreate as pure decoration the melodrama of its most ob-
vious thematic model, in terms of production history, stardom, narration,
and camp, the Judy Garland version of A Star Is Born.
The film exists as a series of alternating surfaces: the show, the fetish,
the spectacle, the soundtrack album, the star, the performance, the auteur—
and most of all the triumphant coincidence of all of them in the production
numbers. The articulation of sound and image across the shot-reverse-shot
cutting, so unnecessarily obvious, constructs the relation between star per-
sona and audience as antagonistic, or at best agonistic, deferring the utopian
moment of the performer’s ecstatic integration with the crowd, the crowd’s
with the performer, into the invisible realm of the score. Already a nostalgic
reconstruction of the Minneapolis scene of the late 1970s, Purple Rain,that
9
NEOBAROQUE FILM
| |
narcissistic exploration of an already fantastic world, is an early monument
of the Hollywood baroque.
Purple Rainsold 205,000 soundtrack albums on its day of release (Prince
2000: 135). The Wagnerian ambition for cinema to become a Gesamtkunst-
werk,a total multimedia experience, has not been lost: it has been dispersed.
The film offers only one part of an experience, the second part of which is
provided by the soundtrack, promoted as a discrete item. Prince of course
also provided the score for the 1980s’ third-biggest grossing film: Batman
(fig. 9.1), stylistically and in terms of cross-media promotion the typical
baroque movie. The vistas of backpacks, fast-food, and breakfast cereal tie-
ins opened up by Star Wars at the end of the 1970s reached a finely honed
plateau in the marketing of the Tim Burton/Anton Furst adaptation of
Frank Miller’s Dark Knight.DC Comics, a Warner product line, had taken
a market lead in the conversion of the comic book into the graphic novel,
signposted by the 1986 publication of Miller’s The Dark Knight Returnsand
Alan Moore and Dave Gibbons’s Watchmen.Carrying the juvenile market of
the comics into the “mature” zone of gothic imagery, enigmatic narrative,
and vivid graphic language, the graphic novels of the early ’80s brought a
new sensibility to ’70s’ attempts to capitalize on figures like Superman.
Camp and irony met with the future-noir established as a newly character-
istic form of science fiction by John Carpenter’s dirty, cluttered, cheapo star-
ship Dark Starand canonized in Lawrence G. Paull’s production design for
Ridley Scott’s Blade Runner(Bukatman 1997; Bruno 1987; Sammon 1996).
At the same time, the success of horror films in the wake of The Exorcist
brought an admixture of sadism and an attraction to the gruesome, centered
on previously marginal terrains of the Batman mythos like Arkham Asylum.
The new comics not only restored Batman to credibility, they freed the
masked avenger from the economic and psychic limitations of a single actor
(as already flagged in the “mobile signifier” James Bond identified by Ben-
nett and Woollacott 1987). Moreover, as the first baroque moved from
feudal personification to the more abstract geography of El Dorado or Par-
adise, so the neobaroque moves away from the promotion of fantasy an-
chored in the star persona to situate it in the diegetic universe from which
it springs—Gotham City—and which it further promotes and develops.
Hollywood’s promotion of diegetic worlds like Star Trek’s Federation Space
not only reconfigured the production of fantasy, it enabled and encouraged
immersion in the myth delinked from the specific film text. Toys, computer
| 218 |
C
h
ap
te
r
9
|
games, fan fiction and Web sites, novelizations, comics, soundtrack and
concept albums, fashion accessories, and collectibles, many of them manu-
factured by wings of the same horizontally integrated corporation, extended
the reach of the event film while reducing the cinema premiere to the status
of product launch for a raft of brands on a synchronized lifestyle marketing
strategy (Meehan 1991).
Purple Rainnot only opened the door to African American cinema for
African American audiences: it refocused Hollywood on its lost black audi-
ence. Prince, at the height of his creative and popular bent, could bring
withhim the African American and gay audiences, and at the same time re-
configure Batman’s Furst-designed body armor as the latest incarnation of
Brando’s leather jacket in The Wild One: the concretized wish of the white
urban youth who formed Hollywood’s core audience, to inhabit, as literally
as possible, a black skin. This is only one of dozens of ways that Hollywood
undertook to create a fantastic setting in which the apartheid nature of the
North American nation-state could be resolved. The multiracial deck of the
| 219 |
N
eo
b
a
ro
qu
e
F
i
lm
|
| Figure 9.1 |
Batman:Anton Furst’s designs for Gotham city stay in the mind long after the plot is forgotten.
Courtesy BFI Stills, Posters, and Designs.
starship Enterprise showed the potential for harnessing popular utopianism
to the manufacture of profit. A specific task of the Hollywood baroque is to
bring wholeness, a healed and healing world that runs against the acknowl-
edgment of difference.
At the same time, as Biskind notes, “Like The Godfather, The Exorcist
looked ahead to the coming Manichean revolution of the right, to Regan
nattering about the godless Evil Empire” (Biskind 1999: 223). The enemy
of neobaroque unity is not so much plurality as the metaphysical evil that
most clearly emerges in the mainstream horror film after The Exorcist but
also, as Barry Keith Grant observes, in the yuppie nightmare cycle of the
1980s and ’90s (Grant 1998: 280), distinguishing them from the screwball
comedy that inspired so many of them. This binary opposition of Good and
Evil leads toward both the pursuit of sublimity and the profusion of motifs.
The neobaroque is enmeshed in intrigue, passions, grotesques, a fascination
with primal forces of water and electricity, an unstable, even violent rush to
eclecticism, a shotgun marriage of reason and irrationality, a rage for free-
dom in a period of domination. More turbid than turbulent, that era extends
back into the 1970s, when the movie brats began their assimilation into the
reformed Hollywood system. In the first years of the twenty-first century,
we have not yet moved beyond that tortured effervescence. The idea of
thebaroque has connotations of excess, decadence, a falling off from over-
ripeness. Though it moves between fetor and ecstasy, its roiling, yearning
activity should indicate that these qualities are not ends in themselves, nor
things to be aspired to, but moments of a more central dialectic between
wholeness and proliferating differences, totality and emergence, global
power and the micropolitics that escape it.
Thomas Elsaesser summarizes the attributes of the “New Hollywood”
under four headings: a new generation of directors, new marketing strate-
gies, new media ownership and management styles, and new technologies
of sound and image reproduction (Elsaesser 1998b: 191). Of these latter,
none is so immediately revealing for this enquiry as the steadicam. The
twenty-minute process shot that opens Brian de Palma’s Snake Eyes (1998)
(fig. 9.2)contains everything we need to know about the film that limps af-
ter it. The central structure is already clear from the way in which the cam-
era is restricted to the point of view of Nicolas Cage: he is being lied to, and,
not quite incidentally, he is lying to himself. De Palma’s bravura shot, mim-
| 220 |
C
h
ap
te
r
9
|
ing a reel-long take (though equally clearly the product of digital editing) is
not entirely without purpose. Throughout the movie we will flash back to
this sequence, unraveling its tricks, its illusions, its red herrings. A decora-
tive flourish becomes the structural principle of the film itself.
It takes chutzpah to open with a shot like this after Altman’s stunning
parody of the mobile crane shot in the opening sequence of The Player.Since
Altman’s film the knowing audience is party to the tricks, which depend on
that knowingness for their spectacular functions. Now that the audience
grants de Palma a postmodern and ironic permission, the gratuitousness of
this elaborate maneuver becomes the rationale not only for the shot itself
but for the whole film. Our job, as viewers, is to be witnesses to the elabo-
ration of spectacle. Contemporary cinema, for reasons both commercial
and ideological, offers itself to a double audience, one that succumbs to the
spectacle and one that appreciates it. The bulk of any given audience will
enter the film with this double vision in place, pleased to be connoisseurs of
effects and their generation, but equally delighted to be suckers for the
| 221 |
N
eo
b
a
ro
qu
e
F
i
lm
|
| Figure 9.2 |
Snake Eyes:Describing space by navigation, not analysis, de Palma’s Steadicam roves between omniscience
and point of view, lying and lying to itself. Courtesy BFI Stills, Posters, and Designs.
duration, enjoying both spectacular technique and the spectacle itself, illu-
sion and the machinery of illusion.
Cleverly providing himself with an Aristotelian unity of place and time
(the boxing stadium in Atlantic City, the ticking clock), de Palma sets him-
self the problem of delivering all necessary back-story in audiovisual terms
that can be naturalized in the diegesis. The hypervisible, hyperaudible pro-
tagonist bedeviled with delusions is the willing victim of a charade, a mas-
sive event designed for the sole purpose of deceiving him. The theme has
occupied de Palma over a large part of his career (Blow Outand Body Double
spring instantly to mind). Nor of course is de Palma alone here: the intri-
cate, obsessive, and if necessary total manipulation of reality to secure an
illusion, the willingness of its victims, and often enough the tragic conse-
quences of piercing it, form the single most popular topic of the Hollywood
baroque, from Sex, Lies, and Videotapeto Schwarzenegger’s The Last Action
Hero, Total Recall, and True Lies, from House of Gamesto The Truman Show.
Our double role as integrated onlookers is enshrined in the complexity of
the shot, in which we shift fluidly from panorama to point of view, between
sharing and observing the illusory nature of his experience. In fact, the pro-
tagonist is alone in failing to perceive the construction of his world: to
everyone else, including the other actors whose unnecessarily camp perfor-
mances ought to give the game away, the artifice is not only transparent but
heavily signaled at every turn.
Illusion, then, is not only a spectacle: the spectacular collusion in its
construction, and the spectacular innocence of protagonists who cannot
perceive its artificiality combine in an entirely artificial diegesis. Truisms of
the contemporary well-made script—there should be no exposition that
cannot be accommodated into the diegesis, and no loose ends—have be-
come sufficient qualities for a baroque film since William Goldman’s script
for The Sting. Here the qualities of vraisemblanceand probability are sus-
pended in favor of the construction of a transparently artificial script of al-
gorithmic elegance.
Classically, the story is a ritual construction intime that works through
the conflictual structures of reality and finds for them a magical resolution.
But the baroque story in its purest form is a purely abstract construction of
time. In this new mode, stories seek not to control but to imitate nature.
This imitation needs to be understood not as nineteenth-century realism
| 222 |
C
h
ap
te
r
9
|
but as sixteenth-centuryImitatio, a concept Rosamund Tuve characterizes
as possessing three levels. At the first level,
the artifact was designed to please on grounds of its formal excellence rather than
by its likeness to the stuff of life.... On [the] second level images must assist in
Imitation conceived as involving the artist’s orderingof Nature, and his interpre-
tation must have coherence... on a third level: Imitation as truth-stating, as
didactically concerned with the conveying of concepts—not simply orderly pat-
terns but what we should commonly call “ideas” and “values.” (Tuve 1947: 25)
The blockbuster movie does indeed, in its elaboration of “right artificiality,”
produce just such ritual incantations of unexceptionable truisms: do right,
don’t mess with nature, look after your own. These truths are open to ideo-
logical analysis, but such analysis can scarcely deliver more interesting re-
sults than that many of our most successful movies have themes as banal as
the vade mecumsof the sixteenth century. But such Eisensteinian images are
not the point of the film, any more than the desultory narratives over which
they are stretched, for example, in Jan van Bont’s Twister. The point is that
such ideological motifs, such clichés, provide the basis for the intricate
weaving of spectacle and narration into a braided web on whose embroidery,
abstract as a Bach fugue, the audience will sit in final arbitration. As we reach
the end of a film like Snake Eyes,we should survey the whole plot as if it were
a knot garden, a spatial orchestration of events whose specific attraction is
its elaboration of narrative premise into pattern, its reorganization of time
as space.
The intrinsically decorative structuring of narrative, the extrusion of
elaborations and fugal variations from basic premises, form part of the fun-
damental spatializing project of the Hollywood baroque. In the opening se-
quence of Snake Eyes, camera mobility and plotting are synonymous, both
contrapuntally constructing elaborations on the motif of spectacle (boxing,
policing, life) as illusion. In Strange Days,a film only slightly more elaborate
than Snake Eyes, there are few shots in which the image is not at least re-
framed, and far more frequently caught in the pirouettes and rotations of
Matthew F. Leonetti’s hallmark steadicam cinematography. The character-
istic establishing shot of Bigelow’s millennium movie, as in films as various
as Super Mario Bros. and Fatal Attraction, not only features fluid camera
| 223 |
N
eo
b
a
ro
qu
e
F
i
lm
|
movement but flamboyantly crowded mise-en-scènes packed with more in-
cident than any single viewing could take in, held in extravagantly deep fo-
cus. The effect is in some ways like that described by Dai Vaughan in the
Lumières early films: “The unpredictable has not only emerged from the
background to occupy the greater portion of the frame; it has also taken
sway over the principles” (Vaughan 1990: 65). But the difference is that,
where the Lumières and all subsequent realists leave space in frame for the
contingent, the Hollywood baroque orchestrates the entire fabric of the
film. In Fatal Attraction’s nightclubs, like the enriched cityscapes of the re-
mastered Star Wars trilogy, it no longer matters whether the protagonists
are ciphers like Luke Skywalker or tormented personae like Michael Douglas:
the diegesis has engulfed them in its own dynamic. Both narrative and styl-
istics have been subordinated to the exploration of the world of the film. If
classical cinema operates in time, as a linear construct whose narration and
stylistics focus on the exposure of the story, the baroque takes time as its raw
material.
In the Hollywood baroque, film is no longer a time-based medium (a
function now occupied by television) but the medium of movement. Spa-
tialization takes over from narrative the job of managing the film’s dynam-
ics. Movement here is sculptural, architectural, or geographical rather than
temporal, and space itself is malleable. Classical decoupage—establishing
shot, two-shot, shot-reverse shot—no longer governs because, with one
swooping sequence-shot, we can establish the diegetic space without stabi-
lizing it according to the 180°rule. The entrances into the nightclubs in Pulp
Fictionand GoodFellas mobilize the diegetic space itself, much as Gotham
City is mobilized in Tim Burton’s Batman. Where the destabilization of
space once was restricted to the generic construction of the nightmare in
horror films and such cognate scenes as the grand finale of High Plains
Drifter,the Hollywood baroque needs no subjective alibis to explain its lack
of equilibrium.
So fundamental to the Hollywood baroque is this motion that the oc-
casional descent into more formally classical structures, such as the shot-
reverse-shot dialogue scenes that punctuate Snake Eyes,seem flat, talky, and
crude. The regression to classical cutting appears symptomatic of uncer-
tainty rather than austerity, lack of vision rather than clarity, indetermi-
nacyrather than symmetry. Some similar feeling obviously dogs Bigelow
inStrange Days, a film whose shot-reverse-shot dialogue scenes are always
| 224 |
C
h
ap
te
r
9
|
framed against mobile back projections and crowd scenes, frequently con-
structed by inserting cutaways into what would otherwise be fluid camera
movement through diegetic space.
Immobility now strikes us as false because it belongs to an emphatically
narrative cinema. Though narrative resurfaces in the baroque, like shot-
reverse-shot structures, it appears as borrowings, residues, homages, re-
flexes, regressions, alibis, and quotations. The baroque’s central tendency
derives from a parallel genealogy in realist cinema. Coppola’s and Scorsese’s
investigations of Italian American culture and Spike Lee’s explorations of
African American neighborhood life draw on and extend the realist para-
digm, not least because they diminish the role of narrative in favor of ex-
ploring the diegesis. These films emphasize the spatial in residual narrative
structures, especially in Scorsese’s typically deranged and humbled salva-
tion scenes. Nonetheless, the point of films like Do the Right Thingand The
Godfather is not how their protagonists acquire the values of their commu-
nities, but how those communities reproduce themselves. Even Raging Bull
and GoodFellas have less to do with the shock of enforced innocence with
which the heroes gaze back at the world in the final shot than with the mes-
merized gaze into alien worlds that the films evoke in their spectators.2
Vagueness
This spatialization process is carried through into the design of stereophony
and multitracking in contemporary Hollywood. This needs to be carefully
distinguished both from the “deep-focus sound” Rick Altman (1994) finds
in Citizen Kane’s appropriation of radio drama techniques, and from Robert
Altman’s realist use of multiple microphones in the ensemble-cast movies of
the 1970s (Schreger 1985). In the baroque cinema, it is not simply a ques-
tion of multitrack recording, but of a process in which the initial cacophony
is reconstructed in such a way as to guide the auditor’s attention from level
to level—as for example in the extraordinarily engineered synchronizations
of voice-over, dialogue, wild-track, and skillfully remastered pop theme in
the scene in GoodFellasin which Ray Liotta’s wife first meets the mafia wives.
Altman’s soundtracks for Nashville, A Wedding,and M*A*S*Hbelong to a re-
alist aesthetic of synchronized location recording. Tom Fleischman’s sound
designs for Scorsese, Lee, Demme, and Sayles, by contrast, produce their
effects by creating not so much a soundscape to explore as a guided tour
through the diegesis (Fleischman 1994). Here the mobilization of the ear is
| 225 |
N
eo
b
a
ro
qu
e
F
i
lm
|
accomplished, as it is in the use of deep-focus crane shots through crowded
mise-en-scènes, by the strict subordination of apparent excess to the overall
trajectory of the film, frequently through the use of hyperamplified motifs
like David Lynch’s fans, drips, and hissings. Where the realist aesthetic en-
gages us as arbiters, the baroque recruits us as collaborators. The sequence
shot with its characteristic combination of structured multitracking, stag-
ingin depth, deep focus, and mobile camera is the central device of this
recruitment.
There is a sequence in Robert Rodriguez’s Desperadoin which the Mari-
achi, having wiped out Brucho’s men in the bar, staggers out into the street
followed by the last survivor of the carnage. The sequence, lasting 2 min-
utes and 3 seconds, is composed of 47 shots. Since the first shot lasts 20 sec-
onds, the average shot length for the remainder of the sequence is 2.2
seconds, with some important variation in the rhythms of the shots and their
relation to the beat and the lyrics of the Los Lobos song (“Don’t look back,
into the strange face of love”) on the soundtrack. The sequence opens with
the camera zooming in to the door of the bar as it opens and the Mariachi
walks out; dollying out, racking focus, and panning left to follow him out of
frame before dollying in and panning slightly further left to pick up his pur-
suer; dollying out, panning left again, and racking focus to follow him out
of frame. The shot is accompanied by the jangling spurs of the Mariachi,
synchronized throughout the sequence to his movements, and the duller
thud of his pursuer’s footsteps, which, unlike the spurs, will be drowned out
in the rest of the sequence by the score. Throughout the process shot back-
grounds are kept in focus. The next twelve shots are composed in depth
along the axis of the sidewalk, save one shot, which crosses the line to es-
tablish the urgency of the scene as a build-up to action, and adding that
slight edge of vertigo which helps both engage the audience and establish
the half-mystical 360°perception of the Mariachi.
At this juncture, we move out of the axis of the sidewalk: only the con-
tinuity of the score keeps us alert to the contiguity of the spaces. Carolina is
crossing the road, causing two cars to ram into one another, with a jump cut
along the axis of vision adding to the sense of impact. The score drops in vol-
ume during an instrumental passage to allow the soundtrack to focus on the
crash, then powers up with the vocal line as we move to a profile shot of
Carolina that brings us back into the sidewalk axis, then her view of the
Mariachi, then his of her. A micronarrative of reaction shots establishes a
| 226 |
C
h
ap
te
r
9
|
relationship, while the major plotline, the pursuit, heads to climax. Here the
cutting is faster, and includes the zoom shot, while the score drowns out
diegetic sound until the climactic gunfire. The sequence ends with six shots
taken from below of the Mariachi’s reaction to the death of the pursuer, with
Carolina holding, helping, and taking him away in cross-faded jump cuts
concluding with an empty sky and fast fade to black.
Desperadodoes not need uninterrupted process shots to establish the
mobility of space that so obsesses the Hollywood baroque. We are guided
here as so often in our explorations of diegesis by the centrality of a specific
consciousness that is not entirely embodied in the protagonist but tends to
gather in the space around them. In the opening shot, for example, we are
granted a look into the eyes of the Mariachi, and we simultaneously see that
he is being followed. In classical composition, that knowledge would con-
note omniscient narration. But when the Mariachi reacts to the presence of
Carolina, we realize, with gathering momentum, that this omniscience be-
longs to the Mariachi. In this way, the Hollywood baroque uses the conven-
tions of establishing shots and intercutting not to establish an external view,
but to create an ambivalent space in which we may or may not share con-
sciousness with a protagonist. This doubleness is a dialectical structure, in
which, once again, we are both participants and spectators, internal and ex-
ternal to the action, while the space of the action itself becomes doubled as
on the one hand the objective reality of omniscient narration and on the
other the subjective and therefore potentially illusory space of the protago-
nist’s consciousness (a possibility pursued to extreme effect in Memento).
This dialectical construction of fluid spaces and mobile interactions be-
tween characters and audiences is a “narcissistic” space, since its charac-
teristic is, as with the centering of the soundtrack on the sound effect of
synchronized spurs, to organize the space, both auditory and eventually vi-
sual, around the natural vision but also the peripheral awareness, the omni-
directional sensitivity, ultimately the global consciousness of the hero. That
sense of mystical union with the environment is of course a strategic ele-
ment in the construction of the noble savage, and an important element in
contemporary New Age orientalism.
The lyrics to the score of Desperadoadd a further ambiguity in a clash of
subjectivity and address—who is speaking, and to whom, or are we eaves-
dropping on an internal monologue? This is one of the characteristically
unclosed elements typical of the neobaroque’s love of movement, and one
| 227 |
N
eo
b
a
ro
qu
e
F
i
lm
|
that leads to further loss of equilibrium. One of the most significant diffi-
culties lies in resolving spatialized narratives, leading to the ambiguous
and ambivalent endings of so many contemporary films. Cynically, one can
always read these as ways of keeping open the diegetic possibility for a se-
quel. But this is only part of the crisis management of a cinema that must,
commercially, come to an ending. Not only do films fade out rather than
conclude, or rely on entirely formal negotiations of completion, as in the
knot-garden model of script-based baroque cinema; certain narrative forms
that have never really addressed themselves as linear frequently reveal, as in
the closing sequence of Desperado,what seems to be one pass of a cyclical his-
tory in which the same or similar narratives will cycle forever—implicitly in
Sal and Mookie’s final scene in Do the Right Thing,explicitly in the Godfather
series. At one extreme, this will provide the universe of Star Wars, with its
serially unresolved New Age binarism of the Force and the Dark Side, while
at the other it brings the perpetually asymmetric Möbius strip of Lost High-
way(Elsaesser and Buckland 2002: 186).
Some classical films, among them Sunset Boulevard, The Cobweb, Sul-
livan’s Travels, Dodsworth, It’s a Wonderful Life, and most obviously Citizen
Kane,appear to work on similar models of depth and surface. The classical,
however, depends on a planar construction, in which each layer of depth is
distinct from the others, as in the famous sequence of Kanein which the boy
Kane and his sled, his father, and his mother and Thatcher occupy three
meticulously separated zones of the image. In a typical neobaroque shot,
mobile camerawork (and digital compositing) eliminates the cut between
layers to promote a vectoral movement totalized in the bounded world in-
side the spatial image. Then, like the deluded protagonists of Three Kings,
the audience is in place to savor the ingenuity of the artifice in which they
have been caged. Inhabiting the here and now becomes problematic, as we
confront the foregrounded recordedness of the illusion to which we are in-
vited to submit. Classical spectacle deployed a closed system of linear nar-
rative to shut down the future: the baroque marks out the limits to our
habitation of the present.
The 1999 blockbuster effects movie The Matrixcame impregnated with
the figures of the baroque. Its camerawork is for the most part less strident
than Strange Days,although the climactic chase through the apartment block
in steadicam, despite sporting more edits than Bigelow’s equivalent scenes,
functions in precisely the same way as her steadicam sequences in Strange
| 228 |
C
h
ap
te
r
9
|
Days, Point Break,and Blue Steel.In The Matrix,constant if less flamboyant
reframing characterizes even dialogue scenes and delivers pyrotechnic
steadicam and process shots, including a hallmark lightning zoom (derived
from the Hong Kong action cinema) on the God-shot (from the ceiling or
sky into the floor or roof). The film resolves its story-telling dilemma in ex-
positional shot-reverse-shot sequences by using constantly mobile back-
projections, notably in a sequence in a car on the way to visit the Oracle,
where acid video colors throw the reality of the city—disembodied by the
lack of street sound—into question. The multilayered soundtrack again
uses a hyperamplified motif—the ringing of telephones signaling connec-
tion to and escape from the computer simulation of the title—to guide the
auditor through the spatialization of the diegesis as soundscape. Other mo-
tifs, like the sound of wipers on the office window during the firing scene
early on, similarly oversignal their function, flagging the later possibility of
escape via the window-cleaners’ cradle in the following scene.
This oversignaling clearly refers us to the film’s referential structure,
less to the cyberspace of internet than to that of computer games, constantly
evoked in the use of mobile phones to guide protagonists through the mazes
of the city. This relation between the operator and the protagonist also
informs the relation between God-shots and point-of-view shots, notably
again in the early sequence that culminates in a composite of a cell-phone
tumbling down the canyon between skyscraper facades. Editing forms a
crux in the baroque: how and where is it possible to cut a sequence shot
whose motivation lies in its subjectivity? With the addition of an operator,
the double motivation becomes clearer than it was in the example from
Desperado: it belongs with the double-vision of the player. Here the dia-
lectical relation of fetishist and voyeur is no longer at the core of the film,
having been superseded by the position of the narcissist. The dialectical
relation between the sucker and the connoisseur is itself doubled in that
relation between the protagonist in the game and their controller, the game-
player. Hence the possibility exploited thrice in the film of mapping God-
shots into points of view.
The use of mobile camera has the recessional sensibility of a Vermeer
raised on The Maltese Falcon. The opening sequence, Neo’s first meeting
with Morpheus and the scene of Morpheus’s torture feature strongly fore-
grounded blocks of shade or color—the backs of chairs, coats, telephones—
forcing awareness of the depth of the image. Balanced against these
| 229 |
N
eo
b
a
ro
qu
e
F
i
lm
|
compositional devices, the parallax enhances continuities between grada-
tions of depth rather than, as in the more obvious use of diopters, their in-
dependence from one another. The motif of fluid instability—the liquid
flame that pours out from the elevator shaft during the raid to rescue Mor-
pheus, the rippling glass wall of the skyscraper as the helicopter plunges into
it—establish the link between mobility and illusion. The moment in which
Neo, having realized his powers, flexes the walls around him after assimilat-
ing Agent Smith echoes the abstract presentation of the Matrix as the space
between letters and pixels on the computer screen (a motif that picks up
from Blade Runner’s endlessly enlargeable photograph a dream of the arti-
fact as complex as reality). Though the narrative wants us to puncture the il-
lusion, it is illusion we came to witness. The film’s liquid instability enacts
that contradiction.
Even those who are not science fiction buffs find the lengthy exposition
of The Matrixpatronizing: Hollywood has no faith in its audience. We are
entering a period of vagueness of which The Matrixis only an early symp-
tom. The visual regime of the indecipherable has been coming for some
time. Blockbuster releases since the summer of 1998—the season of Arma-
geddonand Lost in Space—feature major scenes in which the geography of
the diegesis is radically unclear. In The Matrixthis is neatly tied into the peri-
peteias of the plotting and the diegetic theme of illusion to form a reason-
ably convincing aesthetic rationale for the ambiguity of many of the spaces.
The baroque tends toward the cloudy and disorienting, its tendency to re-
main unclosed resulting in a preference for questions to be left unanswered,
identities to be guessed at. The normative cinemas found beauty in clar-
ity—the glistening surface of spectacle, the hard edge of referential reality,
the adamant certainty of the image. Now we move toward an appreciation
of the indeterminate.
In the movement from plane to recession, we parse in a new form that
transition from tactile to visual, from the metaphysics of being to the cul-
ture of change, isolated by Wölfflin in his Principles of Art Historyas the di-
viding line between classical and baroque culture: “movement is attained
only when visual appearance supplants concrete reality” (1950: 65; see also
Wölfflin 1966). Hollywood enters a new territory of vagueness inaugurated
by doubling, encoded as illusion, and confronted as crisis: the space between
material and immaterial, turbulence and the end of history.
| 230 |
C
h
ap
te
r
9
|
Ecstasy, Totality, and the Grotesque
Kant’s beauty is always dependent on a shared taste; a materialist’s on the
synthesis of conflicting evolutions. The sublime, by contrast, speaks from
some space beyond the common sense of communicative communities. The
authoritative domain of the turbulent baroque is irrational, visionary, inter-
nal, asocial, and individual. It poses itself as the final resolution of the di-
alectic. The beauty of the normative cinema is ultimately communicative:
realism speaks through the social formation of individuality, total film from
the triumph of the state. Classicism’s superficiality is the product of the
spectacular commodity’s dominance of communication. The neobaroque,
however, turns inward to some unfixed and infeasible textual transcendent
within the surface. One avatar of this transcendence is the undecidably
vague, a misty configuration of valueless differences. Another is the com-
pletion that only awaits discovery. The neobaroque is in love with destiny.
Whereas in the classical the context determines the individual will, in
the neobaroque individual destiny conquers context. Not only is the ba-
roque protagonist individual and illusory, he (sadly, the baroque seems no
less sexist than its predecessor) is also fated. From Phenomenon to Little Man
Tate,biology as destiny returns with a vengeance—the call to become what
you already are, a genetic transcendence that depends only on recognizing
the mystery of “potential” that will allow the hero to escape both the sublu-
nary material world of his social class (Good Will Hunting) and the ideolog-
ical constraints of an illusory external control (The Matrix).
In the literature that has grown up around the parallels between the late
twentieth and seventeenth centuries (e.g., Benjamin 1977; Beverley 1993;
Buci-Glucksmann 1994; Calabrese 1992; Deleuze 1993; Maravall 1986;
Ndalianis 1998), Benjamin is alone in defending the value of the term “alle-
gory.” Allegory in the contemporary baroque is that mode in which the par-
ticular is surrendered to the general and universal in the interests of a final
anagogical principle in which all specificities are demolished in the univer-
sality of the transcendent (see Hermeren 1969; Mitchell 1986; Panofsky
1962; Steiner 1981). Such is the closure of The Matrixas allegory of struggle
against the externality of social mores. The alternative is, in the predestined
yet voluntaristic miasma of the neobaroque, unthinkable.
Neo’s ecstatic revelation of his powers in The Matrixis celebrated in a
shot in which the world dissolves into fluid numbers: mere digits, revealing
the poverty of the mechanical world. Transcendence in the film Pialso takes,
| 231 |
N
eo
b
a
ro
qu
e
F
i
lm
|
in the first instance, the form of the parallel and remote universe of number,
but now it is a sacred technology of mathesis to which Max, the protagonist,
devotes himself in solipsistic studies, remote from both the Galilean “uni-
versal language” of natural mathematics and from the universal currency of
information in the global economy. This transcendence of absolute number
is also associated with a visual language that assimilates the cinematographic
to animation in step-motion sequences that, like the slow-motion of Des-
peradoand the animation of digital stills in The Matrix,dematerializes with
a mixture of dread and exhilaration, a combination that, in Pi, comes as
apremonition of an epileptic fugue. As sickness and unconsciousness, but
also as extreme life, filmic technique both describes and risks actualiz-
ingwhat it shows: the viewer’s act of viewing is undertaken in the knowl-
edgethat the flicker of projection might instigate the epilepsy it recounts.
Eliding the description of extreme states with the possibility of evoking
them, like the transports of Charles Borromeo before images of the cru-
cified Christ, leads us to the baroque’s ecstasy, its assimilation, without
will, into the transcendence of art. For Pi this enactment of ecstasis is at
its most intense in the transitional scenes that take us from climactic epi-
leptic bliss (white, silent) to recovery (black, ringing phone).
Part of Pi’s mathematical narrative premise concerns a Jewish sect for
whom the Pythagorean mysticism of the Golden Section has been assimi-
lated to the numerology of the Kabbalah, repository of the most arcane rab-
binical traditions including belief in the numerical encoding of the Bible.
Cut to Fibonacci rhythms, which it also depicts in the form of snail shells,
Golden Sections, Leonardo’s humanist torso, overlaid spirals, formulas, and
numerical series, Pi offers, to the point of incomprehensibility, to enact
mathematics as total allegorical explication of existence. But it is precisely
that totality which brings about the crisis of representation. As Max, the
protagonist, approaches the realization of the mystical unification of pure
maths, natural numbers, and the chaotic systems of the stock market, his
epilepsy becomes more and more violent, and the film veers more and more
cruelly and abruptly toward surreal, wide-angle sequences of paranoia and
self-mutilation, or alternatively through sequences of cascading edit pat-
terns toward the white light of the epileptic fugue. Picleverly orchestrates
the decorative function of its mathematical motifs in the construction of
abaroque architectonic structure in the same moment that it reveals the
| 232 |
C
h
ap
te
r
9
|
superficiality and emptiness at its heart, marked with the sign of epileptic
absence.
At the same time, like its big-budget brothers, Pi is a profoundly nar-
cissistic film. Recruiting popular histories of number (Cubitt 2000a) and
popular mysticism concerning epileptic fugue, it works up the image of des-
tiny—genetic genius—as prison to justify harrowing scenes of intimate
self-doctoring for pain, the experience that will take Max to the threshold of
an escape to the cathartic beyond. By picturing the community of seekers as
either self-interested profiteers or uncanny zealots, the baroque Pishows all
community as false—false as the rabbi’s attempt to inveigle Max into a bo-
gus Cohen family—and so restricts communication to self-communing
face to face with the unmediated cosmos. Thus Pican function as the tran-
scendental descriptor of a prison that erects its own walls in the act of de-
scribing them, while depicting a world of leaking intimacies (the sensual
sounds seeping through Max’s walls), in which the falsely normative hetero-
sexual family can become the family of destiny and self-mutilation is the
sole escape from a too dangerous because too ecstatic biological destiny.
“You’re not a mathematician: you’re a numerologist”: Max’s old profes-
sor, guardian of the absolute purity of pure math, voices a certain disgust
with the loss of classical purity. As memento mori,disgust works on the cen-
tral taboo of contemporary society, justifying the display of putrefaction
through its association with redemption, notably here in the probing of the
fetid brain with a ballpoint pen and the final cure, excising the equated mind
and brain with a power drill. Like tonguing the anal recess and its spinal in-
terface in ExistenZ,dependent on the effect of sound (the pre-echoed blurp-
ing fish of Pi), disgust proposes itself as the opposite of the self-sustaining
clarity of the classical, but equally clearly proposes that the two elements
must be understood in a single thought: there is no absolute division be-
tween the mental and physical worlds, just as there can be no divorce be-
tween desire and intelligence, materiality and transcendence.
Baroque cultures are fundamentally allegorical. Their field is not de-
scription of the real but its ordering in free-standing semantic structures
whose reference is to other semantic structures, including those that would
have been held in dialectical opposition by classicism, like the indecorous
irruption of disgust into the space of the transcendent. Such are the rustic
jokes, satyrs and priapi of the Tivoli Gardens, monument to the triumph of
| 233 |
N
eo
b
a
ro
qu
e
F
i
lm
|
artifice in the ordering of nature. In this sense, baroque allegory is rhetor-
ical, the audiovisualization of the ars bene dicendi,asking to be judged not on
its verisimilitude but the elegance of its structure and the eloquence with
which it voices “what oft was thought but ne’er so well expressed.” Films like
The Matrix, Desperado, Strange Days, and Pi share with others like Twelve
Monkeysan allegorical structure of this kind, symptomatized in the hyper-
detailing that, in a curious inversion of Bazinian realism, dematerializes the
image in its excess of signifiers and functions as an allegorical fugue on
themes of hyperreality, illusion, and the Code. At this juncture, narrative
conclusions become almost impossible because of the allegorical burdens
they have to bear. Hence the implicit tragedy of the closing lines of dialogue
in The Matrixand The Truman Show: there is no exterior to the fiction ex-
cept, perhaps, another stage set.
Baroque cultures arise as dialectical expressions of a crisis of absolute
power. The Church Triumphant of the Counter-Reformation (see Blunt
1940) and the capitalism triumphant of the end of communism both face the
crisis of the end of history. The seventeenth-century Baroque is legible as
the expression of an absolute state confronted with the crisis of its own
mode of signification. The Catholic Church, until then the central force
toward modernization in Italy, was driven by self-preservation (after the
collapse of the Mediterranean economy following the Turkish capture of
Istanbul) into the arms of Spain, whose monarchy and especially whose sys-
tems of taxation belonged to the dying feudal order, but which would be
buoyed up for a hundred and fifty years by its American gold. Caught be-
tween these forces, the Church opted for a denial of “pagan” classicism in
favor of a return to authority and discipline, sweetening the pill by aban-
doning humanist rationalism for the swooning ecstasies of Bernini and
Pozzo. And yet, as John Beverley observes, the Spanish baroque “was, like
postmodernism today, at once a technique of power of a dominant class in a
period of reaction and a figuration of the limits of that power” (Beverley
1993: 64). Both turn toward ultimate things in their pursuit of a resolution
to the crisis: toward transcendence and the sublime. Both face both ways,
toward the transcendental and toward the grotesque (see Wind 1998). Yet
both fail in their refusal of dialectics, their insistence on one side alone pos-
sessing the right.
The classical paradigm in its heyday stands in opposition to but in close
relation with the realist paradigm: the greatest achievements of the period—
| 234 |
C
h
ap
te
r
9
|
Stroheim, Keaton, Renoir, Mizoguchi—swing between the symmetries of
the classical and the openness to contingency of the realist. But even here
another lineage of modernity is apparent, the subterranean strand of the
grotesque, the surreal, the irrational that emerges, indeed, in exactly these
directors. For many, this Bataillean disorder is the emergent form of a new
and radically postmodern cultural poetics: Buci-Glucksmann calls it the
baroque. But for Benjamin, on whom she bases her argument so forcefully,
the optical unconscious reveals the verso of a normality that remains radi-
cally unchallenged by it, since this is precisely its necessary other. When the
Mariachi moves his choreographed way through the charnel house of Des-
perado,when the bullets or kickboxers stand in empty air in The Matrix,we
are treated to the interior of the classical surface. In some films, this effect
opens up the spectacle of the spectacular, introducing a near-Zen meta-
physics built on the emptiness of the commodity, a spatialization boot-
strapped out of its ephemerality as in a number of Ridley Scott’s films,
notably Gladiator.In others, like The Matrix, Casino, and Apocalypse Now,the
invitation is to navigate those nebulous internal spaces where the powers
that support the bubble of style twist in meaningless flux.
The transcendence of the Hollywood baroque belongs to a society of
power in which colonial and imperial expansion has not ended but under-
gone a novel reorganization. As the seventeenth century was the epoch of
the map, the archive, and double-entry bookkeeping, the spatial media par
excellence of the new Atlantic imperium, so is the neobaroque of databases,
spreadsheets, and geographical information systems. Information technol-
ogies are not qualitatively different from the instruments of imperial bu-
reaucracy. Steadicam navigation of indeterminate space is the spatial art of
globalization as the carved fountain was of imperialism. The neobaroque is
the stylistic turn of capitalism in the moment of its uneasy triumph, con-
fronted with the completion of its historical destiny without achieving the
justice, peace, and commonwealth it was intended to bring.
In the magical ascensions painted onto ornate domed ceilings by the
great Jesuit artist Pozzo, the world is gathered around the adoration of
splendor. Even truth surrenders to trompe-l’oeuil. The neobaroque learns
from the older not just the richness of décor, not just the instability of mat-
ter that at any time can lose its crystalline hardness and tumble into the in-
forme (as in the Trevi fountains), but also how to engineer the spectacle
about the fixed void on whose foundation alone its splendor coheres. It is the
| 235 |
N
eo
b
a
ro
qu
e
F
i
lm
|
price of baroque coherence that the subject become abject and that the ab-
ject evaporate, for coherence is the spectacle’s only true product. Once that
single leap of self-abasement and self-abnegation is made, the world or-
chestrates itself as spectacle, and spectacle articulates itself into a single
unity. In cinematic terms, the infinite is first totalized so that it can then be
unified, at which point the subject is rendered as the zero of utter emptiness.
Of its geometry, Marina Benjamin comments “The all-pervasive fractal,
twisted and inward-looking, is so utterly self-referential it replicates itself
on resolution and, since it has no frame of reference outside itself, it is in-
capable of transformation” (Benjamin 1999: 13).
This is the playfulness of the new Hollywood blockbuster movie: an ap-
peal to self-loss in the modeling of a coherent spectacle, whose offer is of
acoherence that is impossible in the contemporary world, and whose cost
isthat the diegetic world can cohere only if the spectator surrenders to ab-
jection and volatilization. For the neobaroque sublime to conquer, it must
sublimate the sense of self. The familiar abstraction of mind and body, of
observer from observed, of subject from object, here reaches a new forma-
tion: everything will be relinquished in favor of coherence. The new world
needs to be utterly absorbing: this is why special effects are so central to the
new Hollywood, and also why the neobaroque is so unafraid of displays of
mawkish emotionalism. To quote Spielberg, “The equivalent of the moth-
ership landing in Close Encounters is, in E.T., perhaps a tear out of Henry
Thomas’s eye. That was my equivalent of a super-colossal special effect”
(cited in McBride 1997: 330). Affect, thrill, shock displace themselves from
the audience to the spectacle. The vanishing point is no longer in the image
but in the rapt attention of the viewer.
Database Narrative and the Montage of Affects
Earlier avant-garde techniques for alienation concentrated on breaking up
identification with characters. The neobaroque responds by inviting iden-
tification with fictional worlds. Here the stakes are higher, in the sense that
the existence of the fictive world depends on the abnegation of the viewer.
Of course, this also means moving away from the knots of ethical distanc-
ings that were available to the classical cinema and its identifications. So, for
example, Peeping Tomwas a viable if gruesome critique of the powers of
identification; Strange Days(fig. 9.3),effectively a remake of the story if not
| 236 |
C
h
ap
te
r
9
|
of the film, is no such thing. We can only empathize with its protagonists,
not identify with them. And Bigelow’s world yields no truth, only emula-
tions and betrayals.
A new tactic emerged in the advance of minimalism in the 1960s and
’70s. Artists like Donald Judd and Carl André and musicians like Philip
Glass, Steve Reich, and Terry Riley developed a modular construction of
works from simpler primitives, run in series with minor variations. The at-
tempt there was to strip the human out of art. “The idea becomes a machine
that makes the art,” in conceptual artist Sol Lewitt’s phrase (1992: 834), al-
lowing the materials to generate their own higher levels of organization ac-
cording to structural logics established as the sole creative act of the artist.
This is not to claim a patrilineal descent for neobaroque Hollywood, which
in any case appears to have derived its new structures equally from the
emerging digital workplace and from whatever social and cultural tenden-
cies likewise informed the minimalists. Rather, it indicates a felt need for a
| 237 |
N
eo
b
a
ro
qu
e
F
i
lm
|
| Figure 9.3 |
Strange Days:empathizing rather than identifying, Bigelow’s Steadicam yields no truth, only emulations
and betrayals. Courtesy BFI Stills, Posters, and Designs.
cultural form that excluded subjectivity, and that placed truth outside the
human, in closed, rule-governed worlds.
The modular structuration of these worlds has a further impact in neo-
baroque cinema. The coherence that passes for truth exists only in modular
events, segments of the film that stand alone as discrete units, most of all
theeffects sequences. Recent films like Star Wars, Episode Two: Attack of the
Clonesmove from set piece to set piece along only the slenderest thread of
narrative, like washing on a line. Each set piece sequence acts to trigger a
rush of emotion: putting a clock on the action, staging the spin-off computer
game as sport, escaping from ghoulish caverns. The scream, the laugh, the
tear, the white knuckles, the racing pulse: the stimuli are clichés because the
emotions they elicit and that audiences seek are clichés. Market research en-
sures, as far as anything can, that expectations will be met. Of course, such
expectations derive from the past, never from the future, and so the hec-
ticoverproduction of affects is only ever repetitive of old emotions. The
clothes-line model of effects sequences held up by a perfunctory narrative
builds on Hollywood wisdom (“Don’t tell me: show me!”). Structured in ac-
cordance with the most trusted modes of narrative, each set-piece sequence
miniaturizes the older classical plot into a few minutes of film, condensing
as it simplifies the emotional content, delivering the intensified segment as
an event in itself, and building, from the succession of events, a montage of
affects that together establish the visceral goal of neobaroque entertainment.
The diegesis of the neobaroque is not only self-enclosed but self-
referential. The repetitive nature of the montage of affects is a theme for a
number of neobaroque movies, Groundhog Daybeing the most egregious ex-
ample. More significant still is the phenomenon of spatialized narrative. Lev
Manovich notes the importance of the database as an alternative source of
narrative in digital media computer games and digital installations (Man-
ovich 2001: 225–228). Daughter of the filing cabinet, the database is a de-
vice for the ordering of materials, as such intrinsic to Hollywood market
research, scriptwriting, and editing. Lévi-Strauss’s (1972) vision of narrative
as an assemblage of narratemes, each of which functions by analogy as a
card-index, was a predigital adumbration of the narrative possibilities of this
extranarrative form. Lock Stock and Two Smoking Barrels, Snatch, and The
Usual Suspectsonly appear to be narrative. In fact they are the result of one
of many possible rifles through a database of narrative events whose coinci-
dence is more structural or even architectural than temporal. Beyond the
| 238 |
C
h
ap
te
r
9
|
modernist opposition of narrative and nonnarrative, the structuring of such
films depends on the satisfaction to be had from realizing the pattern under-
lying the events, in Manovich’s terms “discovering the algorithm.” For this
to work, every loose thread must be picked up, every action matched with
another, and the submerged symmetry of the classical narrative tradition
brought to the surface to be displayed.
In this way the narration, too, becomes spectacular, as we wait for the
moment in which the various unraveled lines are knitted into a satisfying
coherence. In the process, narrative reveals the coincidences, the flukes of
chance that give us this specific version of the story, making play of the ca-
suistry that allows the manipulation of narratemes to pretend to some sort
of causality. We are not taken in by these stories. Rather the pleasure derives
from the craft with which they are put together. Like the washing-line of the
montage of affects, the construction of the database narrative is modular,
encouraging games with flashback (Memento), time travel (Twelve Monkeys),
and temporal dislocation (Pulp Fiction) to demonstrate with even more bril-
liance the command over events enjoyed by the pattern-making impulse.
The effect is to make the narrative, like the diegesis, spatial. Deprived
of causal chains of anything more than pure luck, good or bad, the protago-
nists have only to understand, as the audience must, their position in the
web of events to realize their goal. That goal, however, already exists as the
resolution of the riddle of the world they inhabit. Personal destiny coincides
with the destiny of a Hegelian world, whose task is to understand itself.
This shared ideology in turn explains an oddity in the neobaroque
that distinguishes it from the “trajectories” (Deleuze 1989: 64) of Keaton.
Keaton’s world is animated, in the sense that any object can be full of anima,
ofsoul, of its own will and whims: the playfully retreating girl revealed as—
exactly—a horse’s ass in Our Hospitality, the effervescent transformations of
Sherlock Junior.The neobaroque world is capable only of disappearing, as in
Dark Cityand The Thirteenth Floor.It may promote illusion (and thereby be
capable of revealing the truth behind the illusion), but it is incapable of be-
trayal, or any willed action, as once it was in the days of Keaton, Chaplin,
and Lloyd. Their artistry arose from the happy fault of cinematography—
its readiness to believe in appearances, and most of all, in its unappeas-
ableappetite for movement, its gullibility with respect to the self-governing
activity of its world. The world of Groundhog Dayhas no will of its own:
itexists only to force its protagonist to discover how to live in it. Even
| 239 |
N
eo
b
a
ro
qu
e
F
i
lm
|
itsdenizens are manipulable objects in the hero’s quest. Like the solitaire
player, the film moves its pieces to create an orderly pattern in which the ab-
surdity of the premise—a shuffle of the deck, a throw of the dice—abolishes
chance and clears the way for destiny.
For the fictive world to present itself as coherent, it must eradicate sub-
jectivity as the potential source of novelty. The cleanest cut is to deprive
thecharacters of futurity by endowing them instead with a fate: a foregone
conclusion that empties the future of its difference from the present. Once
it is clear that biology is destiny—as it is in different ways for the heroes
ofPhenomenonandThe Sixth Sense—the details of the story fall into their
patterns, and the purpose of subjectivity is fulfilled at the moment in which
it is absorbed entirely into the pattern of the world. With destiny, there is
noneed for anything more than the sketchiest story.
Self-doubt, for example, is no longer sufficient motivation for a narra-
tive: it is simply an obstacle to be overcome as the pattern hurtles toward
completion. Even doubt will be explained as the necessary corollary of a cer-
tain task required. The neobaroque’s spatialized narratives, with their array
of actions and consequences plotted as on a map, take the picaresque struc-
ture of the road movie to the extreme. Where a film like Vanishing Point
(“The Car. The Road. The Girl. The Shack. The End”) leaves us in no doubt
that the hero will die, it is more existentialist than nihilistic: what the char-
acter does matters. In Groundhog Day, it doesn’t. The end is already ap-
pointed. All the character needs to do is come to it. The coincidence of
personal fulfillment and absorption into the world reduces the future from
a process of hope to an object of faith. Externalizing the inward struggles
ofNeo, his shipmates aboard the Nebuchadnezzar are distinguishable only
by the quality of their beliefs. What narrative there is devolves upon that
single, efficient distinction.
Locking into a pattern at its conclusion, the database narrative reveals
its gestalt. The task of the protagonists is to realize themselves as elements
of an infinitely repeatable, enclosed horizon of rule-governed patterning.
The neobaroque hero inhabits his environment with utter omniscience like
Desperado’s Mariachi (fig. 9.4), like Brandon Lee’s character in The Crow.
The diegesis is a knowledge base, its secrets resources to be picked up and
used, like the energy and weapons in computer shoot-’em-ups. Samantha/
Charly in Renny Harlin’s The Long Kiss Goodnightis alert to the secret power
struggles of her world even though she has had her memory erased: her
| 240 |
C
h
ap
te
r
9
|
body already remembers what her conscious mind eventually recalls, that
the banal world dissimulated a double lie. Paranoia films, from the grit of
Conspiracy Theoryto the wilder reaches of X-Files: The Movieand the parody
of Men in Black,similarly have the world reveal its capacity for truth by first
shattering the illusions of the neophyte, and then requiring him to assimi-
late the new world revealed at the subliminal level of instinctive knowledge
and instinctual action. The only act of will required is the statement of be-
lief. After that, the environment (the Force) takes over. The world can real-
ize itself in the assimilation of the heroic subject.
| 241 |
N
eo
b
a
ro
qu
e
F
i
lm
|
| Figure 9.4 |
Desperado: The hero as center of a world’s consciousness; a world realizes itself in the assimilation of the
hero. Courtesy BFI Stills, Posters, and Designs.
The neobaroque is a Hegelian cinema, in the sense that its goal is not
narrative closure but the revelation of truth as destiny: “that the actual world
is as it ought to be, that the truly good, the universal divine Reason is the
power capable of actualizing itself” (Hegel 1953: 47). Perhaps it is a cinema
out of Leibniz, for whom humans’ true love of their creator
makes the wise and virtuous work for whatever seems to conform with the pre-
sumptive or antecedent will of God, and yet leaves them satisfied with what God
in fact causes to happen by his secret will... recognising as they do that if we
could sufficiently understand the order of the universe, we should find that it
surpasses all the desires of the most wise, and that it is impossible to make it bet-
ter than it is, not only for the whole in general, but for ourselves in particular.
(Leibniz 1973: para. 90, 194)
Contemporary cinema is more ambitious than contemporary philos-
ophy, but neither undertakes to understand the universe any longer. Instead,
the neobaroque builds experimental worlds in which the honest actor must
discover that “preemptive or antecedent will” that animates her world in
order to subjugate herself to it. The film world is a windowless monad, a
simple structure unafflicted by connections to the rest of the world, entirely
inward.3Where this universe distinguishes itself from Leibniz’s and Hegel’s
is in its relentless secularism. For Hegel, “World history in general is the de-
velopment of Spirit in Time,just as nature is the development of the Idea in
Space” (1953: 87). Hollywood deals in the multiple histories of multiple
worlds, and with the particular rather than the general. In its secular plural-
ism, the ambition for evolution of the Spirit has been cast aside, for it de-
mands a future that the premise of eternal repetition cannot sustain. At
thesame time, the notion of an Idea that seeks to fulfill itself in the phys-
ical world is too cold and abstract to motivate an audience. Hollywood’s
achievement in the neobaroque is to have produced a series of worlds in
which Spirit develops in space. Hence the worlds thus created are subject to
human will and structured according to the rational-irrational binary that
shapes contemporary pop psychology.
There is infinity in these enclosed monads, albeit only the infinity of the
inside of a sphere. The film world seeks an audience that will realize it by
uncovering its secret algorithm, but which will also by that act dissolve its
separate identity into the unity of the new world. Neobaroque films are not
| 242 |
C
h
ap
te
r
9
|
simply total cinema, though many exhibit characteristics of totalitarianism.
They are, as Justin Wyatt (1994) argues, extremely visual, lavishing light
onstrikingly graphical compositions. Spatializing narrative as database fits
with this attention to the illumination of the screen as pure style, a style that
moreover is as likely to motivate the storyline as to be motivated by it.
Asimage becomes composition, narrative becomes pattern, and the whole
comes to a moment of gestalt coherence. This goes counter to Kristin
Thompson’s description of cinematic “excess,” which she defines as stylistic
innovations that are motivated neither by the narrative, in the classical man-
ner, or by artistry, in the manner of the art-house film (Thompson 1986:
132–134). Thompson’s excess works against the grain of the narrative, es-
tablishing a conflict between story and an environment strongly marked by
design and composition. But such stylistic traits appear excessive only when
viewed from the grounds of a cinema presumed to be normative. In fact,
quite the opposite process is in train. In creating a world rather than a nar-
rative, the neobaroque seeks instead a circumscribed perfection removed
from history and thence from dialectical process. Of the classical cinema,
Adorno wrote, “In its attempts to manipulate the ideology of the masses the
ideology of the culture industry itself becomes as internally antagonistic as
the very society which it aims to control. The ideology of the culture in-
dustry contains the antidote to its own lie. No other plea could be made for
its defence” (Adorno 1991: 157).
Today that plea can no longer be entered. Certainly there are films that
in various ways conform to Comolli and Narboni’s (1977) “category ‘e,’” the
film that tries to present the dominant ideology but does so in a contradic-
tory way that reveals the workings of ideology itself. The most successful
films, however, succeed because they have nothing to say: no roots in the
social or the material world, alternatives to reality, neither antidotes nor
commentaries.
We might seek forebears in the European artistic and political avant-
gardes, in Jancso’s Red Psalm,with its formal, elegant epithaliamium for land
and people in revolt, in Resnais’s L’Année Dernière à Marienbad, folding its
players in layers of time. Or we might choose Welles’s Mr. Arkadin, whose
eponymous villain feigns amnesia and hires an investigator to unearth his
past so he can murder all its witnesses. Arkadin, writes Deleuze, “makes out
that he is recouping all the splits in himself into a grandiose, paranoid unity
which would know nothing but a present without a memory, true amnesia
| 243 |
N
eo
b
a
ro
qu
e
F
i
lm
|
at last” (Deleuze 1989: 113). Deleuze places the crisis of cinema history at
the end of World War II, in the European reconstruction.
The equivalent moment for the United States came later, between the
Vietnam War years that periodize U.S. cinema for so many commentators
(e.g., Wood 1986; Corrigan 1991; Cook 2000) and Reaganomics. Welles,
Resnais, Jancso, even Buñuel, that most lapsed of lapsed Catholics, explore
the persistence of the past in the present. In the windowless monads of the
neobaroque, the past has disintegrated, no more than a comforting repeti-
tion of the governing pattern—the comfort of the final scene in What
Dreams May Come. Where Leibniz and Hegel sought an end to history in
the reunion of humankind and nature, Hollywood offered an escape from
history by the subjection of hyperindividuals to artificial worlds, narcissis-
tic mirrors in which the unwilling subjects of modernity may unravel the
knot of self and disappear into the arabesques of spectacular coincidence, il-
luminated by flashes of visual, aural, and physiological shock.
Neobaroque Hollywood film is not dialectical because it eschews time.
In place of change it seeks truth, the unique, permanent, and perfect truth
of secret worlds hidden from history. Out of the milling equilibrium states
of the spectacular, the neobaroque produces pattern. For those tired of the
endless, chaotic trudge through daily life, it brings the sense of completion.
For those for whom all hope is lost and who therefore can only believe in
miracles, it produces unity out of nothingness while it annihilates the over-
burdened self.
| 244 |
C
h
ap
te
r
9
|
Digital Materials
It is swarming with planets
Time definitely repeats itself
That’s its only job
—Ed Dorn1
Metamorphoses of Narcissus
It is no longer the case that films in some way respond to, refract, express,
or debate reality or society. Mass entertainment has abandoned the task of
making sense of the world, severing the cords that bound the two together.
This, as much as economics, is what has driven the North American cinema
into the realm of digital imaging. The cost of building synthespians more
sophisticated than the disappearing Kevin Bacon of Hollow Man(Smith
2000) is still prohibitive,2but other repetitive tasks like in-betweening have
been delegated to computers for over a decade. Digital extras are a fixture,
from The Lion King’s flocking wildebeest to the milling crowds of Titanicand
The Mummy. Mattes and traveling mattes, wipes and dissolves, preproduc-
tion tasks like marrying script, storyboard, and budget, and postproduction
work, especially sound recording and both vision and sound editing, are
now digitally based.
Otherwise, to some extent nothing fundamental has changed: the ma-
chines execute the same tasks humans used to, their skills turned into fixed,
“dead” capital. Digital instruments provide soundtrack scores, but they largely
emulate standard orchestral instruments and the overfamiliar nineteenth-
century language of film music. Nonetheless, audiences have a clear idea in
their minds when offered digital entertainment: a certain seamlessness, a
10
TECHNOLOGICAL FILM
| |
generic expectation of something new, a willingness to sever connections
with fundamental laws of nature. It is not necessarily the essential nature of
digital media to provide these things, but they often are provided and be-
come part of the cycle of expectation and satisfaction on which the closed
loop of commodity production proceeds.
History is no longer intrinsic to films but extrinsic. The description of
effects-driven event movies as enclosed and enclosing worlds may seem to
remove them from the political analyses of ideology critique. That, indeed,
is their purpose: to abstract themselves from the temporal to grasp for the
eternal. That grasp is itself of course an ideological task, but it apparently
leaves us with little within those worlds to analyze or interpret. Politics
ishere being conducted at a miniaturized level of micromarkets, lifestyle
groups, and psychic intervention, wholly in keeping with shifts in market-
ing, advertising, consumption, and the intensifying individualism of North
America. Insofar as they are ideological, the ideological practices of film
must be understood more at the level of apparatus than of individual arti-
fact. Analysis of new forms generated in the neobaroque leads toward a
reconceptualization of the interrelations between the social and cinematic
worlds, which may alleviate some of the remaining conceptual problems of
ideology critique and offer some idea of how, despite their self-enclosure,
these film events are not entirely successful in the pursuit of coherence and
so leave an escape hatch for the use of critics and audiences.
To some extent, the micropolitical dimensions of neobaroque cinema
have already been addressed by feminist critics. Thus Ryan and Kellner ar-
gue that the style of de Palma’s Dressed to Kill, Blow-Out, and Body Double“is
defined by baroque excess.” Unlike the meaningful plenum of the child at
the mother’s breast, they argue, the baroque is meaningless, “unpredictable;
it is a world of anxiety projections, threats potentially coming from any-
where, because the secure presence of meaning has withdrawn from it.” This
denial of semantic plentitude corresponds to a patriarchal struggle to take
control of the world through an anempathic mastery of style: “if the world
cannot be trusted, then security can only be gotten in a private, artificial
world of one’s own making.” This, they note, “is Walter Benjamin’s baroque
tyrant become a petit bourgeois family man” (Ryan and Kellner 1990: 190).
Between the construction of private universes and the struggle for mas-
tery, the white man reconfigures his power. The description is particularly
persuasive when applied to films like Twelve Monkeysand Pulp Fictionwhere
| 246 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
0
|
the anticipated resolution between world and subject fails, where mastery is
never achieved, and the world reasserts its meaninglessness. But such ni-
hilism is only the obverse of that blind faith which marks the successful
achievement of unification into a coherent world. Moreover, the result of
this success is less the reassertion of white patriarchy and more the accept-
ance of the artificial world on its own terms, conforming to a need for con-
trol at a moment in which control is simultaneously within the grasp of new
endocolonial technologies and become vanishingly distant. Such are the
contradictions out of which the new event cinema is being formed. They do
not necessarily, however, also describe the morphology of the new films, a
condition for whose functioning is that they abstract themselves from the
historical dialectic. Nonetheless, understanding both the apparatus and the
morphology will make it far easier to understand how and why contempo-
rary culture, contemporary ideology, is so desperately unambitious.
Digital technologies promise to elevate fantasy worlds above the trouble-
some everyday world. Beauty there will be more intense, emotions more
powerful, the adrenalin indistinguishable from the real rush. That extrac-
tion, the apparent boot-strapping of alternatives to the lifeworld, is the
strategic power of the neobaroque. Its films cultivate spiritual values as the
highest of human yearnings, as the old baroque did, but rather than displace
them geographically in the New World, or chronologically into the after-
life, ours enclose them in bubbles of space-time. Rather than invite to the
voyage or the ascent, they cajole us to step inward, into miniaturized infin-
ities bracketed off from the world. If the sense of presence belongs most to
those who are at home in their world, the artificial worlds of the neobaroque
offer us a stronger sense of being than we experience outside, among the
wreckage of modernity, betrayed by the reality of the world, deprived of
truth or justice.
It is not, then, that the world has become simulation, but that cinema
events have become spectacle, addressing atomized audiences intraperson-
ally, turning their gaze inward as the supposed triumph of consumerism de-
cays into poverty, injustice, and ecological catastrophe. For Debord, “the
satisfaction of primary human needs is replaced by an uninterrupted fabri-
cation of pseudo-needs” (Debord 1977: para. 51). Today, the atomic subject
can be offered the virtual satisfaction of virtual needs, and none more so
than the simple desire to be. Fragmented, schizoid, structured in dominance
and by the lack in being, contemporary subjectivity yearns for wholeness
| 247 |
Te
ch
n
o
lo
g
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
and integration. The digital worlds of event movies offer this satisfaction,
no less real for its restriction to the brief seductions of the screen.
Brief, but not passionless. The intensity of digital effects is not entirely
new. Miniatures and double-exposure date back in the United States to
Willis H. O’Brien’s work on The Lost World(Brosnan 1977: 108–110)
andbefore that to Brown’s (1973) experiments for D. W. Griffith, even
toPorter’s ambitious experiments at “perfectly made, handcrafted” films
in Dream of a Rarebit Fiend, Kathleen Mavourneen, and The “Teddy” Bearsof
1906–1907 (Musser 1991: 331). Combinations of live and animated charac-
ters in a single shot were an early Disney specialty in the Alice in Cartoonland
series of 1924–1926 (Schickel 1968: 86–87; Holliss and Sibley 1988: 13).
Motion capture dates back to Marey’s design for a black suit with white
points and lines used to image the stages of movement (Dagognet 1992:
plates 36, 37, and 48). Stunts, demolition, and pyrotechnics remain largely
untouched, save that better safety gear can be used on location because it
can be painted out electronically in postproduction. Animatronics have de-
veloped by leaps and bounds, as the move from miniatures to robotics (and
in the case of Jurassic Park 2: The Lost Worldwaterproof circuitry) largely does
away with the limitations of stop-motion animation by introducing real-
time animation of three-dimensional models.
On the other hand, backdrops, mattes, and rear projections (Fielding
1968) have been only marginally altered by the possibilities of chromakey
and greenscreen (McAlister 1993: 16). In the end, this is merely a more eco-
nomic way of achieving traditional effects. The one signal change here is
that the cameras used necessarily to be locked off in a fixed position. Con-
temporary motion-control rigs allow fluid camerawork in greenscreen se-
quences and permit the movement of a real camera to be matched precisely
by the movements of a virtual camera in 3-D computer space (Bizony 2001:
43–64). Beyond this, most of the advances in digital media appear to de-
rivefrom the process of proletarianization described by Harry Braverman
(1974): old craft traditions like animation in-betweening are condensed into
new technological resources, downskilling their operators and reducing de-
pendence on volatile creatives. There is no specific gain in spectacle. What
is gained is the economy with which these worlds can be manufactured.
That economy in turn enables their burgeoning use.
As late as the early 1990s, manuals of computer-generated imaging
(CGI) and special effects regularly dismiss vector graphics in favor of
| 248 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
0
|
bit maps (see, e.g., Vince 1990). The distinction between bit map and
vector, sampling and polygons, so dear to first-year classes in computer
graphics, isnow approaching obsolescence. For many years, the separation
of thetwo—and the early dominance of bit-map technologies—shaped
theways in which the diegeses of the neobaroque were built. They lie
not onthefamiliar axis of verisimilitudinous painting and abstraction
butalongaline stretching from cartography at one end to architecture
attheother. Somewhere inbetween lie the fields of virtual sculpture and
computer-aided design andmanufacture. Throughout the rhetoric of the
industry and the commentaries to innumerable DVDs, the emphasis is
onbelievability, not verisimilitude. Like architecture and maps, and en-
shrined in the cartographic timelines of nonlinear editing and vector ani-
mation programs, the art of special effects is an art of space.
To seek the origins of this condition, it is no longer adequate to seek a
basic societal mechanism responsible for spatialization. Ideology critique
appears so banal in its familiar guise for the same reason media effects the-
ory is so unconvincing: the causal chain linking media forms and social be-
havior on which both depend has been broken. As Clifford Geertz noted
two decades ago, ‘the established approach to treating such phenomena,
laws-and-causes social physics, was not producing the triumphs of predic-
tion, control, and testability that had for so long been promised in its name”
(Geertz 1983: 3). Space succeeds time as organizing principle synchro-
nously with neobaroque narratives’ turn to the database form, a spectacu-
larization of plot in an ironic mode in which mere coincidence satirizes the
classical working-through of causes and their effects. As the lifeworld ap-
pears consistently more random, so the mediascape becomes more scathing
of any pretense at order, mocking the revelations and resolutions that once
passed as realistic by elaborate and mocking simulations that reveal the dia-
grammatic origins of complex plotting, instead of fostering the illusion of
psychological or moral motivation for action or the patterning of the world.
In the process, pattern is divorced from its old task of establishing morality.
The last, great, tragic attempts at depicting such an ethical worldview,
like the final part of Coppola’s Godfathertrilogy, fall at the critical moment
at which the world dispenses its justice. The unresolvable incestuous love
between cousins is resolved, by one cousin’s death. After his moment of
agony, the tragic hero Corleone dies apparently reconciled with his wife, as-
sured of an heir and sleeping gently in his garden. What should have been
| 249 |
Te
ch
n
o
lo
g
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
the apotheosis of divine judgment looks exceptionally like a thoroughly de-
sirable end to a thoroughly enviable life. Unlike Brecht’s heroine in The
Good Woman of Szechuan (1958), Coppola’s hero does seem to succeed in do-
ing good, or at least doing well, in an evil world. That ambiguity concern-
ing the possibility of natural justice rarely surfaces in the event movie. Such
contradictions are never allowed to surface. Instead, they are congealed into
a pure surface, at best sketched in as “character” in the formula of prefabri-
cated back-story, ray-traced on the epidermis of the players and frequently
derived from the actors’ previous roles, or established as an item (but rarely
a system) of belief to be proven in the faith-filled variant, or disproven in the
nihilist as substantial as midichlorians.
The digital corresponds so closely to the emergent loss of an ideologi-
cal structure to social meaning because it no longer pretends to represent
the world. The linguistic model, no matter how many twists it underwent in
the twentieth century, remains tied to the truth-conditions of utterances,
and they in turn, despite the logicians’ impact on information theory, tied
to the quality of reference. This is the scientific model that today dominates
Western culture: statements must be checkable against observable states.
What digital media seem to do—which is not necessarily what they do—is
sever the link between meaning and truth, meaning and reference, meaning
and observation. Digital media do not refer. They communicate. An older
philosophy of consciousness begins in the relation that a self has to itself, in
subjectivity. A more recent one, as Habermas suggests, sees subjectivity as
effect: “The reciprocal interpersonal relations that are established through
the speaker-hearer perspectives make possible a relation-to-self that by no
means presupposes the lonely reflection of the knowing and acting subject
upon itself as antecedent consciousness. Rather, the self-relation arises out
of an interactivecontext” (Habermas 1992: 24). After modernity’s variants
on Descartes’s “I think therefore I am,” Habermas asserts the “postmeta-
physical” primacy of communicative networks over individuation. It is a goal
devoutly to be wished for, but it is better philosophy than it is sociology.
In nonlinguistic arenas like audiovisual special effects, the relation of
reciprocity cannot be presumed either. From the high ground of philo-
sophical theorization, certainly the networks are universal and equitable,
but at the level of daily experience, they are monopolistic and monodirec-
tional. Luhmann goes so far as to define mass media by the fact “that no
interaction among those co-present can take place between sender and
| 250 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
0
|
receiver” (Luhmann 2000: 2)—and no medium, albeit lightweight, is as
massive as the blockbuster movie. Special effects cinema, especially digital
films, do, however, establish a relation prior to self-consciousness, but it is
not one between social subjects, nor even between an ideological subject
and the Althusserian Subject of ideology (Althusser 1971). It is instead an
intrapsychic event that perceives itself as a relation between psyche and vir-
tual world in which the emergence of self-consciousness is synchronous
with its dissolution.
Like religion, the special effect underwrites an act of communion with
another, higher and different mode of being. Yet that being is no longer, in
a secular epoch and industry, divine. It is instead cosmic, but at the same
time artificial, since it is bounded both temporally and spatially. Within this
bounded cosmos, the lonely subject is constituted as incomplete and needy,
and therefore already destined to assimilate itself with the world from which
it has so suddenly sprung. The most interesting of these films, and often
those that have the strongest box-office draw, require of the constituted sub-
ject both intellection and action, the two united in many instances as heroic
problem solving. Problems in the effects cosmos can be solved, because in
these enclosed worlds alone exists the condition for successful action: truth.
Moreover, that condition, this truth, since it is addressed to the individual
asthe unit consumer of the commodity film, rests on the identity of the
ideaof the pictured world and its being. Like Hegel’s divinity constituted in
the unity of the notion and being, the finite creature who enters the world
is stripped of the being in time and being in space that separates concept
from existence, to reunite being and idea in a single event. Because this
event is intrapsychic rather than social, it constitutes the divinity of Narcis-
sus. The accidents—the accidence, in Virilio’s scholastic terminology—that
so enchanted Bazin in the Italian neorealists disappear into a wholly ordered
world.
In the words of Richard Edlund, founder of effects house Boss Films,
“There is something about serendipity and the ‘happy accident’ that you
can’t get on a computer.... the computer is very precise. Every result must
be thought of and programmed. It is often that unexpected happenstance
that makes the shot real, and organic, and truly satisfying” (Rogers 1999: 117).
Comparing, for example, the opening shots of the battlefield in Mankie-
wicz’s Cleopatrawith the panorama of Egypt in the first shot of The Mummy,
the chaos of the one and the order of the other, you can see the difference
| 251 |
Te
ch
n
o
lo
g
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
between a world in which, if not freedom, then at least chance can persist
and one in which there is no randomness. That the more recent sequence
was undoubtedly far cheaper to shoot only begins to explain its appeal. It
succeeds because it provides mastery over a world subject to the gaze of one
who is becoming a god. The substance, in medieval theology the immutable
essence of the world, is deprived of its accidence, the material form in which
it presents itself to human perception. Now that perception is digital rather
than human, it realizes “the will to see all, to know all, at every moment,
everywhere, the will to universalized illumination; a scientific permutation
on the eye of God, which would forever rule out the surprise, the accident,
the irruption of the unforeseen” (Virilio 1994: 70).
This quasi-scientific expropriation of the divine prerogative also indi-
cates the cataclysmic narcissism of the digital subject, itself a result of what
Giddens refers to as “the looming threat of personal meaninglessness” (Gid-
dens 1991: 201). Mankiewicz’s Caesar wins the world, an ideological sur-
rogate for our loss of it. Sommers’s Mummy becomes the world, a force of
nature that springs into existence at the moment of dissolution back into the
fictive world that gives birth to him. The goal of the film is not the clinch,
nor even the restitution of order, but the assimilation of self into world,
onscreen and in the auditorium. In that moment the self-enclosure of the
diegesis assimilates its spectator in its fatal embrace, unifying concept
and being. Like Bram Stoker’s Dracula, The Mummy stages, with flair, a lit-
eral transcription of undying love.
As summarized by Habermas, the theologian Michael Theunissen argues
that “True selfhood expresses itself as communicative freedom—as being-
with-oneself-in-the-other; love—being-with-oneself-in-the-other—stands
in a complementary relation” (Habermas 2001a: 95). This oscillation of
emphasis between oneself and the other constitutes the polarity of contem-
porary Hollywood: action and romance, a permutation of the mutual de-
pendence of classical narrative and melodrama argued by Rick Altman
(1992). Freedom is so central to North American ideology that its lack is
invisible. The enclosed predestined worlds of the neobaroque annihilate its
claims by granting to action only the freedom to achieve one’s destiny.
Love, however, presents a different conceptual knot. On the one hand,
the protagonists of Draculaand The Mummy(as also those of What Dreams
May Comeand Cameron’s Titanic,The Abyss, and Terminator 2) are tragically
tied to temporal rifts. The relationship with the other is the term left out or
| 252 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
0
|
marginalized in filmworlds whose raison d’être is unifying world and subject.
The presence of another subject suggests the limits to the enclosed world and
poses difficult problems for a culture in which sexual object and sexual part-
ner are all too readily interchangeable. Love is the form in which neobaroque
Hollywood asks itself the question of the social, unequipped as it is with any
way of visualizing a larger social grouping beyond the connectivity of pat-
tern. This aesthetic problem emerges in the editing of digital film.
Editing in 3-D
Stephen Prince notes how the pseudopod, the aqueous tentacle that insinu-
ates itself into the deep-sea habitat of The Abyss,
had started in the computer as wireframe animation, onto which the animators
composited a rippling liquid texture (in a process called texture-mapping) and
shimmery highlights that gave it a three-dimensional appearance. Furthermore,
in a way that dramatically heralded the future, the CGI creature interacted in a
convincing and fully-dimensional way with the human, live-action elements of
the shot. When actress Mary Elizabeth Mastrantonio touches the figure, her
finger goes “inside” the alien, glimpsed through its translucent surface, and it,
in turn, reacts to her touch, rippling with sensation. The effect is completely
credible, even though the alien existed only in computer space and had no live-
action correlate in the shot. Here lay the future of digitally based filmmaking:
the ability to convincingly integrate the 2D and 3D components of a scene,
computer space with live-action space. (Prince 2000: 291–292)
James Cameron’s The Abyss(1989) (fig. 10.1)was a landmark of morph-
ing technologies in special effects cinema. The water-creature was as amor-
phous and lovely an effect as we had ever seen. The creature winds through
the underwater facility in a meandering steadicam point of view. As it enters
the cabin, we get a series of reaction shots, so that our first sight of the crea-
ture is framed as a reverse shot. Silver-blue, lit from within and without and
sharing the colors of the wall behind it, the pseudopod winds across the
screen and over the edge of the frame. Already we are about to lose a crucial
aspect of the vector: its mutability. In place of a pan, we get a cut. The crea-
ture has moved toward frame right; it emerges into frame left in a compos-
ite shot with the film’s stars, Ed Harris and Mary Elizabeth Mastrantonio.
A second cut places us at 90 degrees to the axis between them and the tip of
| 253 |
Te
ch
n
o
lo
g
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
the water-finger, now a more slender shape. Now comes the sequence’s only
true point-of-view shot, from within the water. Cut to a reverse angle shot
combining both stars’ profiles with the water-creature’s tip as it takes on the
shape of a human face. Reverse angle for their reactions: a relieved smile and
sigh. Reverse angle: the creature imitates the smile. Eight shots in 29 sec-
onds to explain the two registers of cinema to one another.
Here the grammar of classical continuity cutting is followed to the let-
ter: 180-degree rule, 30-degree rule, eyeline match. Critical to the scene’s
construction is the shot at right angles to the action, which will be followed
by a return to the point-of-view shot. Moving us to an unmotivated position
beside but outside the action, it presents us with a schematic of what can
only be read as a face-to-face confrontation, even though one of the partic-
ipants lacks a physiognomy. The face-to-face presumes that the creature
will adopt some kind of visage. The amorphous morph has been tamed, by
a combination of editing, compositing, and the cutting force of the frame.
| 254 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
0
|
| Figure 10.1 |
The Abyss: Director James Cameron abandons fluid camerawork for analytic editing.
Courtesy BFI Stills, Posters, and Designs.
Only a brief moment of the genuinely unexplained is left us, in the first ap-
pearance of the creature. When, at the end of the sequence, the demented
Navy SEAL slices the column of water in two with a sliding door, we are
only seeing onscreen a figuration of the editors at work on this sequence.
The pseudopod presents itself first as a graphic, a formless firstness. In
the Lumières’ Sortie, firstness is movement; here firstness is the infinity of
possible permutations, reversing the historical movement from event to
sign. This is why the editing is so hard and so classical, quite unlike the fluid
crane and steadicam that characterize much of Cameron’s other effects
work. Although the state of motion control in 1989 would not have allowed
compositing on a constantly reframed shot, the effects technology would
have allowed rendering the tentacle from any angle. In the rest of the film,
the 180-degree rule is flaunted constantly, and our orientation within the
deep-sea station is never important to the editing. On the contrary, we are
expected to navigate a space established through mobile camera work, not
through cutting. The resort to classical continuity editing is jarring in this
context of fluid spatial constructions. It serves to unify and give identity and
direction to the unnameable water, which is all we can discern in the first
frame. To do so, it fragments the vector until it becomes recognizably ori-
ented in both space and time, as a moving-toward, a teleological entity,
rather than a bundle of potentially endless morphs. In creating unities, the
editing also creates a series of distinct single views that break the morphing
creature analytically into a series. The series then returns to the base prin-
ciple of the pixel: movement. Despite the temptation to read cinematic
movement as fragmentary, the digital deploys the invisibility of the inter-
vals, in the terminology Deleuze (1986: 80–86) derives from Vertov, to
recreate the vector as what Jonathan Crary (1999) identifies as distraction,
Leo Charney (1998) as drift, and Jonathan Miller as “an ‘automatic self’ of
which they have no conscious knowledge and over which they have little
voluntary control” (Miller 1995: 27–28).
This drifting inattention evoked by the film but absented from it sits
beyond the useful double concept of hypermediacy proposed by Bolter and
Grusin (1999). Hypermediacy tempts us to perceive the illusion of a world
beyond the medium, while fascinating us with mediation: simultaneous en-
joyment of Vermeer’s milkmaid and the brushstrokes that compose her. In
the sequence from The Abyss, attention flickers from the creature’s move-
ments to its elements, as it were to the brushstrokes of temporality. This
| 255 |
Te
ch
n
o
lo
g
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
unconscious is not, then, the fantastic of Cohl’s Fantasmagoriebut the drift-
ing reverie appropriate to a pseudo-reality reconstructing itself constantly
from clouds of polygons, pixels, photons below the threshold of conscious
perception. We are being led toward firstness. This is perhaps the principal
source of the sense of awe in science fiction movies. But it is also a precon-
scious state, a mesmerized gaze. This is magical, but it is neither the magic
of the illusion of life, nor of the awareness of trickality, nor yet of the end-
lessness of the graphical vector: rather it is delight in the illusory perception
of illusion.
Henry Jenkins refers to the same distracted state when he writes (1998:
263) of the “virtual play spaces” of computer gaming. The promise of the pi-
oneer cinema was to promote a new interface, a partnership between human
and machine in the making of a new art. In The Abyssthat relation is one of
seduction. The découpage of the morphing water-tentacle moves away
from the infinite, not toward totality but toward the stasis of zero as a bal-
ance of forces, producing a hypnotized subordination to the magic of illu-
sion. Artificial but not synthetic, this is a moment of subordination to the
machine as consciousness, an inversion of Heideggerian ekstasis turned
from preconscious union with nature to preconscious subordination to tech-
nology. Despite the narrative’s attempt to make the corporate state the vil-
lain of the piece, The Abyssmesmerizes its subject into descending into the
depths from which the magic arises. Without dialectic, committed to the
exposure and eradication of difference, The Abyssdescends into the virtual
in the poor sense described by Damien Keown when differentiating Bud-
dhist meditation from “the stasis of a virtual experience, wherein however
much the wheels spin, nothing ever moves” (Keown 1998: 86). Sacrifice
leads not to salvation but to finality, to a union with the wise spirit of the
deep in whom all change, all history resolves into karmic equilibrium.
Contrast a scene from Alex Proyas’s 1999 Dark City. Clearly a mid-
budget production compared to the immense expense of Cameron’s film ten
yearsearlier, Dark City equally clearly benefits from the tumbling costs of
computer-generated imaging (CGI). We are in a world that owes something
to the traditions of Groundhog Dayand The Truman Show, something to
the neonoir production design of Blade Runnerand Batman, something
tothe cult gothicism of Proyas’s previous film, The Crow.The Strangers are
mad scientist aliens in control of the strange nocturnal shenanigans; every-
| 256 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
0
|
one else is at best ambiguous, more often downright sinister. It is midnight,
and while the city sleeps, architectures, interiors, clothing, circumstances,
marriages, families, and, as we soon learn, even memories are being altered.
Proyas’s camera rarely occupies positions motivated by a human ob-
server. Compositions emphasize depth, points of view are literally incon-
ceivable as human, and cutting serves an alien point of view—the viewpoint
of a mechanical perception autonomous of human sensoria. Like some key
Japanese anime and manga comics, cuts are governed at least as much by
graphical as by continuity matches. Moreover, at this stage in the film, nei-
ther the characters nor the viewer have a clue what is going on. We do not
know what the morphing buildings are doing, where they are going, why
they are changing, growing, grinding their way from one location to an-
other. Nor, and this is the point of distinction between Dark Cityand The
Abyss,does the editing help orient us. Quite the opposite. We are as lost in
the city as the protagonists. And although the film is neatly circular, what
delights its fans is the vertigo of unexplained procedures and the sense of the
endless that they evoke. If in The Abyssthe CGI effects are subordinated to
the photographic, here the photographic elements are subordinated to the
graphical code. As a result, even though bound into form by the terminal cut
of closure, the film presents us with a sensation of openness in the paradox-
ically claustrophobic confines of the nightmare burg.
Dark City’s effects combine CGI, the building of virtual objects and an-
imations that exist only in cyberspace, and compositing, the use of comput-
ers to layer elements deriving from studio and location footage, model and
miniature stages, into single images. Compositing demands more even than
technological wizardry, immense preplanning, and forethought. The type of
explosive used in miniature pyrotechnics, the speeds at which they are shot—
up to 300 frames per second—and the stopped-down iris—as low as f32—
needed to give miniatures depth make demands on the types of film stock
and the quantity and quality of light and color-response, which have to be
matched as precisely as more obvious matters like shadows. The difference
between CGI and compositing is neatly caught in Michele Pierson’s (1999a)
historical distinction between technofuturist and simulationist modes of
digital special effects. CGI, she argues, especially during the transition from
analog effects in the early 1990s, is characterized by its encouragement of
awe, by its presentation of the spectacle as worthy of contemplation. Scott
| 257 |
Te
ch
n
o
lo
g
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
Bukatman makes a similar argument when he suggests that “Special effects
redirect the spectator to the visual (and auditory and even kinaesthetic) con-
ditions of the cinema” (Bukatman 1999: 254).
Although the decision to go with miniatures rather than CGI is as often
financial as aesthetic, nonetheless there is an ethical dimension to the choice.
Shifting emphasis from CGI to compositing corresponds to a shift away
from spectacle toward simulation of reality. Lee Tamahori’s Mulholland Falls
provides a neat example in the sequence showing a huge crater left by atomic
testing. Unable to access restricted areas of the Nevada desert, the effects
crew provided a virtual crater for this otherwise realist period thriller. Here
it is not so much a question of alternative reality as of enhanced reality—as
effects are now routinely used to brighten or darken skies, correct period de-
tail in location shoots (Devil in a Blue Dress), turn small groups of extras into
swarming crowds (as in the concert scenes in That Thing You Do) or to air-
brush in or out wanted or unwanted details in the cinematographic image.
Pierson cites Sobchack on films like Tronand The Last Starfighterto the
effect that “The privileging of electronic depiction depends upon its marked
difference from cinematic space rather than upon its integration with it”
(Sobchack 1987: 261). Despite the fact that many of the effects in Tron were
hand-drawn cel imitations of digital effects, the film still made much of its
early use of computer imaging, taking on the task of visualizing the emer-
gent world of cyberspace for its new inhabitants, in a way picked up on and
expanded by later films such as Johnny Mnemonic and Lawnmower Man(see
Hayward 1993). Like La Valley (1985), Sobchack sees the cinema of digital
effects as pivoting on the incompatibility of familiar-analog and alien-
digital. Pierson fingers Emmerich’s work on Independence Dayand Godzilla
as the end of that era in which, in the words of Pohl and Pohl, “Audiences
watch new sf flicks as they do a conjuring show” (Pohl and Pohl 1981: 315).
The seamlessness of contemporary compositing, the erasure of the differ-
ences between the various elements and their subordination to the con-
struction of a coherent diegesis, ends the period in which, says Pierson, the
difference between elements was the source of the magic.
Enhanced reality, however, does not quite conform to this description
of simulation. It is not caught in the representational matrix of simulation,
the theoretical end-stop to the old paradox of representation (that any rep-
resentation is, by definition, inadequate to the reality to which it refers). At
best, the cinema of enhanced reality serves up the cold comfort of sense
| 258 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
0
|
forced on a recalcitrant world. More commonly, in Mulholland Fallsor That
Thing You Do,it subordinates the profilmic world to the necessities of com-
munication. In itself, this is the process of all communication. But in these
instances, what is lost is the Batesonian “difference that makes a difference,”
specifically the difference between communication and environment that,
for Luhmann (1995) and his sources in Maturana and Varela’s information
theory (e.g., 1980, 1987), constitutes the grounds of communication’s pos-
sibility. For Pierson, the trajectory of the science fiction film from fetishized
effect to integration results in the closure of science fiction’s utopian proj-
ect: “The future has once more dropped out of sight” (Pierson 1999b: 176).
Undying Love
When we seek to be represented, what is it that we want to see? Is it, as The
Abyss would suggest, ourselves as we are: concepts without an existence, de-
prived of meaning and reality, seeking in the movies the fleeting, horizon-
haunted space in which for a brief interlude we become our worlds and so
achieve being? Or are we, as Dark Citywould seem to suggest, concepts with-
out existence, pure substances whose experience is as illusory as the movie
itself, with nothing to cling to but a haunted, amnesic conviction that some-
where among the detritus and the mobile world there was once a true self to
which it is our task to return? The Incredible Shrinking Man’s visionary final
sequence spoke of boundless space within the atom. Dark Cityfinds the cos-
moshabitable only when it is bounded. The same year’s The Thirteenth Floor
argues an even more paranoid cosmos of nested virtualities, one inside the
next, in a potentially infinite mise en abyme.Even our infinities are bounded.
The gods we may become are deeply diminished.
Thus the importance of the theme of enduring, undying love to the
blockbuster. There is no need for The Abyssto delay and then celebrate first
coition: our romantic leads are divorced from each other. There are ele-
ments of the comedy of remarriage (see Musser 1995), but they are recruited
for the most part as typical and reliable storylines to hang the big scenes on;
the only one persuaded of their ideological significance is the director of the
film. Lacan decrees, notoriously, that “what one calls sexual bliss is marked,
dominated, by the impossibility of establishing, as such, anywhere in the
enunciable, the unique One which is important for us, the One of the rela-
tionship ‘sexual relations.’” Lacan was no feminist. His interest lies in the
maculate processes of being masculine: “Phallic jouissance is the obstacle
| 259 |
Te
ch
n
o
lo
g
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
which stops man arriving at jouissance in the body of the woman, precisely
because what he gets his bliss from is the jouissance of his own organ” (La-
can 1975: 15).
This claim needs rephrasing to bring it up to date. Sex is no longer for-
bidden or shameful, least of all to the ex-marrieds of The Abyss.The point of
the affair is not sexual—any more than it is ideological. The impossibility
of sexual union lies in the impossibility of unity: that in the sexual relation
there are always two. Given this impossibility, the life-affirming vitality of
love can be realized only in the readiness to sacrifice everything, including
love and life, in its name. Self-loss is the condition for self-realization, and
both deny the union of lover and beloved, self and other, where that other is
not a world but a subject. This is where modern love and the neobaroque
coincide so powerfully. The hero cannot lose himself twice, in the beloved
and in the world, in another subject and in an object. This is why love, pas-
sionate and enduring love, to be passionate and enduring has to be wrecked
on the rocks of time, and thus to lose what makes love lovable—its altering,
fluctuating, ever-evolving nature as mutual exploration, mutual evolution.
Love, in the neobaroque, endures or is not. It persists, even at the expense
of the lovers. The relation turns on those it relates and destroys them (The
Mummy), or tears their hearts from them (Titanic).3
Digital effects tend to communicate rather than represent, a shift in em-
phasis from the analog era of ideology. They not so much depict or falsify
actuality but communicate aspiration. To that extent they are utopian or
dystopian. The concern with undying love that arises in the digital era with
films like Ghostis, then, a utopian-dystopian complex in communication that
relates to the changes that have overcome love in the late twentieth and early
twenty-first centuries. For Ann Swidler (1980), for example, modern love is
no longer about discovering a lifetime’s relationship somewhere during early
adulthood, but a lifelong search for a partner who will aid in self-realization,
and therefore a narrative of attempts, experiments, disappointments, part-
ings, new relationships.
Spatialized event rather than narrative, the self-oriented search for love
becomes in the digital cinema a discovery of someone who was alwaysmeant
for you. In Niklas Luhmann’s analysis, love had already become incommu-
nicable in the eighteenth century. No longer a legible code of silences, stam-
mers, and blushes, he argues, “It was not the failure of skilfulness that [was]
| 260 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
0
|
the problem, but the lack of a capacity for sincerity” (Luhmann 1986: 122),
a lack he describes as the discovery of incommunicability. That is the nexus
transformed in Titanic(fig. 10.2)and the others: from an experience of in-
communicability to an acausal, immediate, and therefore timeless commu-
nication that, in extreme forms like Ward’s What Dreams May Come,has an
almost Mormon fascination with the eternity of love as perfect communi-
cation, and one that specifically does not require sex as a communicative
medium. Love in such films is distinguished from and set in opposition to
nature, especially to that most natural fact of all, death. The iceberg, the wa-
ter, the night, characterized by their refusal to communicate, confront the
lovers of Titanic as their enemy, while the lovers’ communication survives
the death of one of them and so overcomes the natural order. Undying love
requires no medium in its immediacy, and therefore abstracts itself from the
time of mediation, the time of history. Likewise, it overcomes death and so
transcends the time of nature. Deprived of time, it becomes a purely spatial
configuration, a crystal, sublime.
| 261 |
Te
ch
n
o
lo
g
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
| Figure 10.2 |
Titanic:Seamless compositing of set and computer-generated imaging: no lack of skill but a loss of the
capacity for sincerity. Courtesy BFI Stills, Posters, and Designs.
Few instances of this spatiality are as clear as the climactic sequence in
Zemeckis’s Contact (fig. 10.3). Propelled by alien technology into the far
reaches of the galaxy, scientist Ellie (Jodie Foster) finds herself on a myste-
rious, nebula-lit beach where she is greeted by an alien intelligence who
takes the form of her dead father. The production schedule demanded that
the location be filmed in advance of the shoot with the actors. The Fijian
beach footage was tiled into a spherical virtual set so that any future camera
move could be accommodated. The tiled set was then enhanced in a total of
39 blue-screen composites, adding digital starlight, color-correcting the
water where cloud shadows had passed over it, and mapping the pho-
tographed elements onto a 3-D CGI set to allow for perspective and paral-
lax effects. To heighten the effects, tree shadows were accelerated and the
waves projected backward. Finally, to produce the desired sense of dream-
| 262 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
0
|
| Figure 10.3 |
Contact:Bluescreen composite places Jodie Foster in a perfect closed sphere that will contain infinite vistas:
a digital monad. Courtesy BFI Stills, Posters, and Designs.
like awareness, Foster’s character is surrounded by a translucent sphere de-
signed to produce ripple effects every time her hand touches it. Motion con-
trol cameras stored and recalled the camera passes over the actors to define
their relation to the virtual set (Rogers 1999: 226–228).
Two aspects of the sequence are significant for this discussion: the rela-
tion between father and daughter, and the spherical infinity of the virtual
set. Not only is Ellie’s father dead, but the physical realization of daughter-
father love is automatically debarred. In this way love can be abstracted
from the sexual and rendered quasi-religious (in harmony with the film’s
central theme, the relation between belief and evidence) in the same way a
motion-capture rig abstracts motion from the moving body. The doubly
spherical design of the visionary space, nesting the rippling vision-sphere
inside the virtual set, nests the purely experiential within a world that is itself
whole and entire. More: this larger world is perfect, reminiscent of Boullée’s
projected spherical Cenotaph for Newton, its vast interior a depiction of the
whole night sky. As Eaton argues, Boullée’s plan embodies “the transition
from an architecture and town planning that privileged the enchaînement—
the flow of dominant movement through an urban composition” to an “au-
tonomous architecture” (Eaton 2000: 131). The virtual sphere that forms
the end point of Ellie’s odyssey, ambiguously physical or spiritual, mirrored
across a series of circular and spherical compositions throughout the movie,
encloses in perfection the possibilities of development and change. In its
perfection, in its awesome evocation of final things, it makes visible the end
of history, not as bang or whimper, but as perfect realization of the present
and the self.
The perfect sphere is the culmination of the millennia of evolution with-
out conflict, without randomness, without any of the motors of history that
our culture recognizes, and therefore also without politics, which has lost its
claim on the cinema of digital effects. In the 1980s, for example, the political
role of wonder appeared clear: “The style of these films [of John Milius] is
congruent with the ideology of radical individualism in that it promotes awe
at the majestic power of nature and of the warrior leader. Awe is the correla-
tive of the political attitude of obedience superior individual leaders must in-
spire and require if they are to succeed” (Ryan and Kellner 1990: 224). In the
period between the two presidents Bush, attempts to credit the White House
with intelligence and honesty have been tongue-in-cheek cornball, like the
| 263 |
Te
ch
n
o
lo
g
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
fighter-pilot president of Independence Day,while more typical onscreen lead-
ers are venal buffoons (Mars Attacks!) or ineffectual accountants (The Fifth
Element). Leadership is no longer a vital element in the blockbuster.
Awe, however, remains of central importance: awe at the majestic power
of spectacle, whose apolitical correlative is self-subjugation, the acceptance
of solipsistic destiny. The power of the digital spectacle is coherence: the
world not as collocation of things but as a single object. This is an apolitical
power in the sense that it no longer brooks the possibility of resistance. In
its earlier moment, neobaroque Hollywood devoted itself to moments of
awe, glimpses of the sublime. In more recent films, that awe is anchored most
of all in moments of destruction, like the marketing image (see Wyatt 1994:
112–133) for Independence Day, the spectacular destruction of the White
House, an image that recalls the spectacular montage of H-bombs that closes
Dr. Strangelove,the first great antipolitical film of modern times.
Kubrick’s film was a paean to impotence: the impossibility of not de-
stroying the planet, once the means to do so are in our hands. The last hours
of the species are lit and shot in the same way as the doomed protagonists of
film noir. Human beings have no wish to destroy themselves, but once
events are in train, their will has nothing to do with the destiny that drives
through them. Vera Lynn singing “We’ll Meet Again” on the soundtrack of
Kubrick’s finale evokes only to mock the last heroic stand against self-
destructive evil in World War II. InIndependence Day,pace Michael Rogin’s
(1998) detailed ideological reading and titular comparison of the Zemeckis
and Kubrick films, the heroism is presented ironically, and the aliens are de-
feated despite the ineffectual nature of the opposition. The truest moment
of the film is anchored in the relationship between the President and his
wife, who dies. We learn that it was for her that all this destruction has been
suffered and overcome. Love, undying, unconditional love, has taken the
place of politics.
In Pierson’s transitional period, the sublime moment of the special ef-
fect emerges and irradiates the ordinary world, transforming and transfig-
uring it with immortal longings. In the fully integrated worlds of more
recent digital effects movies, the sublime has achieved its goal of transfigu-
ration to such an extent that the act of transfiguration is itself overwhelmed
in the perfection of the integrated spectacle (Debord 1990: 9). The com-
modity no longer reveals its inner dialectic of completion and void: the world
itself becomes commodity, and there is no outside, no beyond, to which the
| 264 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
0
|
films give us access. The meaning of sublimity, to speak oxymoronically, has
changed. Where once it spoke to the flat tedium of Kansas in the emerald
tones of Oz to return to Kansas and find it beautiful, now it eliminates
Kansas. Films that attempt to rebuild beauty by picturing reconstruction—
Waterworldand that allegory of internet as democracy, The Postman—nose-
dive at the box office. Where, in the finale of Soylent Green, the panorama
of “archeological” images of natural beauty moves the dying Edward G.
Robinson to tears, by 2001, the pristine wilderness of Aotearoa New Zea-
land’s South Island in Lord of the Rings: The Fellowship of the Ringhas become
pure special effect.
In Arwen’s repudiation of her immortality, we see writ small how the
commodity sublime demands the death of beauty: “By sacrificing itself, the
imagination sacrifices nature, which is aesthetically sacred, in order to exalt
holy law” (Lyotard 1994: 189). For the philosopher, by sacrificing its own
freedom, imagination achieves the freedom of the law. But for media theory,
that sacrifice buys only the freedom of trade, to choose anything so long as
it is a commodity. It is only in such cinematic events that the wholeness of
the diegesis can be fully realized as both immersion in the world and devo-
tion to undying love. Unconditional surrender to the other joins uncondi-
tional surrender to the world in abolishing the difference between love as
communication and world as environment. At exactly the same moment,
self sacrifices itself to achieve the status of wholeness and holiness.
The filmic world thus constructs itself as sublime monad, timeless be-
cause elementary. Its price is the sacrifice of self in a historical epoch in
which self bears more of a social burden than it is capable of carrying. After
the centuries during which freedom was the crux of philosophical and po-
litical thought and action, the goal has become peace.
Digital Monadology
This peace, however, is submission, not surrender, not the mutuality of or-
dinary love, but self-abasement to the enormity of the sublime. But it would
be a mistake to believe that the enclosure of the monad is a fruit of digi-
tality.On the one hand, the opposite is rather the case: almost every inter-
viewwith effects technicians and supervisors indicates that the invention
they bring to bear is always at the behest of a creative vision arising from
who knows what complex interplay of professionalism, commercialism, and
biography.
| 265 |
Te
ch
n
o
lo
g
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
On the other hand, the digital itself is increasingly dependent on photo-
graphic elements. As early as The Abyss,the CGI crew led by Dennis Muren
and John Knoll of Industrial Light and Magic (ILM) used reference plates
shot in the Deepcore underwater set to provide the internal reflections of the
pseudopod (Vaz and Duignan 1996: 199–200). Independence Dayeffects super-
visors Volker Engel and Douglas Smith likewise dressed their computer-
graphic models of U.S. fighter aircraft with stills of real planes, wrapped
onto the wireframe in place of detailed ray-tracing. Although Thomas G.
Smith could still see, in the landmark Genesis effect in Star Trek II: The
Wrath of Khan, evidence for “digitized movies: a scenario for the future”
(Smith 1986: 198), nonetheless he still opined that the effects for Return of
the Jedi would have required “a good sized warehouse simply to store the
data” (ibid.: 204). Even full-animation CGI movies like Toy Storydepend on
motion capture, a technique not utterly dissimilar to the use of rotoscoping
live action as an aid to animators back in the days of Snow White,to draft the
facial characteristics and performance mannerisms of Tom Hanks and the
rest into the onscreen characters.4
More so even than visuals, sound effects remain tied to analog sources.
Luke’s hovercar was powered by the sound of the Los Angeles Harbor Free-
way recorded through a vacuum cleaner tube, the sound of whalesong in the
engines of Klingon spaceships (Kelleghan 2001: np) are second only to the
infamous source of the gloop for T2’s T-1000 morphs: “What’s amazing to
me is... Industrial Light & Magic using millions of dollars of high-tech
digital equipment and computers to come up with the visuals, and mean-
while I’m inverting a dog food can” (Kenny 1991: 64). Needless to say, the
mixing of elements to produce a final soundscape of anything up to thirty
elements involves a great deal of both digital and analog recording, manip-
ulation, layering, and mastering; yet the connection with the analog world,
and the ability to hear with astute and creative ears the attack, mass, and
decay of sounds as well as their potential credibility and emotional impact,
are highly prized skills in the world of film sound. Relatively few sounds,
even musical sounds, are digitally originated in Hollywood. The old fear of
electronic noise still haunts decades after Louis and Bebe Barron’s score for
Forbidden Planet. In the transitional period, Frank Serrafine, whose credits
include Star Trek: The Motion Picture, Tron, and Lawnmower Man,was creat-
ing up to five thousand synthesized digital effects per movie, but even so he
was reliant on raw sonic material from artfully recorded organic sources
| 266 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
0
|
(LoBrutto 1994: 219–226). The analogy with wireframe rendering is at-
tractive: like Alias, SoftImage, and Renderman software packages, syn-
thesized sound creates audio “shapes” to which analog-derived “surfaces”
can be applied. At the same time, the analysis of sound design seems to lead
in similar directions to the analysis of production design: a gradual shift
from the spectacle to the integral illusion, such that the sounds no longer
stand out, as the warp factor of the Starship Enterpriseonce did, as elements
to be enjoyed for their own sake. Today, audio sweetening, the addition of
layers of subtle shading to location and foley sound, is more highly prized,
lending itself more assiduously to the creation of coherence.
The synthesis of digital and analog achievable in contemporary cinema
is hailed as a marvel of verisimilitude, that realism which Andrew Darley
sees as a persistent goal of computer-imaging technologies since the 1960s
(Darley 2000: 16–18). But it is also a source of marvel in itself. Digital
cinema, in the mode in which it has arrived at the beginning of the third
millennium, completes the world-building project of the neobaroque. The
project can be read in one particular meaning of the word “virtualization.”
The spectacle, “the self-portrait of power in the epoch of its totalitarian
management of the conditions of existence” (Debord 1977: para. 23), is vir-
tual in the same sense that power is virtual: as Foucault argued throughout
his career, it is never complete. The spectacle of total power, therefore, can
exist only as a virtual world. As technological artifacts, the spectacular vir-
tual worlds of digital cinema are hermetically sealed against their lack of re-
ality and their disjuncture from it. To this extent they conform to the later
Heidegger’s (and poststructuralism’s) account of the end of metaphysics:
metaphysics is that history at the end of which nothing is left of Being as such,
or in which Being is forgotten in favour of being ordered in a system of causes
and effects.... [T]his total forgetting of Being is the total technical organiza-
tion of a world in which there is no longer anything “unforeseen” or historically
new.... The system of total concatenation of causes and effects, prefigured by
metaphysics and actualized by technology, is the expression of the will to dom-
inate. (Vattimo 1993: 85–86)
There is a discrepancy between Debord’s Hegelian and Vattimo’s Hei-
deggerian accounts of total management. The organization of total cinema,
as it existed in Eisenstein’s time, was profoundly ideological. A rhetorical
| 267 |
Te
ch
n
o
lo
g
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
cinema, it aimed to persuade its audience of what they already believed, to
impassion them with the power of a shared belief in the vital task of saving
the homeland once again from the brute enmity of the Germans. In few
films are we so privileged to bear witness to the self-portraiture of power as
we are in that paean to Stalin and the cult of the personality. Today, however,
total cinema has shrunk to the status of an effect. Each film, enclosed within
its own sphere, asserts its dominance aside from the “conditions of exis-
tence” to which Debord, in the 1960s, was still able to give credence. In a
similar historical shift, Vattimo’s “will to dominance” results not in the abil-
ity to achieve but in the loss of the power to make history, the very purpose
of Eisenstein’s Alexander Nevsky. Yet the real and the making of history re-
main. Dominance in digital cinema is no longer an ideological project of so-
cial manipulation, but an intimate microphysics addressed to the capture
and recreation of subjectivity among the dispersed and unhappy mass of
consumers.
When critics and Hollywood professionals alike refer to films as bubble-
gum, we think of an entirely superficial art beneath which there is nothing,
an empty, unmoving, and pure spatiality. The one great lie, the one remain-
ing element of false consciousness that links this construction to the older
project of ideology is that there is no void. Instead, each closed diegetic
world is replete, condensed, full as an egg, solid as a billiard ball. Seizing on
the equilibration of flux as surface in classical Hollywood, the neobaroque
takes up the circle of total cinema and folds it into a sphere. The digital
moves that spatialization onward into the totalization of contained space.
The classical practice of holding an open line of sight into a scene into
which a new character can enter becomes, in the digital, the structuring of
space as a wholly navigable virtual map or virtual architecture, in which no
space is empty that is not already filled (with smoke and digital “fog” to cre-
ate depth and concretize light, and with real and virtual objects and their tra-
jectories) or destined to be filled. Learning the trick of totalization, digital
Hollywood has embraced too the unification characteristic of realist film,
and assimilated the one to the other to produce a unified totality and a total
unity played out as the narrative of predestination, the whole stripped of the
geographical powers of the state or the historical powers of society to ad-
dress the purely cultural domain of the hyperindividual. The pleasure on of-
fer is no longer ideological reassurance but the return to being. In return for
| 268 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
0
|
the simple sacrifice of reality, the digital cinema of the new Hollywood of-
fers the assurance of a whole and satisfying if circumscribed existence.
Presenting itself as if it were Peircean firstness, in fact Hollywood to-
day offers its audiences a mirror in which their aspiration toward being is
rewarded with the vision of the absolute object, secondness without the pos-
sibility of thirdness that can arise only from a socialized system of texts and
spectators. Since both the films themselves and the spectators they address
are holistic monads, socialization and conflicts of interpretation can be side-
stepped in favor of the experience of being here now inside the confines of
any one film’s microcosmic infinity. When we are no longer invited to enjoy
the effect in and for itself, but to marvel at its integration into the “Recre-
ation of Reality” (Burch 1990: 6), we oscillate between that wonder which
is the proper, conceptless affect of firstness and the ordered constitution of
subjectivity in the experience of the object that is secondness. In its latest
form, digital film subordinates the phenomenon to the subject-object nexus
of the commodity, so that we stand in awe of the object nature of the object,
and surrender to that. It is this movement that constitutes the digital sub-
lime, its pre- or alinguistic nature no guarantee of escape from ideology but
rather of a refusal of the social, the only possible ground of ideological work,
conflict, interpretation, dialectic, and history.
As Darley argues in his important chapter entitled “Surface play and
spaces of consumption,” the spectator of digital media “is more a sensualist
than a ‘reader’ or interpreter” (Darley 2000: 169), acting in a transformed
mode of play, prizing intensity over intelligence. Raising the critical issue of
the relative degrees of audience autonomy and activity, he rightly criticizes
the risk run by any generalized and abstracting description: that we might
lose “any sense of disparity, diversity, specificity and nuance” (ibid.: 189).
The experience of cinematic spectacle is not the only experience. It be-
longsto external systems of communication that themselves trace parallel
histories (e.g., from “Have you seen X?” to “Have you seen X yet?”—the
hallmark of the event movie) in a shift from cultural capital to consumer
discipline. The transition from the diegesis of the film to the social realm
ofthe multiplex, even the emergence from video or DVD viewing to the
familial space of the living room, is not without a certain frisson. The bor-
der state too has its significance, especially in the diminution of intensity
coupled with a heightened alertness to whatever quirky events might occur
| 269 |
Te
ch
n
o
lo
g
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
outside the theater. An aura of wholeness persists, fading, as you make your
way home. In comparison with the cultural engagement of the classical film,
digital Hollywood denegates culture, raising it as the last alternative to so-
ciety and state only to create it as the moment of its vanishing.
Never a shared experience, and lacking any relation to belief systems, it
is instead entirely devoted to communication, with a fervor that appears, in
the early years of the twenty-first century, to be a revelation of a state of af-
fairs that has always been the case: that all the human universe is composed
of communication. In this special instance, however, the communication
spurns the old adage of information theory, that the channel is insignificant.
Here the medium is so entire unto itself that the transfer of message is ren-
dered marginal. Films like Titanic or Black Hawk Downmay seek to persuade
us that love is good and war is bad, but such sentiments—and they are
strictly sentimental—are no more essential to the attraction of the films
than their residual narratives. The obligation to consume communication
(rather than to communicate) supersedes citizenship, even economic ex-
change, as pure being. The commodity form seems almost to escape its
bonds of exchange value, as earlier it escaped those of use, and finds itself on
the brink of leaving behind the symbolic or sign-value ascribed to it by Bau-
drillard (1980). Digital film proposes a mode of communication in which
the central purpose is to create subjects for the object of communication,
subjects that exist only to be subsumed into the object, and thus to achieve
a plentitude in which no further communication is desired or necessary.
The only thing essential to it that the digital retains from narrative is
closure. Benjamin (1969) distinguishes between the traditional storyteller
and the modern novelist. In tales, death is ubiquitous and reversible, but the
novelist needs to write “The End.” Doing so introduces the irreversible
form of death: individual mortality. In death, the protagonist is an individ-
ual whose memories accumulate to give her or his life form and meaning.
The hero of the tale, on the contrary, is typical, and the telling reengages
with the rhythms of a time that repeats and extends itself, in retellings and
in other tales. In the tale, time is a raw material; in the novel, it is a sword of
Damocles. In his commentary on the essay, Scott Lash suggests that because
“Only in a state of transcendental homelessness can time—in the sense of
death as finality—become constitutive of the meaning of life.... [T]he
reader must read the novel in terms of the already known death of the pro-
tagonist” (Lash 1999: 150). Rather than bed the hearer into the web of tales,
| 270 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
0
|
modern communication “fragments into the individual narratives, which
now are limited to the individual’s subjective cultural space and to one gen-
eration of time” (ibid.: 153). The continued acceleration of modernity in-
tensifies this movement to the point at which the individual is knitted only
into a single event, the event movie whose communication is so intense it is
over in ninety minutes. Death no longer underwrites, as it did for Heideg-
ger, the future-oriented process of becoming, so enabling the novelist’s art.
Instead, death itself becomes a model for communication: sifting life’s acci-
dents into the substantial form of its pattern. As integral spectacle, commu-
nication addresses only the present instant, doomed by its dependence on
the cutting-edge to radical obsolescence. Time is tied to the cycles of con-
sumption, rather than the fatal moment of mortality. When the digital ad-
dresses death at all, other than to fantasize an afterlife, it turns nostalgic, as
if mourning a moment when it was still possible to die.
Or indeed, as if mourning a moment when it was still possible to ex-
istasthat vaunted pinnacle of capitalist culture, the individual. As Debord
noted, returning to his earlier theses to define the concept of integrated
spectacle, the absolute knowledge achieved in databases, the absolute
logic achieved in computer programming, and the absolute secrecy of the
military-industrial complex converge in “the erasure of the personality”
that “is the fatal accompaniment to an existence which is concretely sub-
missive to the spectacle’s rules, ever more removed from the possibility of
authentic experience and thus from the discovery of individual prefer-
ences” (Debord 1990: 32). Today, we must doubt even the assumption of a
lost authenticity: the authentic itself has become a special effect, a conno-
tation of a specific type of brushstroke in painting, a specific vocal style in
music, of handheld cameras in Dogme movies. Experience has always been
mediated, but never before to the point at which it can appear to result
inthe loss of tactility (Dixon 1998: 36) and even of the unconscious (Creed
2000). The closure of communication has been achieved in a surface that
draws a veil of illusory emptiness over an impenetrable fullness constituted
bythe integration of subjectivity into the pure objectality of the medium in
itself. That would-be final contradiction, although it may yet become the
springboard for a further development of Hollywood’s monadology, wants
desperately to look like the last glimmer of conflict—this latest, almost
compulsive lie from a system that no longer acknowledges truth might,
allthe same, be enough to permit another mode of cinema to emerge.
| 271 |
Te
ch
n
o
lo
g
ic
a
l
F
i
lm
|
The digital child of the neobaroque is, in any case, not only utterly dif-
ferent from the other media, even those produced by the same corporate be-
hemoths: it is not even the only mode of contemporary cinema, nor is it the
norm against which we must judge the cinemas of the rest of the world. For
all its armored solipsism, the digital pretends that because it is unified it is
unique, and because it is enclosed in its own sphere, there are no far hori-
zons. There are, and they are plural.
| 272 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
0
|
Fantasies of Eco-Catastrophe
Sing out the song, sing to the end, and sing
The strange reward of all that discipline.
—William Butler Yeats1
The Gates of Eden
There are Irish, Scottish, and Welsh nationalists, Basque nationalists, Bre-
ton and Corsican nationalists—and German, British, and French Greens.
The more liberal populations of the old European imperial powers are
chary after a century of racism and genocide. Yet love of the land, the geo-
graphical claim of identity, faith in a natural source of the sense of self still
appeal deeply as political and ethical grounds of action. It is on this basis
that conservation allies itself with conservatism, producing those unusual
alliances between mud-caked New Age travelers and labrador-walking land-
owners that have accompanied protests against the expansion of motorways
and airports across Northern Europe. In some European science fiction, es-
pecially French, the theme of home and nature lost under the burden of
transnational capital has become a sort of allegory of the struggle to restore
real estate to the state of reality.
The best of these films, those signed by Jeunet and Caro and by Luc
Besson, imagine futures of appalling anonymity, postglobal cities plummet-
ing into decay, bereft of hinterland. Where Jeunet and Caro are relentless in
their pursuit of the logic of a decaying ecosphere, Besson has reached into
another tradition to evoke the possibility of salvation for both humanity and
the environment. That tradition, while it promises to reach back and return
to new generations an ancient legacy, is in fact a modern invention with
11
ONEIRIC FILM
| |
roots in Blavatsky’s theosophy and Steiner’s anthroposophy at the beginning
of the twentieth century. It is best known to us today as the philosophy of
the New Age.
For the most part, those who do not share the neomysticism of New
Age beliefs look down on it as gently quaint and morally neutral eccentric-
ity. But, as even the entertainment industry, in the shape of Spielberg’s Indi-
ana Jones and the Holy Grailreminds us, such mysticism has a darker history
among the European powers. Wulfram Sievers, the high-ranking Nazi of-
ficer whose task was to explore the bogus archeology of the Aryans, was sent
by the ideological arm of the SS to seek out the ancient roots of the Teutonic
culture in the Holy Grail and the lost island of Atlantis. Part of a more than
usually pseudo-science of archeology and anthropology, the Nazi quest for
a race-historical construction of the past still quivers in the undergrowth of
European New Age mysticism. Simon Schama’s (1995) essays on the ide-
ology of the forest in Poland, Germany, and England likewise recall the
pseudo-histories that have allowed us to construct the wilderness as the im-
age of a folk soul. The heritage claimed by conservationists, by national
parks, by Green parties, by advertisers positioning wholemeal and organic
produce, even by the wave of caring management consultants that arrived
inthe late 1980s (see Ross 1991, especially chapter 1) is all too frequently
based on a whitening of history. Proximity to the land and racial purity are
all too common bedfellows. The production of national identity depends on
a refusal to accept that nature is indeed a social construct, not a historical
given. The myth of a feudal peasantry living in some idyllic communion with
their environments, upheld in national legends from Robin Hood to the
Serbian oral epic tradition, produces the requisite authenticity, homogene-
ity, and natural status on which the ideology of nationalism can operate
without recourse to imperial histories. This is why it is so insidious, not just
at flashpoints like the Balkans but in the urban civilizations of the great met-
ropolitan powers.
The truism powering Delicatessenis, despite appearances, the same neo-
mystical thesis underlying Besson’s Fifth Element, Subway,and The Last Battle:
that the environment is the mirror of the soul. Whether the corrupted en-
vironment of the city destroys the natural health of the body, or moral cor-
ruption breeds the degradations of urban decay, the theme governing Jeunet
and Caro’s and Besson’s films is that which structures Eliot’s The Wasteland
of 1922, a structure he derives from the earlier comparative religious stud-
| 274 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
1
|
ies of J.G. Frazer (1911–1915) and Jesse L. Weston (1920), centrally the
myth of the Fisher King. In its basic form, the Grail knight comes upon a
land laid waste, whose king is wounded and in some variants castrated. The
healing of the land and of its ruler are the same quest, resolvable in a single
act of courage, purity, and moral probity. Jeunet and Caro’s portrait of cor-
ruption, plainly allegorical of a general state of social ill-health in the pres-
ent, shares the Fisher King’s association of private and public wound. The
ideological unity of moral purity and hearty land is an ancient and power-
ful European myth against which the scenarios of degradation and deprav-
ity, human and ecological, can be played out as fantastic narratives. Echoes
of it still remain in the immigration policies of eximperial colonies, in the
stigma attached to tuberculosis and other diseases associated with squalor.
It powers a certain aspect of European Green consciousness, and in partic-
ular the apocalyptic vision of ecological collapse. Where the approxima-
tionof a life lived in accord with “nature” is promoted as a good in its own
right, it is fairly innocuous. Where it empowers the righteous totalitarian
response to what is promoted as an emergency, it is a dangerous political
myth. Fantasmatically projected onto an anonymous future, Jeunet and
Carot’s derelict world appears only as a further stage on a downward spi-
ral already begun in the late twentieth century. A wasteland without a Grail
knight, Delicatessen(fig. 11.1)sets its protagonists the modest goal of sur-
vival, at the risk of a fatalistic quietism in the face of enormity.
In the version of Lovelock’s (1979) Gaia hypothesis adopted by Jeunet
and Caro, the alien is Man, who has exiled himself from the Edenic inno-
cence of a life attuned to nature. Innocently, nature will attack the denatured
and vacuous culture of humanity, as an immune system would attack a viral
culture. This cleansing work is the task of natura naturans, nature going
about its own work unobserved by science and unbounded by the laws sci-
ence reads into it. But where Kant saw natura naturans opposed by natura
naturata, nature turned into an object of knowledge and named to dis-
tinguish it from the human, this variant on the Gaia hypothesis reads the
opponent as natura denaturata, the denatured humanity that, by seizing on
technology for its salvation, has abandoned its link with nature and assaulted
her in the bargain. Not only does this understanding pitch humanity as man
against Mother Nature as woman, an important gendering that will struc-
ture the film’s narrative resolution; it is a central theme of the loss of child-
hood and motherhood. The lost ability to dream, the disembodied brain, the
| 275 |
O
n
e
ir
ic
F
ilm
|
gormless unmothered clones of The City of Lost Children(fig. 11.2)are all
aspects of technology as denaturing. If nature is to be recovered it will be
through the restoration of paternity, traced in that film in One’s relation to
the little girl, his protégé. In Delicatessen,a similarly important role is played
out in the relation between the clown Louison and the two young boys
whose antics enliven the film’s action and add depth to its conclusion.
In the best-known sequence in Delicatessen,the unexpected harmony of
music, sex, and work in the different rooms of the lodging house become a
unified whole. But its claim to a utopian humanity against the backdrop of
the inhuman, its alienation under conditions of ecocollapse, curtail it as an
isolated instant. Indeed, technology and the capitalist war of each against
all envisioned as the dependent and determined upshot of overtechnolog-
ization, are portrayed as the spiritual as well as environmental pollutants
thatexacerbate the cannibalistic antagonism of contemporary society. The
naïveté of our hero is comic and touching because he alone fails to fathom
the depths of the depravity that surrounds him. Technology appears as a
| 276 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
1
|
| Figure 11.1 |
Delicatessen:concluding rooftop harmonies for the imaginary family under a permanently poisoned sky.
Courtesy BFI Stills, Posters, and Designs.
false nature, an antinature usurping both ecological and human nature as
they should exist—unalienated. That innocence is what makes the con-
struction of an alien humanity so distinctive a quality of the film. The satire
of Delicatessendepends on an intuition of what a whole nature would be like.
This ideological presumption of a shared memory of wholeness, essential
for the film to work as narrative and for it to meet its audience, is itself a con-
struct, and a dangerous one.
The danger is, in a curious way, particular to representational media
when, as in Jeunet and Caro’s film, they address us in the double mode of de-
piction and spectacle. On the one hand, we delight in the capabilities of the
cinematic apparatus; on the other, we try to peer through it toward the
pleasures of an impossibly pure depiction of an utterly unmanipulated real-
ity, forgetting what we have always known about the factitious nature of the
mise-en-scène. At a more ontological level, our knowing alertness to the
postproduction manipulations of compositing and computer-generated im-
aging promotes a willing mistake of the world-for-itself, natura naturans,for
| 277 |
O
n
e
ir
ic
F
ilm
|
| Figure 11.2 |
The City of Lost Children:One and Miette: personal loyalty transcends the vileness of a corrupted world.
Courtesy BFI Stills, Posters, and Designs.
the world as it presents itself to the camera. Because we feel we can distin-
guish between the spectacular cinema of effects and the documentary real-
ism of the older cinematography, we have a greater faith in unmediated
recording than before the advent of photorealistic illusion. Perversely, then,
the more our films call to us with their displays of postcinematic tech-
nique—in the sense both of film after photomechanical recording and of
film subjected to postproduction effects added after the moment of perfor-
mance to camera—the more we hanker for an unmediated relation to the
world. That yearning for the unmediated becomes the narrative goal of this
ecoapocalyptic cinema.
A recent series of North American films suggests that the theme is not
unique to Europe, though the directors of two comparable titles, Dark City
and The Thirteenth Floor,are Greek-Australian and German, respectively.
The real for which the protagonists of these films hanker is that icon of
ecological harmony, the seashore, where land and water, finite and infinite,
meet as equals on a shifting border, and where the idyll of a renaturalized
humanity can be lived out, washed by the purifying waters of the ocean. At
that dreamed-of shoreline, the human confronts the limitless mercy of na-
ture. Far more important, he forgives himself his own past crimes. The ide-
alized experience of nature is embodied in this unmediated meeting of the
man and the waves. Typically, the most highly mediated narratives are those
that tend to resolve themselves in the idealization of the unmediated. Even
were unmediated perception a possibility, yet this construction of it would
be deeply flawed, because we meet it not as actuality but as depiction.
In the fantasy of a healed and reunified human nature, for whom the
natural environment is posited as an absolute good and enjoyment of it as
both moral right and ethical obligation, what relation is being constructed
between human and nature? The figure of the littoral man is specifically a
narrative image, and even more specifically a concluding image. As such it
is not a resolution but the image of a resolution. There is something of a tru-
ism in film studies that the final scene defines the meaning of a film: we
might call it the Rosebud thesis. But just as the ambiguous sled in Citizen
Kanetells us a great deal less about the film than almost any preceding scene,
so the littoral man at the terminal beach tells us little about the pleasures and
conflicts the preceding ninety minutes have offered and enacted. The mean-
ing of a film rarely resides in its conclusion.
| 278 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
1
|
Dr. Johnson observed of Shakespeare that “When he found himself
near the end of his work, and in view of his reward, he shortened the labour
to snatch the profit” (Johnson 1969: 66). Much the same is true of the com-
mercial cinema. What makes moving pictures move, as both affective and
narrative devices, is conflict. Resolution of conflict may be commercially
necessary, ideologically desirable, and rhetorically acceptable as a way of
stopping that movement, but it is rarely the privileged moment that reveals
the film’s motivations. The felt antagonism between culture and nature, the
built and natural environments, biological and technological processes, is
not “resolved” in the figure of a man standing on a pier. Like the pseudo-
psychotherapeutic fetishization of “closure,” the image of the littoral man is
entirely irresponsible sentimentality, like those images of starving children
we have no intention of ever meeting and the obligatory wildlife documen-
tary lament for fragile environments we have no intention of protecting.
The terminal beach and the littoral man are sentimental because they invite
us to enjoy their unmediated harmony as spectacle. Their spectacular har-
mony is the overdetermined resolution of a dialectic that we are nonetheless
aware is far from resolved, and which is indeed dialecticized once more in
the spectacular mediation of immediacy.
To their credit, Jeunet and Caro avoid that sentimentalism. And yet, as
Fredric Jameson argues of the transition from modern parody to postmod-
ern pastiche, the parodic relies on a shared system of values that, under the
conditions of postmodernity, can no longer be assumed (Jameson 1991: 16–
19). In the culture of the late twentieth century, one of the few values the
film industry can appeal to is the equation of nature with the good. The rise
of Green politics, indeed, disproves Lyotard’s (1984) thesis that our epoch
is characterized by the demise of master narratives: the Gaia hypothesis and
similar apocalyptic ecological scenarios have become the most widespread
basis for political action since the self-destruction of communism in 1956.
The equation of the natural with the good, or at the least the unavoidable,
strikes us, children of Darwin, Freud, and Keynes, as self-evident.
Nor is it adequate to argue that in some fashion the movie business mis-
represents the truth of ecopolitics. There are no truthful representations. To
be depicted, the world must be other than both the medium in which it is
depicted and the agent—human or technological—that does the depicting.
This is the burden of Kant’s distinction: natura naturans,nature naturing, is
| 279 |
O
n
e
ir
ic
F
ilm
|
not the same as natura naturata,nature as the content of regimes of knowl-
edge, morality, and use. Nature is always othered in that single action of
representing. Jeunet and Caro pursue a fascinating course in showing us
denatured nature, but since the film functions primarily as spectacle, that
denaturing serves only to reinforce the ideological faith in a truly natural
nature that exists as the object of scientific or artistic contemplation. Nature
is good only so long as it is other. Its moral status depends on its difference
from the contemplating lens or eye. The very act of taking responsibility for
nature, in the terms demanded by those wildlife documentaries, turns na-
ture into an object over against the human subject.
The truth of good nature as it is depicted in cinema, mediated as spec-
tacle, is as truthful, only and precisely, as the montage of wilderness views
accorded to the dying Edward G. Robinson at the close of Soylent Green:
apainted paradise, an illusion within an illusion. On our behalf, Robinson
witnesses a crucial turn of the dialectic: that nature has become spectacular
for us. We stand, as human, by definition outside and against nature, which
exists for us, today, only as object. The spectacle is itself an effect of the com-
modity form in consumer capitalism, so all-embracing that we have become
accustomed to the policy statements implying that the purpose of factories
is not to manufacture goods but to produce jobs—jobs having themselves
become empty signifiers rather than productive engagements in the world.
That nature against which our species fought so hard for so long is now so
profoundly conquered that we permit ourselves the tourist pleasure of vis-
iting our vanquished enemy in her chains, as we set off to excolonial posses-
sions in search of an impossible authenticity. If, as Green political thought
has it, nature became object in the industrial revolution, in the consumer
revolution it has become spectacle. But, as Slack has it, “the pristine is not
an unambiguous resource” (1998: 87). Belief in an unalienated nature is an
aspect of the spectacularization of nature, and faith in an unmediated per-
ception of it is nostalgia for a state of affairs that never existed. In the end,
that nostalgic tone is what deprives Delicatessenof a politics, even as it pro-
vides it with an ethics.
The relation to nature as spectacle arises not as a quality of the world
but initially as a problematic relation to the self. By posing the world as
(spectacular) object, the self posits itself as subject of this spectacle. Specif-
ically, in replacing the interactive relation with others by the relation with
the world as object, subjectivity becomes, in that mirror, a troubled image
| 280 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
1
|
of the entirely void and the entirely self-sufficient, which are the conflicted
characteristics of the spectacle. Unlike the closure afforded by the submis-
sion of self to world in digital film, this relation to the self is an unhappy and
unstable one. Unhappy because it is deprived of any relation but that of dif-
ference by means of its self-sufficiency, while by reason of its emptiness even
that difference is rendered indifferent and so meaningless. This unhappy
consciousness is apparent most of all in Julie, the cello-playing daughter of
the butcher, whose very existence depends on the central operator of the can-
nibalistic system, whom she despises, refuses to forgive, attempts to kill, and
yet whose gifts have allowed her to survive thus far, at the cost of a lack of self-
esteem and, in her near-blindness, a cinematic mode of self-ignorance.2
This unhappy self is unstable. On the one hand it seeks integration into
a whole—the integrated spectacle—which, however, reveals itself to be
wholly surface. On the other, because it is a product of the objectification of
the world, the self is simultaneously master and slave, dependent on and
responsible for the world. This binary of freedom and necessity can be re-
solved only dialectically, by our overcoming the difference between self and
world, but to do so we must sacrifice self and world, so risking once again
the undifferentiated indifference of the commodity spectacle. The option of
tragic failure is enacted by the character of Aurore, who believes her suicide
is dictated by internal voices, and although her admirer’s brother confesses
to being their actual source, she clings to her delusion and to her suicidal
destiny rather than believe in the power of an external other over her inter-
nal freedom, however self-destructive.
Habermas’s axiom—“the self-relation arises out of an interactivecontext”
(1992: 24)—makes strange this now normative yet unhappy and unstable
relation of self to self and self to world. Habermas restricts interactivity to
human agents engaged in rational discourse, but communication cannot be
restricted to rationality: it embraces communication with the natural envi-
ronment. The sentimental relation with the environment merely regrets its
degradation, and the imperial asks us to assume sole responsibility. But
where the natural world addresses us as an agent in dialogue, this responsi-
bility is neither personal nor exclusively human. It belongs instead to a
polity that includes the environment as protagonist and citizen. The inter-
twining of community and environment in Delicatessenreads this interac-
tive and autopoetic conception less as sympathetic magic and more as a
dialogue, or at least a feedback loop. The principle is the old slogan, you are
| 281 |
O
n
e
ir
ic
F
ilm
|
what you eat, given the anthropophagy that forms standard diet in the apart-
ment block.
Delicatessen has great difficulty realizing this dialogic conception of the
ecological relation. But it does introduce us powerfully to a third partner,
alongside nature and human society, that engages in the constitutive dia-
logue of ecological subjectivity: technology. The kind of humanism that ex-
cludes machines from dialogue with humans and environment is in hock to
nostalgia for immediacy. Only a recognition of the technological media-
tionof this and any dialogue—from architecture to cinema, food to speech,
clothing to music—centers mediation in the technical relation between en-
vironment and consciousness and allows for the possibility that the world
perceives, understands, and thinks us. Understood as an active partner in
the dialogue, technological mediation constitutes that difference between
self and world through which alone dialogue becomes possible.
Ecological realism demands such a relation of dialogue over and above
depiction, which too often has been associated, as in the cartographic (Harley
1989, 1990) and orientalist traditions (see Tawadros 1988), with mastery.
Clearly Delicatessen is anything but a realist film in Bazinian terms. Yet in
certain ways, and especially in its confusing of mise-en-scène and postcine-
matic, postproduction effects, the film foregrounds the mediating functions
of cinema as technology. Praiseworthy as this foregrounding is, the substi-
tution of technological spectacle for environmental dialogue sets the stage
for the film’s ecopolitical failure while offering a model of what a successful
ecoethical film might look like.
Muddle
Caught up in a Catholic phenomenological movement informed by Sartrean
existentialism and colored by the critical theory of technology developed by
the great Jesuit philosopher Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, Bazin permitted
himself a belief in the world as objectively an object since it was created and
known by a God to whom, as its creator, it was already primordially other.
Without the alibi of a divine gaze in which the truth of nature might be
thought of as separate from humanity, contemporary secular media have to
understand nature as alien to audiences, and audiences as alien to it.
This understanding is no longer, however, a matter of divine ukase
issued at the doors of Eden as they clang shut. Rather it is a materially and
historically specific condition subject to all the usual social laws, and, as Del-
| 282 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
1
|
icatessenadumbrates, evolution itself is technologically mediated. Technol-
ogy as it exists in this film is no one-way relation in which human will is
imposed on a passive and objectified environment. Instead it figures the
reciprocal imposition of natural laws on the extension and complication of
human faculties. The cinematic technologies that Delicatessenembraces are
not barriers placed between (subjective) perception and (objective) world but
active participants in the mutual construction of both. By placing the tech-
nological relation center stage between subject and object, the emphatically
technological aesthetic of Delicatessenthrows the relation into conflict again.
Neither Eisensteinian humanism nor Bazinian realism had been able to get
beyond the binary opposition of perceiving subject and perceived object:
Delicatessenlearns from both how to render that opposition dialectical again.
The film faces its greatest crisis in its need for a harmonious resolu-
tiontothe conflict. There is a deeply ingrained historical aesthetic sense
that guides filmmakers toward a satisfying ending. The feudal narrative’s
conclusion arrives as sententia; as already noted, Shakespeare huddled
hisendings; by the time of Jane Austen and even more so of the great
nineteenth-century novelists and dramatists, the ending has become a sty-
listic tour de force, the endgame in which not only are loose ends gathered
up and sententiae enounced but all ideological conflicts brought to res-
olution with the finality of a Brahms symphony. It is a gestalt that urges
ustoreconsider apparent motives, to understand hidden causes, to un-
ravel overlooked clues and to revise the opinions voiced by characters. If
there is a certain brutality to this totalitarian gearing of narration to its
conclusion, it is nonetheless conducted in the awareness that conflicts ex-
ist,and that out of conflict something new can be born.
The near-comic tidiness of database narratives’ conclusions does away
with that possibility. The ending spatializes the fiction and distinguishes it
from any externality to secure the triumph of identification with the die-
gesis. Despite the apparent similarities, Delicatessentakes a subtly different
route. The loose stair, for example, has the idiosyncracy of a Jacques Tati gag
until its reappearance in the unfolding plot resituates it so thoroughly that
it becomes a motif serving the intense formality of the ending. The bizarre
auditory properties of the plumbing, conductor and originator of sounds,
have similar multiple functions concentrated in the elaborate perepeteia.
Soperfectly is the ending orchestrated as necessary outcome of the film’s
logic as to place its resolution inside inverted commas, encompassing it
| 283 |
O
n
e
ir
ic
F
ilm
|
inirony, and so mocking both the enormity of the characters’ situation and
the audience’s engagement with them. It is a strategy of impotence.
Delicatessensets itself small goals. Amelioration of the immediate prob-
lem—will Louison escape anthropophagy?—and personal salvation—can
Aurore deliver herself from her demons?—are the lonely goals of the nar-
rative conclusion to a film that gives away neither the causes of nor the
solutions to its mise-en-scène of ecological disaster. Its proposition is that
happiness is possible only in small things and among small people. A certain
humanism guides this ending, Julie’s cello and Louison’s singing saw har-
monizing on the roof where surrogate children play. Like the children of
Tati’s Mon Oncle, these relieve the adults of the necessity for sex, and the
children themselves of the guilt of generation. Meanwhile, the earlier mon-
tage of work, love, and music as a single harmony endows this concluding
scene with the symbolic value of an ideally innocent family. This closing
shot, with its appeal to the romantic trope of the rooftops of Paris, sums up
and redirects the film’s echoes of Popular Front films like Carné’s Le jour se
lève,Pagnol’s Marius(evoked not least by the Provençal accent of one of the
cast) and Renoir’s Le crime de M. Lange,with their evocations of apartment-
building community and the camaraderie of the courtyard. But where those
films had explicit political programs, Jeunet and Caro derive from them
only the chiaroscuro stylistics and the nostalgic sense of predestination
characteristic of 1930s French poetic realism (see Andrew 1995). These der-
ivations sentimentalize community. We cannot therefore look to the ending
for a summation of the ecopolitics of the film. Instead, the ending strips the
scenario of both ecology and politics. And although we can surely enjoy be-
ing beguiled by the disillusionment with politics, the abandonment of the
diegetic world in favor of the protagonists that inhabit it cannot resolve the
initial conditions that the film sets up. Classically modernist in its romantic
individualism but clothed in postmodern irony, the final scene fails to re-
solve the central theme: survival.
Worst of all, the final scene mocks honorable resistance as futile, slap-
stick muddling-through. Like Mr. Tuttle the heating engineer in Terry Gil-
liam’s Brazil,the Troglodyte underground of Delicatessenare clumsy dimwits,
creatures of a world they know enough to hate but which they have no
means to revolutionize. The motor of the narrative, then, is not contradic-
tion but self-contradiction, and its conclusion is only the vindication of the
self as the site of a mitigated, circumscribed, temporary, but finally invalu-
| 284 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
1
|
able happiness. On the other hand, the story, cunningly plotted as it is, is not
the central charm of the film. What fascinates is less plot or diegesis than the
self-conscious mediation and spectacularization of the mundane. Achieved
through compositions emphasizing mechanical vision—the camera situ-
ated where no human eye could fit—and the use of graphical and sound
matches, the estrangement of the present, one of science fiction’s honored
goals, is here achieved through a double activity of situating the everyday
under that aspect that links it to the recent past (the quartier, the apartment,
the local shop) and projecting it into the near future. Notable by their ab-
sence are multinational corporate logos, symptomatic of the characters’
abandonment by their world. In place of transnational capital, we are pre-
sented with a local politics of patrons and tenants against which the human-
ist anarchism of the film’s conclusion is a suitable if unconvincing raspberry.
Sentimental in its narration, nostalgic in its mise-en-scène, the film’s
greatest strength is in its mischief. The two small boys with their home-
brewed technologies for making mayhem and their capacity for amazement:
are these the signatures of the film’s two directors? Reveling in the techno-
logical, the boys and the directors can revision community under the guise
of retroengineered objects like the talismanic singing saw. Throughout the
film, technologies, especially ad hoc technologies like the painting machine
formed from braces, embody the emotional and social relations between
characters, while the shopworn psychologism of an older Hollywood and
astill contemporary art-house cinema is shuffled to one side, a matter of
tokens, like the sensuality of the butcher’s mistress or the poujadismeof the
postman. The drama eschews conflicts within individuals to embrace con-
flicts within a community, and especially conflicts enacted through such
emblematic technologies as the butcher’s knife, his mistress’s bloomers and
his daughter’s eyeglasses. The drama arises from these thoroughly mediated
interactions, not from the subjectivities of the protagonists, nor, therefore,
from the problematic of the self. Where ethics concerns the primacy of re-
lationships, this is an ethical film.
Yet since that ethics does not embrace the natural environment, we are
left in a quandary. The clown Louison gives us a model antithesis to the
butcher. He is a vegetarian whose deepest relationship has been with an
animal, his chimpanzee partner Livingstone. Yet his triumph lies in his ad-
justment to heterosexual and, more specifically, human romance. And mean-
while, although the sky has been tinted a pale shade of orange (the promised
| 285 |
O
n
e
ir
ic
F
ilm
|
Age of Virgo), the impossibility of anything ever growing back, first an-
nounced by the butcher in dialogue with the taxi driver, is never contra-
dicted. Nature is externalized from the new community, and what hope
there may be is only that based in the oldest of all predestinarian technol-
ogies, the zodiac. But though it is a vast celestial clockwork, our relation to
astrology is always anchored in the random moment of birth. This play of
necessity and chance is key to the role of special effects in contemporary
media formations.
The Gender of Chance
In contrast to the North American cinema of submission, the European and
especially the French cinema embraces its unhappy consciousness. There is
here an echo of the other side of predestination, casino capitalism and the
cult of luck, tied to the emergence of a global economy so vast as to operate
beyond the capabilities of individuals to imagine its operations, let alone
influence them. The Comaroffs describe these new belief systems and the
service economy model of religious belief that they spawn as “occult econ-
omies” (Comaroff and Comaroff 2000: 310), noting that “To the degree
that millennial capitalism fuses the modern and the postmodern, hope and
hopelessness, utility and futility, the world created in its image presents it-
self as a mass of contradictions: as a world, simultaneously, of possibility
and impossibility” (ibid.: 315). Chance and necessity, randomness and des-
tiny, are the obverse of one another, another binary disguising the stasis of
a global system with no desire to evolve, no hope for a future. Delicatessen
plants itself with almost ludicrous faith in the field of the probabilistic, while
The Matrixdwells in the shadow of necessity, but both inhabit the same uni-
verse in which what appears necessary from one aspect appears random
from another. So in The Fifth Element,the monastic cult is empowered, with
the active encouragement of the audience, to play with unknown forces of
nature to restore planetary health, and Korben Dallas (Bruce Willis), as
Grail Knight, to restore wholeness through the healing power of virtue.
Bycomplete chance, Dallas comes to achieve his necessary destiny.
The term “fate” describes the quite comprehensible way in which life’s
circumstances circumscribe our choices. Fate concerns how we got here: it
describes the presence of the past. Destiny, on the other hand, concerns the
future. “Taking one’s fate for destiny,” Bauman notes, “is a grave mistake,”
the error of fatalism, in which the persistence of the past that defines the
| 286 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
1
|
present is extended into the indefinite future. “Taking distance, taking
time—in order to separate destiny and fate, to emancipate destiny from
fate, to make destiny free to confront fate and challenge it” is the task of so-
ciology (Bauman 2000: 210). Bauman’s freedom is the ethical obligation to
maintain the possibility of an open future. Erasing the distinction between
fate and destiny amounts to an acceptance of the present and its determina-
tions as the sole dynamic forces operating on the future, so foreclosing the
possibility of difference. The aesthetic is the alternative: the possibility of
evolving, of becoming otherwise than the present, and more especially oth-
erwise than the past. As André Breton put it, writing of “the time when the
surrealists were right,” “it cannot be a question under a capitalist régime of
defending and maintaining culture. Culture only interests [the surrealists]
in its becoming” (Breton 1972: 98).
Bazin is not alone in believing that the shock of the train entering the
station is the birthplace of a cinema of dreams, an oneiric cinema whose
characteristic technique he identified in the 1940s as superimposition (Bazin
2002). The theme underpins the theoretical writings of Eisenstein and his
early if not his later films. The dialectical montage of the early Russian cin-
ema is worked out in one direction by the Stalinist total cinema, in another
by the trajectories of the surrealist cut, in layers within the image and in
transitions from shot to shot. Bazin’s interest in superimposition as a tech-
nical evocation of the supernatural is a tacit recognition of the claims of sur-
realist montage: that the surrealist object is capable of disconnecting the
dreamwork from the artifices of repression and socialization. Like the pas-
sages from present to past in Bergman’s Wild Strawberries (Mazars 1965:
180), surrealist collage and montage allows multiple pasts, some of them
suppressed or imagined, to cohabit with and pluralize the cinematic present.
Such use of the cut does not synthesize wholes. It manufactures a wild pro-
fusion of surplus metaphors and so undercuts the metaphorical underpin-
nings of social and personal cohesion.
The “permanent revelation” of surrealism always risked descent into
kitsch. Today it has been split between elitist vanguardism in the international
art market and banal expropriation in various drug cultures and advertising
campaigns barely distinguishable, eighty years on, from postmodern pas-
tiche. Yet there is all the more an onus on film studies to account for the pleas-
ures of the fantastic and the surreal, if they are, as they seem to have become,
intrinsic to contemporary media formations. In a prefiguring of Bauman’s
| 287 |
O
n
e
ir
ic
F
ilm
|
distinction between fate and destiny, Lukacs makes a kind of peace with sur-
realism when he writes that “the fantastic is not the opposite to living, it is
another aspect of life: life without presence, without fate, without causality,
without motivation” (cited in Elsaesser 1987: 21). Film is a fantastic medium
to the extent that it accepts the materiality of the profilmic without forming
it. A kind of automatic empiricism governs its associations of objects, just as
the technology of the lens combines and severs foreground and background
according to machinic logics that traverse and transgress socially conformed
regimes of vision. As pure surface, the succession of images is purely additive.
Causality is elsewhere, and with it the structuring force of psychological or
social motivation that might determine action. Things merely occur. Surre-
alist cinema emphasizes this aspect of the film, against the current of psy-
chological realism and continuity cutting that seek to return these random
collocations to order, meaning, presence, and destiny.
This objectivity, this disciplined work of cinema defines its difference
from the surrealism of Bataille and his circle, from Artaud, for example, for
whom “the cinema is made primarily to express matters of thought, the in-
terior consciousness, not by the play of images but by something more
imponderable which restores them to us in their direct material, without
interpositions, without representations” (Artaud 1978: 50). Such, for ex-
ample, is Dalí’s kitsch collaboration with Hitchcock on the dream sequence
in Spellbound. A depiction of a psychological state ascribed to a fictional
character who, by definition, cannot have an interior life, the sequence en-
tertains to the extent that Dalí’s pastiche of nineteenth-century beaux arts is
amusing, but is otherwise a simple case of false witness in the service of in-
dividualism and destiny. Dalí’s dream, like Artaud’s “matters of thought,” is
the evidence that will resolve the conflict between self and society. In the
surrealist cinema, on the contrary, that conflict is not only irresolvable but
uninteresting. The sense of self is only an intersection of multiple, overlap-
ping pasts. The machinery that produces it as unstable and temporary is
what interests oneiric film.
The function of the surrealist object is not to express but to serve as a
machine for producing automatic events, emotional states and states of the
world beyond human authorship. Not only does it not offer to express a
character’s psychology: it cannot express an author’s inner being. Its task is
not exploration, still less explanation, of psychology but the construction of
apparatuses in which the dependency of the world on the psyche and the
| 288 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
1
|
mutual interdependence of the psyche on the world are enacted in ways that
inveigle an audience into revery, uncertainty, exploration. The surrealist im-
agination is not a function of the mind but a relationship between bodies.
The artist is merely the first interpreter of the images produced by the auto-
matism of cinematography—the one who, for example, gives them a title.
Cinema is a surrealist object in the sense that it stands outside authorship,
adevice for manufacturing rather than securing images, for producing
rather than expressing psychic states. Where psychologism prefers depth,
surrealist cinema loves the disjuncture between layers. In this sense the
workof Jeunet and Caro is exemplary: “This well-oiled machine lacks nerve
and demonstrates not the least emotion” (Prédal 1996: 668); “With unde-
niable efficiency [Jeunet and Caro] recycle human figurines borrowed from
poetic realism and penny dreadfuls, artificially animated in a series of clumsy
skits based on winks, gadgets and bogusness at no risk to anyone” (Frodon
1995: 802).
Bogusness (mauvais esprit) is just that unhappy consciousness whose un-
happiness the neobaroque has sought to heal. The fantastic in cinema can
choose to heal, or to fetishize the binary, as happens in the horror genre. But
it has also the option of embracing unhappiness, not to render it fatal in
Bauman’s or Lukacs’s sense, but to insist that only in that unhappiness is it
possible to recognize the lack of fit between consciousness and world. When
for example we confront moments of Delicatessenwith feelings of disgust,
there is no ecstatic plunge into abjection and the vile, but what is more fit-
ting for action, an awareness of the banality of dirt, the casual nature of or-
dinary violence. Offering neither the purified enjoyment of the sublime nor
the reified psychology of individualism, the film engineers a machine for the
production of unhappiness. The symphony of the ceiling-painting braces,
bedsprings, novelty toys, and cello practice is the cinematic equivalent of
Duchamp’s great bachelor machine, the Large Glass,with its endless and ab-
surd productivity of something that never quite achieves the status of mean-
ing. Outside some films signed by David Lynch, few films in North America
attempt anything comparable, and when they do, they come swathed in psy-
chobabble that disarms their radical possibilities. Even then, the menacing
invisibles that thrum in the soundtracks distinguish Lynch’s more expres-
sionistic psychologism from the surrealistic apparatus of Delicatessen and
The City of Lost Children.
| 289 |
O
n
e
ir
ic
F
ilm
|
Nonetheless, there is no easy escape from the brute fact of individual-
ity. As Susan Hayward points out, in the postnarrative, postphotographic,
postbiological world of The Fifth Element, despite the fact that Leeloo, the
supreme being, is a woman, it is men who must solve the enigmas and
bring about the dénouement, which Hayward sees as a standard Oedipal
one. Xavière Gauthier, among others, deploys the Lacanian reworking of
psychoanalysis to claim that surrealism is powered by the disavowal of re-
ality characteristic of all perverts, where perversion is always a refusal to
accept the Oedipal ban on those careless pleasures a baby enjoys in the pres-
ence of his mother (Gauthier 1971: 356). For psychoanalysis, the founding
law of socialization is that which establishes sexual difference: the bache-
lor machine of the cinema is potentially just such a fetishistic construct of
disavowal. For the (male) surrealists, this posed no problem: transgression
of sexual boundaries constituted a necessary and obvious concomitant of
revolutionary automatism. In Rosalind Krauss’s reading (Krauss 1993:
315–316), the bachelor machine is less the organization of onanism than
the precursor to Deleuze and Guattari’s body without organs, the paranoid
selfless body of the infant surrounded by machinic part-objects, stripped
of or prior to the meanings and purposes that come from insertion into
the social and environmental systems of desiring machines. The body with-
out organs, though invested with polymorphous eroticism, is prior to and
beyond the claims of gender. The concept of fantasy, however, allows for
both strongly and weakly gendered, bachelor machine and body without
organs to obtain simultaneously. Fantastic cinema works at the level of a
gendered world, but to promote the fantastic possibility of multiple sexu-
alities, cross-gendered or better yet nongendered bodies.
To the fantastic coexistence of incompossible temporalities and sexual-
ities can be added the coexistence of incoherent spaces. The shock of the
new, the never completed leap between tradition and modernity, is a global
event. It is no surprise, then, that “surreal” clashes of imagery should form
so central a device in the cinema worldwide. Mystery, grotesque, eroticism,
satire, ugliness, and dignity combine in rich, distracting disorientations of
realism in the cinemas of Mendieta, Angelopoulos, Patwardhan, Kurostami,
and a hundred others. The clashes of old and new cultures appear in the
comedy of objects, and attitudes become bizarre by persisting out of their
own time: precocious arrivals of futurity, savage returns of tradition, blank
incomprehensions of the present. The gods, indeed, must be crazy. What
| 290 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
1
|
today, and to the cosmopolitan film critic, must appear as global casino cap-
italism is constantly experienced locally as the random irruption of the alien,
while to the metropolitan intellectuals of Lagos, São Paolo, Mumbai, Mon-
treal, Liverpool, or Osaka, the iterations of rituals deprived of the media
formation that once gave them sense and direction equally explode with in-
congruity and strangeness.
Comedies of cultural incongruity may resolve in favor of the visitor (Les
Visiteurs du soir, Crocodile Dundee) or they may explore the explosive energies
that destroy the old traditions when the metropolitan stranger arrives, as in
Chocolat.Such films are not fantastic, insofar as they maintain the manifest
destiny of global capitalism. The cases of Groundhog Dayand Lola Renntare
more subtle. In the former, the antihero must learn how to live well to es-
cape his motiveless imprisonment in a single day that plays over and over till
he resolves its enigma. In Tykwer’s film, three iterations of the narrative re-
sult in three distinct endings, but we are left not with the sense of a moral
justification for the last of them, the only one in which both lovers survive,
but with the sense that the repetition could go on endlessly because there is
no reason, no causal chain, no effectivity of action or intention that can de-
termine or persuade the blind workings of chance. If the former is cynical,
the latter is nihilist, but both sympathize with the foolishness of their pro-
tagonists. Both to that extent go back to the origins of the fantastic film, at
least as they were traced by the surrealists. Richter, for example, analyzes the
dual origin of fantasy in Epstein’s medium-specific concept of photogénieand
the vulgar magic of fairgrounds and circus. That populist, all but folkloric
enjoyment of the grotesque and the magical is for Richter a class rather than
a gendered machine: “The fool who speaks the truth is a philosophical fig-
ure. Throughout human history he has been a favourite of the lower classes,
for in the roundabout manner of folly, he gives shape to their ideas, voice to
their sufferings” (Richter 1986: 63).
At the same time the fool is far more frequently male: the wimp, the
nerd, the geek, the idiot, from national favorites like Norman Wisdom and
John Candy to international stars like Jerry Lewis. In this figure the demas-
culinized masculine becomes not only a source of fun but an object of sym-
pathy. Often, like Mike Myers or Louis de Funès, associated with bumptious
and incompetent eroticism, such figures certainly ridicule the bumbling fa-
tuity of patriarchy, but they also play out the situation of masculinity as a
role that demands too much of its bearers. The bachelor machines of stunts,
| 291 |
O
n
e
ir
ic
F
ilm
|
scrapes, and accidental connections that characterize the action sequences
of their films, with their apparently random attachment of multiple devices
to form a single apparatus of perpetually thwarted desire, is the machinery
of farce, and low farce at that. It belongs not to mastery but to those con-
demned to enact the ideological roles of heterosexuality in the service of
reproducing labor power. The fool’s truth concerns the imbecility of a sys-
tem that demands the full majesty of the phallus from the exhausted work-
ing man.
The transvestite, camp, and polymorph all bring to this figure the in-
nocence of childhood, like Benny Hill’s forever wide-eyed blinking. In The
Fifth Element(figs. 11.3, 11.4), Chris Tucker’s Ruby Rhod follows the tra-
dition of Liberace and Danny la Rue in combining the knowing with the
infantile, like the simultaneous sensuality and childishness of the dumb
blonde. Such types do not require psychological depth: they set themselves
up as counter to psychology, referencing not the inner life but the ways in
which acting out a role reveals the mediations at the heart of human inter-
action. If the depth-psychology model of expressionism asks us to savor the
| 292 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
1
|
| Figure 11.3 |
The Fifth Element: Bruce Willis and Chris Tucker, worlds of action and mediation, definite and
indefinite gender, raw materials for mayhem and catastrophe. Courtesy BFI Collections.
paradigmatic axis of meaning in each individual, the clown machine situates
that meaning as the function of syntagmatic linkage. The former delves into
the essential meaning, the latter sets up fate as merely the raw materials for
mayhem and catastrophe. The desiring machine that builds itself around the
fool is incontinent, incoherent in the manner of Méliès’s Institute of Inco-
herent Geography, a vector whose infinity is that of chance, the triumph of
connectivity over the nodes that it connects. Only the commercial impera-
tive of a happy ending controls the lunacy of its fabrication.
This much is true too of Delicatessen,and perhaps even more so of the se-
quence of coincidences that stitch together the fable of City of Lost Children,
notably the return journey of the flea to its owner so that he can rescue One
and Miette from the sinister twins. Leeloo, the Supreme Being of Besson’s
Fifth Element, genders the machine as feminine. Susan Hayward, contrast-
ing her with Besson’s earlier creation Nikita, notes that “We are led to be-
lieve that she is amazingly strong (her hand-to-gun combat on the paradise/
space-hotel Fhloston), but she has none of the muscularity and vigorous
| 293 |
O
n
e
ir
ic
F
ilm
|
| Figure 11.4 |
The Fifth Element:postbiological prosthetic mutants, morphs of perfected violence. Courtesy BFI Collections.
health we associate with techno-bodies” (Hayward 1999: 254). This fight se-
quence intercuts between Leeloo’s acrobatic martial arts battle and the tran-
sition from elegaic aria to disco fever that transfixes Korban and the audience
of the alien diva in another part of the hotel. The two femininities, one a mys-
tic savant who will sacrifice herself to save the world, the other the battling
gymnast, interweave in a single cinematic machine. It may be that they form
two aspects of a single male fetish, in the manner suggested in Theweleit’s
(1987) psychosociology of fascist masculinity. But if so, they exceed, as spec-
tacle, the machineries of dominance that give them birth. As Hal Foster
emphasizes of the robots, automata, and mannequins of interwar surre-
alism: “Too often strategies of chance are seen as opposite rather than
immanent to rationalization. And yet just as the modernist value of origi-
nality is incited by a world of increased reproductions, so the surrealist
values of the singular and the insoliteare articulated against a world of
increased repetition and regularity. Chance accident and error are thus
bound up with the advent of administered society” (Foster 1993: 151).
The discontinuous motions of serial production appear in surrealist
avant-gardes and the popular cinema alike as parodies of repetition and the
incomprehensible syntax of the Fordist production line. The discipline of
consumption likewise requires an unanalyzable series of discrete experi-
ences. Surrealism might be seen as merely imitating the bizarre juxtaposi-
tions of serialized modernity. On the other hand, Foster suggests, not every
avant-garde has been assimilated to the machinery of dominance. Bound up
as they are with social mechanization, “this positioning gives them a dialec-
tical edge” (Foster 1993: 152). In the same way, the bachelor machines do
not simply replicate the fetishized desire of commodity culture: they set
those desires in motion according to their own logic to demonstrate that
there is no end to desire, and that the contradictions that power its first bud-
ding remain ingrained even as it is rarefied and reified.
Wonder and Despair
The commodity that so wanted self-sufficiency thus acquires a contradic-
tory history. The dream state that inhabits any experience of cinema shares
with the commodity the difficulty of existing in the present. As cut, oneiric
cinema exploits that difficulty, doubling and destabilizing time by juxtapos-
ing layers of different temporalities. As vector, it evokes the multiplicities of
fantasy by opening out this unstably recorded image to its future-oriented
| 294 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
1
|
unfolding. Although that unfolding is “planned” in the production process
before the film meets its audience, it depends on the experience of the
viewer to realize it.
Yet the experience is always unrealized in the sense that its future is al-
ready the planned past of the filmmaker. Man Ray’s claim that film is best
when seen only once rests on this understanding: we cannot see a film twice
without sacrificing its oneiric potentiality, the openness of the film to futu-
rity that arises from the contradiction of the unforeseen and the foreseen,
another task now usurped by television. Recording is already uncanny: the
watching of the recorded image evokes this disturbance of the present in a
way that distinguishes schizophrenic postmodernity from the presence of
the ancients, as Heidegger understood it. The contemporary present is al-
ways an unfolding whose prior determinations govern it, as physical laws
and as habits of perception and cognition. To this extent the contemporary
present is always an informational order, a transmission of data and struc-
ture from past to future that therefore never possesses the pristine inno-
cence of the unrecognizable and the unrepeatable. Those rare, brief moments
in which we experience what is present as present occur to us as epiph-
anies, miraculous abbreviations of memory and expectation into pure be-
inghere and now, entirely exceptional, even spiritual. Habitual perception
and habitual foresight, reenactment and preenactment, shape every other
experience. In the cinema that dialectical interference of the planned and
unplanned, the expected and the miraculous, the banal and the heightened,
can be foregrounded, but only at the sacrifice of the ordinary construction
of meaning in the continuity between past and future characteristic of
Western modernity.
Fantastic cinema retrieves the now alien quality of being in the world
and presents it as supernatural. This explains why film can so readily be ap-
propriated to psychoanalytic interpretation, as text and apparatus, and why
the filmgoer always responds to psychoanalytic commentary with the same
disappointment. What is most precious about the experience of fantastic
film is what is not interpretable: its failure, even its refusal to mean, its
dreamwork rather than its symptomatology, the failure of the letter to arrive
at its address, and the arrival instead of some unintended missive from a to-
tal stranger. The fantastic in film as in life is fantastic insofar as its analysis
is not so much interminable as uncommenceable. Whence the startling
dullness of key surrealist documents: what renders delirious is never what
| 295 |
O
n
e
ir
ic
F
ilm
|
can begin to be analyzed. Hermeneutics addresses the work as past. The
dreamwork of fantasy addresses the work as present, and though it may well
be, and almost necessarily must be, followed by interpretation, the first flash
of the new, the surprising, the lovely, the ugly, is not tied to interpretation
but precedes it, motivates it, perhaps demands and yet refuses it. The sense
of wonder stitches an arc between the vector and the pixel, acknowledging
that in the age of the spectacle, thirdness has relinquished the object’s claim
to truth, even to ideology, in favor of an appeal to the miraculous sensuality
of preconceptual firstness.
The blunt incommunication of the film text is the source of fantasy, not
its depiction. The cinéma du lookof directors like Beineix and Carax as well
as Jeunet and Caro and Besson, nudges toward recognizing the quality of
film as something to look at, an absorber of looking that stylizes its images
to the point that their meanings, narrative roles, and ideological purposes
are subordinated as much as possible to the sheer pleasure of seeing. That
pleasure is far from innocent, shaped as it is already by the stylization of ad-
vertising imagery. The cinéma du look,however, has nothing to sell, beyond
the ticket that has already been sold: a postcommodity, like Un Chien anda-
louand L’Age d’or, “which place themselves above everything that exists”
(Nadeau 1964: 321).
As John Izod observes of Diva,“The structure of the film is startling and
charged with energy that the narrative itself does not fully absorb.... It en-
dows the diegesis with a persuasive virtual reality, which can be understood
as the beginning of an emerging cultural differentiation” (Izod 2000: 191–
192). Differentiation emerges from the virtual, the “almost reality” that
doubles the world with its simulation (Schirmacher 1994: 67), not a psycho-
logical but a sociological and ultimately media-technological doubling that
finds its fulfillment in style, “a self-evolving activity producing a gaze and
opening the ear... a game playing with time and language in which you
discover and forget the self... instead of ecstasy and intensity, the styles of
the self and multimedia express connectivity and application, the skills of an
instrumental life-world” (ibid.: 78–79).
Style, which subsumes story and psychology to itself most fully in fan-
tastic film, is a hybrid that evolves when the authorial self surrenders to the
instruments of cultural creation. Connecting human and machine in the
transfiguration of what is given to sight and hearing disassociates perception
from both individualism (and its attendant psychologism) and anthro-
| 296 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
1
|
pocentrism. The commodity form’s last privilege is the claim to fulfill the
lack in being: “I consume therefore I am.” The neobaroque proposes to ful-
fill the commodity’s spectacular destiny by subsuming subjectivity into the
diegetic world. In the triumph of style in the oneiric film, the diegetic world
is ironized, its planes dislocated from one another, its unreality fore-
grounded, refusing any attempt to sink into its embrace. Rebutted by the
multiplying surfaces of the diegesis, the self is cast back into appreciation,
the distanced pleasure of the observer abandoned to the contemplation of
the space and time dividing it from the impossible world onscreen. Such
contemplation takes as its object, of necessity, the stylistics of the film. That
stylistic look is the film’s work, mediating between world and self. The
viewer’s job is to mediate between the disparate elements of the diegesis.
Contemplation of style renders the subject stylish: self becomes mediation.
Thus the self-narrating protagonists in Gilliam’s films, from Time Banditsto
Fear and Loathing in Las Vegas, and most of all in The Adventures of Baron
Munchausen,whose cosmic egoism dissolves in its own aggrandizement.
The sense of wonder evoked in oneiric cinema is a matter of style
asself-derealization—a special moment in the history of wonder. Fredric
Jameson observes that the decentering of subjectivity that is such a major
theme of poststructural criticism is itself merely diagnostic, and that “only
the emergence of a post-individualistic social world, only the reinvention of
the collective and the associative, can concretely achieve the ‘decentering’
of the individual called for by such diagnoses” (Jameson 1981: 125). The
mere sense of wonder cannot achieve this on its own, though recognizing
that it exists as a human faculty is an essential step. Like every instinct, won-
der becomes socialized as a drive. As hunger that once demanded hunting
and slaying now needs a burger, so wonder has its history. Already in the Eu-
ropean Middle Ages, wonders were at once evidence of God’s omnipotence
or of the consequences of sin and at the same time both commodities to be
traded and “a form of symbolic power—over nature, over others, and over
oneself” (Daston and Park 2001: 91). In the long transition to Enlighten-
ment rationality, wonder ceased to be exercised over the boundaries of nat-
ural law and instead was inscribed in appreciation of the natural order itself.
In the division of scientific from artistic culture, that appreciation was split
between visualization and calculation, the “unresolved dichotomy between
a rationally ordered repository of knowledge and a free-form entertainment
spectacle” (Stafford 1994: 264).
| 297 |
O
n
e
ir
ic
F
ilm
|
Jameson notes how, in twentieth-century modernism, spectacle
achieves an autonomy and a dignity of its own in the emergence of abstrac-
tion from the work of the Impressionists:
So Lukacs was not wrong to associate the emergence of this modernism with the
reification which is its precondition. But he oversimplifies and deproblematizes
a complicated and interesting situation by ignoring the Utopian vocation of
thenewly reified sense, the mission of this heightened and autonomous lan-
guage ofcolor to restore at least a symbolic experience of libidinal gratification
to a world drained of it, a world of extension, gray and merely quantifiable.
(Jameson 1981: 63)
Derived from the reification of vision under conditions of factory produc-
tion and the scientific division of labor under Taylorism, tightly entwined
with the history of chronophotography, the new autonomy of visual style
(and parallel autonomization of sound in both formal and popular music
since the beginning of the twentieth century) retains nonetheless a utopian
vocation.
The sense of wonder, like the instinct for play, belongs wholly to the
world in which it is exercised. In our time, the pitfalls lie on two sides. On
the one hand lies the lure of the commodity sublime, heralded by the neo-
baroque, at its apogee, so far, in the digital film. On the other lies despair,
the fascinated gaze into the pit of ecological collapse. Dr. Strangelove’smon-
tage of H-bombs inaugurates another genealogy, this new fascination with
surviving the end of the world. In Delicatessenand City of Lost Children,
though the protagonists achieve their goals, the world remains dead: a cess-
pit of muck, slicks, and smog in which the desecrated remnants of a nature
utterly denatured outlast the challenges of the storyline, forming their own
alluring world alongside that of the narrative.
The sense of despair that underpins this aspect of oneiric film is cap-
tured in Ivailo Dichev’s account of the end of communism in Bulgaria:
“there is nothing to learn from the fall of communism, no moral to be taken.
The enemy left no corpse behind—you have ruined economies, killed
people, polluted land, but the transcendence as artefact is nowhere to be
seen; the will to power disappeared in being defeated and one could ask one-
self whether one’s life has been real at all” (cited in Buck-Morss 2000: 242).
If, as Jameson argues, it is the critic’s duty to pair the analytical with the
| 298 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
1
|
utopian, there should be some way to build outward from a state where de-
spair of totality becomes total despair, and a way to do so that does justice to
the profundity of the experience of Eastern Europe since 1989. When the
fall of communism was promptly followed by the failure of capitalism, it
seemed both of the great modern systems for producing sociality had col-
lapsed, with an expectable turn to older Orthodox and newer cult religions.
Defeat unmakes. Its contemplation is also a surrender, though in this case
there seems to be no victor.
Poets from Hopkins and Pound to Berryman and Celan have con-
fronted despair as the quintessential condition of modernity. Ecological col-
lapse has overtaken nuclear holocaust as the popular figure of this despair,
and it is one that in the end may be unanswerable. As Mary Douglas wrote,
“any given culture must confront events which seem to defy its assumptions.
It cannot ignore the anomalies which its scheme produces, except at the risk
of forfeiting confidence” (1966: 33). On the one hand, that loss of confi-
dence is the one hope we have for change; on the other hand, it opens the
curtains on a horror that invites to self-immolation.
The strange, the fantastic, the dream, all the modern forms taken by
wonder offer us these choices. Sometimes there is only the will to optimism
with which to confront the intelligence of despair. Anything else, like the fi-
nal coupling of The Fifth Element,is mere sentiment. At its best, and its best
often occurs in scenes and sequences rather than whole films, oneiric film
stands, in this cold light, at the unreal crossroads of the inexplicable event,
deprived of agency. Whether that is an intimation of panspecies connectiv-
ity or an impasse at the end of the history of humanity is the primal ambi-
guity of the twenty-first century.
| 299 |
O
n
e
ir
ic
F
ilm
|
12
REVISIONARY FILM
| |
Once Upon a Time in the Asia-Pacific:
History as Effect
If miracle it be, it was most savage.
—Vincent Ward1
After the End of the World
Invitation to inhabit an uninhabitable world, invocation and refusal of
interpretation, mediation and specter of its impossibility: the oneiric film
responds to the random seriality of factory production and spectacular con-
sumption with chaotic anxiety. The cinema as dream begins to doubt the
category of society. Today “society” no longer looks like a given but an ar-
tifact, a concept hypostatized at the expense of its empiria. The unresolvable
opposition of self and society, and the central sociological problem of the
all-too-visible dissolution of the social, appear now not as qualities of the
world but as constructs of a mode of thought.
The turn to “culture” as an alternative explanatory framework has not
resolved that methodical doubt: Friedman (1995) is not alone in demanding
that we interrogate and condemn the presupposition of culture, singular or
plural, as the best way to understand how we make sense of the world. Both
anthropology’s professional dedication to the illiterate and “primitive” and
cultural studies’ attention to the ethnography of the internal other (youth,
migrants, the working class) are objectifying gazes constructing of necessity
a governing binary opposition between sameness and otherness. The same
conclusion is the upshot of Balibar’s analysis of neoracism (Balibar and
Wallerstein 1991): culture has become an alibi, a concept that, by dint of its
object status in social theory, is now an excuse for othering, marginalizing,
and ethnicizing. The concept of “culture,” like its offspring “tradition” and
its parent “civilization,” today blocks rather than facilitates the communica-
tion of change.
Nationhood has an even weaker explanatory claim. Initially proposed
as resistance to imperialism and now as alternative to globalization, nation-
alism increases in rabidity in direct proportion to the diminishing power of
the state. State funding of film culture, contradictorily aimed at simulta-
neously celebrating and creating national identity, is as common today as
the processes of print capitalism in the formation of “imagined communi-
ties” (Anderson 1983) in a previous generation. The impasses of individu-
ality and the social, tradition and modernity, identity and hybridity are
irresolvable, and not only because they are so defined that there can be no
way through and beyond them. Culture, society, and nation nonetheless
pose the necessary question of historical agency, even if it is in the wrong
terms. History films invite us to inhabit our own societies, cultures, and na-
tions, but to do so they must construct all three. That is the history effect in
cinema.
Historical film presents as complete, at origin, what it seeks to create.
Bazin’s vision of cinema transforming reality into the self-identical it has
never yet been is the type of the history effect that extends to geopolitical
scale the objectivizing tendency to other the world. Film’s dialectical nature,
not least its dialectical temporalities of recording and unfolding, makes it
unusually capable of voicing such contradictions, as also the contradiction
between preserving and creating national identity. Especially where cinema
approaches the quality of dream, it has little difficulty in assimilating these
contradictory purposes to its own oneiric ambiguity, enacting contradiction
| 301 |
R
e
v
is
io
n
a
ry
F
ilm
|
as the ground on which audiences can be made into communicating ma-
chines. Both digital and oneiric film work through the fantasmatic modes of
the individual-society dialectic. The digital at once creates and fulfills the
desire to be self; the oneiric deploys style as the fantastic realization of con-
nectivity. In the historical film, the arguments between inheriting and cre-
ating nationality oscillate between submission to what is and the enabling of
community. The immense, global popularity of the Asian cinema belongs
especially to this claim to both produce and reproduce identity.
To mediate contradiction, especially the passionately fought contradic-
tions of national identity, is not a cozy undertaking. Like warfare, it demands
the articulation of visual intelligence, camouflage, false lures, and encrypted
truths (Virilio 1989; Kittler 1997) with the Freudian dream processes of con-
densation and displacement shaping the interplay of armed struggle and the
struggle for identity. Courage and self-sacrifice, the two typical moments
ofheroism in national epics, rest on a further nest of contradictions: the con-
stitution of the individual as self-identical while also both author of and
authored by a shared national identity, at once universal and particular. Thus
Pearl Harbouris simultaneously a universal outrage and a national catas-
trophe. Akira, on the other hand, fictionalizes the atom bomb as universal
cataclysm experienced on behalf of the world by a single nation.
Akirapitches itself against entropy. Hawking argues that psychological
time is tied to the second law of thermodynamics, according to which we
cannot remember the future because the future by definition contains less
order and less information than the past (Hawking 1988: 155–156). Akira
argues for the opposite: a structuring memory of the future. In dialectical
counterbalance to the cinema of destiny, this most successful export of anime
works in relation to the time of evolution, the biological principle out of
Darwin (1985) that suggests that environmentally favored mutations sur-
vive and multiply. Where the physical principle of entropy sees information
decreasing, the biological principle of evolution envisages organization
increasing through the ever-closer fit of environment and species. Informa-
tion science extends the evolutionary principle by emphasizing the acceler-
ation of evolution in autopoetic feedback loops of environmental alteration,
visualized in Akira’s mutant Neo-Tokyo.
Externalizing information processes as media is integral to the human
variant of the bioevolutionary arrow of time. Cinema, as recording and un-
folding, seems to have evolved precisely to explore the drift between higher
| 302 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
2
|
(larger, more complex) systems like cities, nations, and metanational organ-
izations, simultaneously with apparently atavistic recursions to familiality,
locality, and ethnicity. “Nation” here does not describe a sociological object,
but the result of a process of negotiation in which the claims of older, smaller
units are counterbalanced and played off in the realm of supranational loy-
alties, ideologies, religions, political movements, and cultures. Like finance
capital, these transnational media formations are communicative structures
with typical constellations of media types and usages. For the cinemas of the
Asia-Pacific, the history effect is critical among these uses.
Western discourse either looks forward to Armageddon, or imagines
with Fukuyama (1992) that we already live at the end of history. But what if
you have already survived the end, and have to build on its ruins? What if
the futuristic and the repentant alike rest on the scorched earth of Hiro-
shima and Nagasaki? Akiraand other successfully exported anime like Ghost
in the Shell explore the mutant future. Both, but Akirain particular, strip
from their manga origins the complex subplots concerning renunciation
and spiritual salvation (Otomo 1988–1995). Other films look to the doubling
of the present world with an unseen universe of horror: Wicked City, Blood:
The Last Vampire. In another, more offbeat film, Wings of Honneamise(fig.
12.1), the future emerges as an alternative past.
At a key press conference on August 30, 1945, Prime Minister Higa-
shikuni Naruhiko, appointed to office to oversee the transition from Em-
pire to Occupation, reflected that “the armed forces, government officials
and the population as a whole must search their hearts thoroughly, and re-
pent. Nationwide collective repentance is, I believe, the first step on our
road to reconstruction, and the first step toward national unity” (Barshay
1997: 273–274). With the horror of the bomb fresh in mind, faced with the
downfall of the empire of Greater Japan and the shame of surrender, the
politician utters a theme that seems to resonate in the curious, slow budding
of Honneamise.At the time of its release the most expensive animation ever
produced in Japan at eight million yen, and with a creative team almost all
in their twenties, the film envisions a future-past country of lamplighters
and steam trains, trams, and prop-driven warplanes, a universe that the
Meiji modernization of the later nineteenth century might have arrived at
had it not been urged along other routes by its exposure to Western tech-
nology. Shirotsugu is a disaffected space cadet in the rundown Space Force
whose perennial sleepiness is punctured by a meeting with the girl Rikuni,
| 303 |
R
e
v
is
io
n
a
ry
F
ilm
|
impoverished sole missionary for a homemade religion of renunciation and
impending judgment. The tram that takes the young pilot out to Rikuni’s
rural home, like the tram in Sunrise,seems to leap across decades, and cer-
tainly across modes of understanding and being in the world. Two naïveties
meet as the would-be bumptious lad comes to savor the puritanical regret of
Rikuni’s belief.
Town and country structure the diegesis. Although Japanese and West-
ern experiences of modernization share a growing division of labor and life-
style between city and country (Williams 1973), as Ohnuki-Tierney writes,
| 304 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
2
|
| Figure 12.1 |
Wings of Honneamise:antihero between destructive technologies and the cult of renunciation.
Courtesy BFI Stills, Posters, and Designs.
The success of the representation of Japan as agrarian did not rest on the impe-
rial system. The skilfulness with which political elites mystified and naturalized
agrarian ideology during subsequent periods is only partly responsible for its
success, which owes in large measure to the symbolic significance of rice and
rice-paddies in day-to-day practices through which they became powerful meta-
phors of the collective self. (Ohnuki-Tierney 1993: 98)
The Japanese urban–rural continuum does not depend on the economic or
even dietary importance of rice, both of which are diminishing and over-
estimated historically according to Ohnuki-Tierney. Nor does it depend on
the foundations of imperial rituals in the Edo period. Rather it depends on
the mythic standing of rice as medium of “commensality,” of sharing, hos-
pitality, connection to the gods, the environment, and the cycles of sexual
reproduction. In the imaginary country of Honneamise,the humble bowl of
“terish” seems to work in the same way, a dish whose origin is not clarified
in a brief shot of harvesting what might be wheat or millet. The offering and
sharing of food brings the stranger into the community in a way that idle
urban drinking and gambling cannot. As Dirlik notes of the case of Asian
revolutions that were forced to rely on agrarian movements, “local society
would also emerge as a source of national identity, against the cosmopoli-
tanism of urban centers drawn increasingly into the global culture of capi-
talism” (Dirlik 1996: 24). The political pull of rice farmers, for example, in
1980s agitation against U.S. rice imports, is then an enactment of ethnic
identification far more than economic special pleading.
At the opposite pole to “rice as self” lies technology as the hallmark of
the (Western) other. Surveying the vicissitudes of this formation over the
last two hundred years, Najita chronicles a gallery of attitude changes ac-
commodating exotic Western technology into a cultural conjuncture already
buffeted by the confrontation with Chinese cultural leadership in previous
centuries. Distinctions between knowing (Chinese ideograms, for example)
and being (Chinese), between technical efficiency and aesthetic value, sup-
ported a sense of “cultural certitude.” “For Japanese, self-knowledge, de-
rived from prelapsarian encounter with the gods and the land they created,
always forced a difference between the plentitude of being and otherness,
whether the Other was China or the West” (Najita 1989: 9). In the postwar
period, however, the same strategy of a retreat to certitude seems naïve, even
dangerous if, as Najita argues, the postmodern is inherently conservative,
| 305 |
R
e
v
is
io
n
a
ry
F
ilm
|
allowing for the mechanical reproduction of things as they are and “since
there is no privileged position in relation to history, there will be a variety
of ‘custodians’ of culture, among which the state will undoubtedly be a
strong and self-conscious player” (ibid.: 19).
Andrew Feenberg finds a solution to this impasse in the late philosophy
of Kitaro Nishida. Comparing MacArthur’s then approaching fleet to the
armies of Nebucchadnezar, Nishida noted that
despite their conquest, the Jews maintained their “spiritual self-confidence” and
transcended their merely ethnic limitations to create a world religion. Just so, he
argues, “the Japanese spirit participating in world history... can become the
point of departure for a new global culture” but only if Japan overcomes its “in-
sular” and “vainly self-confident” outlook. (Feenberg 1995: 191, citing Nishida
1987: 116)
Only by accepting defeat could Japan undertake its spiritual role in world
history, and so overcome the Hegelian unification of all cultures under the
Western aegis. The surrender of specificity was the only way to achieve uni-
versal significance.
In its negotiation with the universal, the soundtrack of Wings of Hon-
neamiseeschews the roar of motors for a contemplative electronic keyboard
score by Ryuichi Sakamoto, notably in the sequence of the training flight
through the clouds, light, ethereal, aligning the longing for space with a
spirituality far removed from the stadium rock of Top Gun. The Wingsse-
quence is vectoral, not just in its graphical movement but in its displacement
of totality to a space outside the film’s world, even beyond its concluding
space launch. Its infinity, however, is spatial rather than temporal, even
more so because the world figured is so meticulously fictional—we see maps,
for example, of the land boundary between Honneamise and the neighbor-
ing state.
But there is also another logic running through the film, shadowing the
philosophy of Nishida and especially the “place of nothingness.” According
to Akira Asada, Nishida’s wartime lectures situate the place of nothingness
in the Imperial household. There, nothingness “negates itself and becomes
an empty place.... There, instead of being aufheben-ed toward the higher,
contradiction is dissolved, so to speak, toward the lower. The dialectic of
conflict and strife, which is supposed to evolve into history, is replaced by
| 306 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
2
|
the topology of subsumption which is atemporal and peaceful” (Asada 1989:
277). In this perspective, what Feenberg sees as an overcoming of Hegelian
unification becomes, in Asada’s term, “zerofication.” The word is suggestive,
not least because it is the religious renunciation of not just the film’s philos-
ophy that it evokes, but the animation style. Like many manga of the later
1980s, the film derives a great deal of its attraction from the detail of its de-
sign, and from the use of angles that would be unusual in a cinematic movie.
Many shots have minimal movement, only a few use the movement in depth
that comes with rotoscoping (George 1990), and hardly any use the kind of
spectacular reframing that characterizes contemporary North American
cartoon features like An American Tail.Often a minor fluctuation is all there
is to denote the atmosphere or emotion of a scene: the closing of eyes in an
otherwise static face, the wafting of a curtain. The appeal to a sophisticated
audience’s ability to decipher these small motions grows into an overall im-
pression of lassitude before a world and a life well worth renouncing. The
two major action sequences, the chase and death of the assassin and the launch
sequence, cut in the frame, the edit and the construction of depth, but they
resolve into the absolute indifference of movements in equilibrium.
Like the zero of the Lumières’ flickering views, the action of Honneamise
sums at nothingness, a zero degree of the political that removes its resolu-
tion from history, and from time itself, into the atemporal zone denoted by
Shirotsugu’s orbit beyond Earth’s atmosphere: an empty place from which
alone the strife of warfare and suffering sinks into pure regret, not so much
an end as an exit from history. Where Akiraconfronts the dangers of infor-
mation as evolution, Honneamiseresolves it into imperial nirvana.
Love and History
In Asada’s analysis, Nishida’s noplace is the electronic space of infantile cap-
italism, the playworld of corporate, transhistorical, transnational manage-
ment. Certainly Honneamisemakes great play of the childlike nature of its
protagonists, and the incompetence of their short-sighted, dim-witted, and
tradition-bound elders. Youth, it seems, is a critical quality for films devot-
ing themselves to mythologizing the emergence of the nation-state.
But youth runs up against that other moment of origin, sexual awaken-
ing. Its title a palimpsest of this doubling of origin, 1942: A Love Story(figs.
12.2, 12.3) traces the romance of Naren and Rajeshwir (or Rajju) against
thebackground of the independence movement as it is experienced in the
| 307 |
R
e
v
is
io
n
a
ry
F
ilm
|
mountain village of Kasaouni. The central story is structured around the
protagonists’ immediate families. Rajeshwir’s father Raghuvir Pathak is a
revolutionary whose wife and son have already died in the struggle. Naren’s
father Dewan Hari Singh is a collaborator with the British, although his
mother is loyal to the cause of independence. There is immediately a prob-
lem in the construction of the hero, who “should be the perfect son”
(Darmesh Darshan, cited in Kabir 2001: 113). In the main subplot, Major
Bisht is the sole parent of a daughter who also first falls in love with Naren
and later joins the independence movement before inspiring her father, a
major in the British Army, to do the same. The British are represented by
General Douglas, who is depicted with no reference to family, and whose
relationships are entirely masculine and entirely violent. The interest of the
| 308 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
2
|
| Figure 12.2 |
1942: A Love Story:General Douglas: tyrrany as abstraction from the family.
| 309 |
R
e
v
is
io
n
a
ry
F
ilm
|
| Figure 12.3 |
1942: A Love Story: Major Bisht at the historical moment when colonial service turns to
anticolonial revolution.
film lies in the ways in which the stylistics of the Bombay musical have been
adapted to the purposes of telling a patriotic story, and the significance of
these stylistic choices against the background of mid-1990s communal vio-
lence in Mumbai, Amritsar, and Ayodhya.
The film 1942is one in search of an adequate form in which to resolve
a critical question in the experience of Indian nationhood in the 1990s, or
rather three mutually dependent questions: What is it for a nation to acquire
historical agency? How does a nation become modern? What is the status
of the divine, which plays so significant a role in the self-definition of both
the Bombay cinema and the political life of the country during the commu-
nal violence of the mid-1990s? 1942does not resolve these questions because
they are stated, with considerable political and cultural nous, as inseparable
but, at the same time, incommensurable. Aumont defines analysis as “trav-
elling backwards”:
This is none other than the well known mathematical method which consists in
supposing a problem has been solved. The difference is that in analysing an im-
age, a painting or a film, I do not have to suppose but can assume that the prob-
lem has been resolved: what I have in front of my eyes constitutes its solution.
So analysis indeed consists in travelling backwards, though not in the form of a
demonstration (in the sense of a verification of linked logical consequences).
Rather, starting from the solution that the image gives me, it is a question of
constituting the problem. First question, at the base of any analysis of the im-
age: what is the problem? What problem can I pose starting from this or these
images? What problem does it or do they pose, to which they are the solution?
(Aumont 1996: 26)
Aumont’s principle suggests that we must read films from what they
present to us: that formal analysis of the audiovisual text precedes any inter-
pretive attempt. As Aumont’s title suggests, “films think”: more fundamen-
tally, they communicate, and the mediation between apparatus, text, and
reader is as complex as that between human interlocutors. This film thinks a
construction of history intended to address the rifts in Indian society at the
time of its making. Eisenstein’s Russ, far from speaking to the whole of the
U.S.S.R., was ethnically and geographically specific, and its unity and co-
herence could be assumed. That is not the case with 1942in the 1990s. His-
tory, like nationhood, society, and culture, must be here a special effect.
| 310 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
2
|
The initial crux of the film’s stylistic in the construction of the histori-
cal narrative comes in a shot from the campanile of the British headquarters,
foregrounding General Douglas’s sweating pate, emblem of the difficulty of
rule and the unnaturalness of the Raj. From behind this crag of authority we
peer down to the crowds below, distance doubled by both the mountain
slope defining the village and the camera’s tilt. In a film marked by skillful
reframings in steadicam, we are halted by the privilege of the colonist’s view.
The monumentality and stasis of the shot characterize one aspect of the in-
dependence narrative. But the film must somehow articulate this conflict of
mobility and stillness with the central narrative structure of the love story
that gives the film its name.
The problem is also generic: how to articulate the songs with the nar-
rative. Underlying this formulation is another: how to integrate the love story
into the historical map of the age, a map ingrained in the popular memory
of the film’s key audience. Other films of the mid-1990s would employ the
classical Shakespearean device of lovers divided by factionalism, notably
Bombay.In 1942,all the youthful protagonists, and by the end all but one of
their parents, will have joined the Congress cause. That unity is an essential
part of the film’s unitarian message. It is notable that the revolutionary lead-
ers are Pathak and Ali Baig while the hero’s family name is Singh. The reli-
gious connotations of these names are scarcely adumbrated—there is only
the briefest call of a muezzin in the background soundscaping of one chase
sequence. Instead they quietly indicate an all-India opposition to the Raj.
This unificatory thrust is amplified by the mountain setting in a film made
during the early period of the conflict in Kashmir, directly addressed in an-
other key nationalist film of the 1990s, Roja(Bharucha 1994).
The obvious solution would be to make the theme of romantic, hetero-
sexual love central to the politics of revolution: to make love the goal of the
war, and to articulate its success with that of the revolution. This is in a way
the achievement of the film’s final scene—the lovers united as the hated
symbol of tyranny burns—but it is never articulated in the dialogue. Naren’s
two speeches in which he expatiates on his love for Rajju scarcely mention
the war for independence except as an obstacle to true love’s progress, and
his second speech serves rather to motivate a throwaway subplot concern-
ing the resistance leader Surabandhar’s suicidal knife attack (and subsequent
reconciliation with Naren, his rival for Rajju’s hand). After a touching duet
sung on the mountaintops above the village, there is no shadow of returned
| 311 |
R
e
v
is
io
n
a
ry
F
ilm
|
affection on Rajju’s face, though the match between the revolutionary’s
daughter and the resistance fighter might have provided exactly that recon-
ciliation of love and history which the film seems to demand. The song in-
stead reflects Teri Skillman’s observation that “The emphasis is on the
context, action, and emotion being expressed and not whether it is appro-
priate to the character. The sentiment a character expresses often reflects the
audiences’ emotion” (Skillman 1988: 152). Melodrama, especially as it de-
rives from Indian traditions (see Mukherjee 1985), approaching Ang’s (1985)
definition of “emotional realism”, exaggerates character and coincidence,
and “with its typical focus on the family [and] the suffering of the powerless
good” binds the tearful experience of the heroine or hero narcissistically
into involvement with family, community, and nation (Dwyer 2000: 108–
109). The formula certainly works for the middle-class romances that form
the focus of Dwyer’s analysis, but it is less stable in relation to 1942, where
the nation has yet to be formed and the family is corrupted by betrayal.
Love and revolution cannot be completely articulated. The war, shot
often in colors of flame and sand, forms a series of obstacles to the reali-
zation of romance. The love songs, which include a particularly elegant
rain-soaked “wet-sari” sequence, are coded through saturated color and es-
pecially through fluid, “intentionally obtrusive” (Gokulsing and Dissa-
nayake 1998: 96) steadicam work distinct from the rest of the film. Music
and playback singing figure in key political scenes as well as in the love story,
notably the hummed motif attached to the protesters with their burning
brands and their Swadeshi tunics. Similarly, key motifs from the love songs
also feature at critical moments in the historical narrative, an association
through which they gain considerable emotional weight (notably Mangesh-
kar’s song “Say Nothing”). In this way, song and dialogue sequences are
more closely interwoven than is often the case in Bombay musicals.
At the same time, however, the bright primary colors of several of the
love scenes have no parallel in the restrained palette of the mountain’s lower
slopes in the narrative sequences. Fire and blood provide the strongest col-
ors here, and sharp reframings and hard edits replace the mobile camera-
work of the song sequences. Where the songs are characterized by high
degrees of symmetry among graphically matched shots, the narrative se-
quences more frequently exhibit sudden juxtapositions, leaps from extreme
close-up to long shot or from shadow to light, and rapid shot-reverse-shot
cutting. The use of fast zooms is restrained and often replaced by cutting.
| 312 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
2
|
The result is a depiction of the narrative as typical, in the sense that it in-
volves types engaged in a recognizable taxonomy of patriotic actions. This
itself poses problems.
On the one hand, the film depends on the exceptional nature of the love
between Naren and Rajju. On the other, their sacrifices for the cause are
reflected across so many other characters, especially Naren’s mother, that
there can be no doubt that their heroism is to be understood as a heightened
depiction of the ordinary heroism of the Indian masses. The theme is car-
ried through especially in the death of the comic servant Mandu and the dis-
traction of Govind’s widow at the martyr’s funeral given to her husband after
he has died under British torture. Through such characters the anonymous
crowd is imbued with narrative depth, and we are allowed to feel, in the style
of the Odessa Steps sequence in Potemkin,that each face stores some tale of
brutality and bereavement. Yet the crowd remains anonymous and uniform,
not least because of the politically significant ubiquity of homespun cloth.
Anonymity does not preclude community; quite the opposite. The night-
time sequences most define the particularity of the protagonists in the po-
litical narrative. Interior sets gather the central figures into a shared space,
but the reduced illumination, often just firelight, isolates the detail of faces
to create Rembrandt-like compositions focused on those characters, by no
means all of them studied in close-up, who form the central core of the rev-
olutionary camp. Night and dark catch a sense of intrafamilial emotion, a
familiarity that underpins the emotional structure of the revolution and fur-
ther isolates the family-less, sun-pinked General Douglas.
Often nation is an extension of family, just as romance is its renewal, but
here narrative justice demands also the death of Rajju’s father and the re-
nunciation voiced by Naren’s mother. The narrative works counter to the
family as the ground of revolution, instead presenting it as its result. The old
families fail to provide a logic for loyalty and freedom. Naren’s conflict with
his treacherous father is mirrored in the split loyalties of Major Bisht to the
army and his daughter. The parents have to learn from the children here,
inopposition to the deep-seated theme of family loyalty, and especially
mother-child relations, in the Bombay cinema. The dialectic of modernity
and tradition in nation-formation makes continuity impossible.
Phalke’s Swadeshi politics of the atemporal eternity of village values
remain vital to the ideological task of 1942: A Love Story. But at the same
time, the struggle for independence defines a moment in which village
| 313 |
R
e
v
is
io
n
a
ry
F
ilm
|
values—notably the relation between fathers and daughters and between
mothers and sons—must confront the processes of modernization, and es-
pecially the iconically modern achievement of nation status. Whatever the
problems of nationhood as a Eurocentric goal (Chatterjee 1997; Davidson
1992), it occupies a critical moment between the eternity of the mythic
cycles of ancient wisdom and the progress-orientation of modernity. Al-
ready presupposing that historicizing set of circumstances, 1942moreover
adds to the hero’s motivation a discursive teleology: the achievement of
nationhood. Naren’s achievement of masculinity—of independence from
both his father’s tyranny and betrayal and his mother’s love—is thus tied
tothe independence of his country from both colonial oppression and
thetimeless hug of mythological narration. So it is that, where explosions
and destruction signal an exit from history in contemporary Hollywood—
most egregiously in films evoking natural forces beyond human control like
Twister and Dante’s Peak—in 1942they point toward the cataclysm of entry
into it. Like that precious sense of history as successive moments, narrow
gates through which the Messiah might enter, voiced in Benjamin’s Theses
on the Philosophy of History(1969), the two explosive moments of 1942, at
Pathak’s villa and at the British headquarters, are aspects of the entry of his-
tory into the moribund world of coloniality. Indeed, they might be consid-
ered as a single explosion distributed across two separate sequences: the one
defining the sacrifice of the patriot, the other the death of the oppressor—
mutually dependent moments in the ideological construction of the nation.
Sacrifice is essential to independence because, in Fanon’s terms, it rep-
resents the moment of the assumption of responsibility, and with it “the will
to liberty expressed in terms of time and space” (Fanon 1968: 240). The
Hollywood cinema addresses us, typically, as consumers, and respects most
of all our right to be entertained. The film 1942addresses us as citizens and
respects our acceptance of the duties and obligations that accrue to citizens.
That is the point of Fanon’s insistence on responsibility: blaming the op-
pressor is a prehistorical moment of the struggle, which enters the arena of
“space and time” only when the question of blame is associated with the as-
sumption of responsibility—responsibility for change. The North Ameri-
can vengeance ethic belongs to that prehistory.
Rather in the manner of those medieval courtly miniaturists who por-
trayed importance through scale, Bombay tends to define importance
through duration. Nor is time dilated by deferring the ending, in this film
| 314 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
2
|
both predestined and somewhat inconclusive. Rather, the insertion of emo-
tionally charged, music-driven shots and sequences into the narrative allows
us to appreciate that narration is only part of the film’s charm, that the film
is to be enjoyed as a presentation of the present, not as ahistorical sublime,
whose sensory and affective processes are to be shared with the audience
rather than hoarded by the protagonist. The explosions of 1942last because
they are important, and because they are not events but processes through
which the central figures pass on their way to their changed status, trans-
formed in a process whose temporality is extensive because it is precisely the
time of transition from the banal, closed time of the colonized to the open
time of the free citizen.
Similarly, the explosions are shown from a number of standpoints, by
no means all of them associated with human viewers. The key to under-
standing this quality of the sequence lies a few shots earlier, in the point-of-
view shot of the crowd as viewed by General Douglas from the campanile
ofthe headquarters building. Here it is not simply that the crowd, as the
emblematic instrument of historical change, is viewed from a position of
power, or that we are momentarily invited to share that literally towering
perspective of domination, but that through this shot the very conception
of a single, unifying viewpoint is associated with the oppressor. Compare
the love scenes: there we find as many close-ups of the male as of the female
star, a microcosm of sexual democracy. The over-shoulder point-of-view shot
of General Douglas moreover obscures as much of the view as it reveals:
power is incapable of the omnivoyance it claims for itself, and it will be that
blind spot (Douglas’s disgust at the thought of Indian blood and the perhaps
consequent invisibility of the low-caste water carrier) that precipitates the
denouement. Instead of such a spatially anchored point of view, answered by
the uplifted, fearful looks of the crowd toward the tower, we see the explo-
sions from many viewpoints. For each view we can extrapolate a certain spa-
tial relation and from that a specific emotional response—shock of the ruler,
terror among his troops, disorientation among his supporters, relief among
the hero’s friends, triumph in the crowd. But most of all we see aspects of the
blast that can not be pinned down to any human eye.
In a certain kind of filmmaking, notably in European but also in some
Latin American films, such unmotivated angles can provide a cold, clinical
distanciation from the scene. In this sequence we are instead privileged with
another dominant vision: that of the land itself. The road from dominance
| 315 |
R
e
v
is
io
n
a
ry
F
ilm
|
to liberation is undertaken not only in the familial language of Mother India
but in the sense that there is a higher but now secular source of ethical ac-
tion and, therefore, of aesthetic pleasure, which is that of the nation itself.
Thus the summit of the sequence is not the ahistorical sublime of an indif-
ferent God-shot or of spectacle, but rather a shot that expresses triumph be-
yond the victory of the romantic leads, a triumph associated with the newly
historical centrality of the independent nation. The evocation of a nonhu-
man eye provides us with a sense of justice, especially in the balancing of the
self-sacrificial explosion at Pathak’s villa with the death of General Douglas.
The land itself—the mountains, but by implication a united India—looks
on, demanding only the highest from her offspring and giving them a yard-
stick by which to measure the decency of their actions. This presence acts as
the bedrock of ethical action in the secular democracy it grounds.
The love scenes code emotion in the details of hands, gestures, and fa-
cial expressions, what Melanie Klein would call part objects, removed from
the historical body and translated into mythological time. As Naren says so
often, their love is destined, and to that extent has no place in history: it is
unchanging and therefore ahistorical. Yet that same love must be compat-
ible with the struggle if the struggle itself is to be worth winning. The prob-
lem of General Douglas’s head can now be situated properly. The blockage
it presents to the camera’s and the audience’s vision is not a “third meaning”
as Barthes (1977b) discusses it but a “‘hole in the Symbolic’... the terrify-
ing encounter with the truth that there is no Other guaranteeing the con-
sistency of the Symbolic order and the meaningfulness of the world” (Prasad
1998: 231). Prasad here draws on Zizek’s terminology to describe the produc-
tion of terror in Roja,whose project is largely, he says, to ensure the passage
of authority from the divine to the secular state. In our film, the Raj occupies
the position of the Other illicitly, an emptiness at the heart of meaning.
The solution 1942proposes is that the secular romance takes on the
mythical, structuring role previously afforded to the theological domain
corrupted by the usurpation of the divine by the Raj. Since religion defines
no longer truth but only relations between cultures, the film diminishes the
particularity of the protagonists’ religious affiliations. At the same time,
rather than situate the romance as the narrative beginning of a family, it
places it in a position in which the private, indeed the intimate sphere now
can be premised as the foundation of Indian modernity. Yet unlike teenage
rebellion in the Hollywood canon, from Rebel Without a Cause to Slackers,
| 316 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
2
|
this privileging of the intimate is not founded in an existential void. Where
Hollywood’s teen rebels discover their fullness by embracing emptiness,
Bollywood’s reject the theology of the void for the discourse of completion.
The task of 1942,then, is to describe the emergence of India from colo-
niality into modernity as a transition from myth into history. Using all the
bravura masalamixing of moods, genres, and technical effects endemic to
contemporary popular Indian films, 1942reworks them as dialectic between,
on the one hand, the necessity of reinterpreting the war of independence as
a unified struggle during a period of intensifying communal violence, and
on the other the necessity of reconciling the theological and ideological fo-
cus on the family as source and origin of social meaning with the emergence
of a mass modern culture that is nonetheless historically and culturally in-
imical to Western concepts of individualism.
The film 1942: A Love Storyis a historical document, not of 1942, but
of 1994 to 1996, “an allegory through which a post-Ayodhya cinema wishes
to affirm its own investments in the Indian nation-state” (Mishra 2002:
231). The rewriting of history is itself a historical act. Here that act can be
described as the conversion of the normative spectacle of the Hindi musical
toward the project of realism: the reunification of the dispersed action and
the casual pleasures of motion in equilibrium in order to apply them to to-
tality. In contrast with the zerofication that sums Honneamise’s directionless
flickering, 1942is riven by the demands of totalization.
The Heavenly Fist
Both films demonstrate that the popular cinema can undertake historiogra-
phy capable of articulating present and past. Tsui Hark’s Once Upon a Time
in China(fig. 12.4)emerges from a similar desire. The legend of Wong Fei
Hung, a historical martial arts master who lived from 1847 to 1924 (Logan
1996: 10), has been mined by Hong Kong cinema for decades, starting with
the series of 99 films associated with director Hu Peng, scriptwriter Wang
Feng, and star Kwan Tak-hing (Rodriguez 1997). When Tsui Hark began
work on the latest series, the sixth of which appeared in 1997, the return of
Hong Kong to the republic of China from British sovereignty was much in
the air. The ominous events in Tiananmen Square during the summer of
19892made it essential to find a way of telling history between or beyond
the belligerent or melancholic Sinicism that Tan See Kam identifies as the
governing dichotomy of postwar Cantonese cinema (Tan 2001).
| 317 |
R
e
v
is
io
n
a
ry
F
ilm
|
Once Upon a Timeis also one of the most popular films of the 1990s,
picking up the tired kung-fu genre and infusing it with the visual flair of the
Hong Kong new wave, fast cut and intercut, with an eye for graphic com-
position that appears to owe something to the massive popularity of Japan-
ese manga comics in Hong Kong. Scarcely a shot is without some kind of
compositional interest, flamboyance, or unexpected quirk, and many shots
involve rapid tracks, cranes, and lightning zooms, often featuring wide-
angle lenses with all the attendant skills they demand in keeping focus. The
graphical language of the film places it squarely in the field of the vector,
even as its editing and staging in depth pull in the direction of the cut and
the wild wirework and stunts hold us in the balanced center of the whirl-
wind. In short, this is a film in which the full range of cinematic motion is at
play, and which binds its historical setting tightly to the contemporary
pleasures of highly technologized cinema.
The irony is that the film so consciously and carefully addresses the in-
troduction of Western technologies to China. Westernized Aunt Yee brings
| 318 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
2
|
| Figure 12.4 |
Once Upon a Time in China and the West:from a later film in the series, the confrontation of traditional
and technological worlds. Courtesy BFI Stills, Posters, and Designs.
a camera whose flashpowder kills a caged bird, a traditional Chinese pet,
asif to emphasize the fatal consequences of an influx of Western goods (the
cine-camera will feature in the first sequel). At the same time, as Tony
Williams (2000) argues, the film traces the gradual, grudging acceptance of
the necessity for change on the part of the master Wong Fei Hung. “We
cannot fight guns with kung fu,” says the dying master Yim. Cinema is one
of the technologies through which China will enter the modern world as an
equal. For Natalia Chan Sui Hung, nevertheless, the film forms part of a
cycle of nostalgia films characteristic of 1980s and 1990s Hong Kong, both
as a representation of a now ancient history, and as a recycling of previously
popular forms, the old Kwan Tak-hing series (Hung 2000: 257). David Bord-
well likewise dwells on the way “Tsui often reflects on the national heritage
by examining traditions of vulgar entertainment” from Shanghai pop to
Peking opera (Bordwell 2000: 139), recalling Stephen Teo’s description of
“nationalism on speed’ (Teo 1997: 162). Teo regards Tsui as a nationalistic
auteur whose flirtation with Western technologies is “a necessary step to re-
juvenate the nation so that it may deal with Western intruders and rise up to
face the world on equal terms” (ibid.: 170), while Wong Fei Hung, Confu-
cian gentleman, practitioner of herbal medicine, is essentially a conserva-
tive figure who only under the moderating influence of Aunt Yee can be
brought to cope with the challenge of modernity.
Once Upon a Time is drenched in knowledge of and love for North
American as well as Chinese film history (Dannen and Long 1997: 136), so
much so that history here takes on a double sense. At once the representa-
tion of things enacted long ago and the modes of representation that
accompanied them, Tsui’s historiography is more complex than the ascrip-
tions of conservatism and nationalism would suggest. Tsui’s generation
undertook to make Hong Kong’s cinema anew. On the one hand, as a com-
mercial producer-director with a large company answering to him, Tsui is
adamant: “Film is a mass medium.... The masses go to feel, not to under-
stand” (cited in Bordwell 2000: 138). On the other, he says his movies must
“reflect what we are thinking at this moment in our time” (cited in Stokes
and Hoover 1999: 93). History, as the fate that shapes the present, structures
both feeling and understanding, understanding as feeling. For Hong Kong
especially, there are multiple constructions: colonization by the British, a
distinct sense of superiority over mainland peasants, a fear of Japanese cul-
tural imperialism (Lee and Lam 2002). Identity is a process perpetually in
| 319 |
R
e
v
is
io
n
a
ry
F
ilm
|
formation, perpetually self-critical, and to that extent perpetually modern,
and as a result its heroic figuration cannot be without self-doubt and adapt-
ability. Hence the notable shift from Kwan Tak-hing’s patriarch to Jet Li’s
uncertain wooing of Aunt Yee. Only in action is Tsui’s hero utterly centered
at the still point of the turning world. Otherwise he is as much the necessary
outcome of his circumstances as the most downtrodden of the women slaves
he liberates from the clutches of the Americans at the end of the film.
Moreover, the film is structured along a scale of “Chineseness,” with
treachery at one extreme and unthinking violence at the other, with incom-
petent bureaucracy, cultural conservatism, and the ideology of success at all
costs in between. The position of cinema seems to work along this axis,
from betrayal to hyperviolence (Tsui and John Woo had a famous falling out
over the final cut of A Better Tomorrow,and the author of one fan handbook
notes merely that he “deserves a place in Hong Kong cinema history be-
cause of his influence on directors, producers, actors and genres, but he has
only occasionally directed Heroic Bloodshed movies” [Fitzgerald 2000: 11]).
At one extreme, cinema appears as an imported, alien device; on the other,
as with Phalke, there is the possibility of making one hundred percent local
films. But cinema is both a medium of depiction and a medium whose own
history has begun to enter its vocabulary. It is this revisionary quality that
opens the door for film as historiography. If, then, Honneamisedescribes an
imaginary past in terms of a possible future, and 1942a constructed past as
a moral present, Once Upon a Timesurrenders to the revisioning of a fictional
past for an imaginary future: posthandover, post-Tiananmen.
The film is revisionary rather than revisionist. There are certainly revi-
sionist aspects to Once Upon a Time: the “yellow peril” and its “white slave
trade” dear to orientalist Hollywood (Marchetti 1993) are stood on their
heads to reveal the Americans as the traders in women as sexual commodi-
ties, their features stereotyped with long faces, distorted Cantonese accents,
caricatured villainy, a propensity for stupidity (as when the Americans are
fooled into firing a cannon into the British ship). Like Jackie Chan’s Project
A,there is scant respect paid to the detail of chronology. Instead, the histor-
ical sources are the popular memory constituted especially from previous
screen avatars of the hero, and constructions of imperial bureaucrats and
foreign traders derived from earlier films. This is not a history film in the
way that Neil Jordan’s Michael Collinsis, a carefully documented recounting
of a critical period in Irish history, whose director was deeply conscious of
| 320 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
2
|
the “inaccuracies” and condensations introduced by the necessities of eco-
nomic scriptwriting (Jordan 1996).
These films—Honneamise, 1942, Once Upon a Time—are revisionary,
then, because they do not so much revise history as revision it, look into
itwith a new mode of envisioning the relation between the past and the
present. Revisionary movies draw on older traditions of depiction—the
long centuries of Japanese graphic arts, of popular melodrama and divine
dance performances in India, the recent but nonetheless powerful tradi-
tions of film and television in Hong Kong laid over the popular traditions
of circus, sport, and opera. And what they revision is the old vision. To some
extent they are visionary too in that they displace the fate of the present,
opening instead a vista onto an elsewhere that, although it may not be ex-
clusive to cinema, is nonetheless happily at home there—the popular tradi-
tions of ghosts and the uncanny, cinemas of the invisible. Revisionary film
addresses those mysterious forces and offers in cinemas that are ready to for-
sake the Western ideal of realism, the possibility of understanding how they
might remake the past and so make the present other than it is.
Contemporary historical film (an informative oxymoron) needs to be re-
visionary, needs to undertake the deconstruction of the present, and most of
all in the territory of identity, because identity is no longer a stable creature.
Gwailo and gaijinjostle in the elite meeting places and boardrooms of world
cities like Hong Kong, Tokyo, and Shanghai, in production centers like the
software farms of Bangalore, and in political centers like New Delhi. Chi-
nese and South Asian diasporas spread across the Pacific and Indian Oceans,
articulated through the circulation of popular films with an increasingly dis-
tant home culture. Japanese businessmen throng the corridors of transna-
tional corporations, Chinese students attend universities, Indian medics staff
hospitals around the world. “Since the entire Once Upon a Time in Chinase-
ries involves movement from one geographic location to another, it also
posits a particular definition of diaspora related to questions of national and
cultural identity” (Williams 2000: 11). The significance of Indian and Hong
Kong films to the South Asian and Cantonese diasporas is only one element
of their global success. The significance of Hong Kong movies to the African
diaspora in the Caribbean, the United States, and in the U.K. as well as the
important Korean market is paralleled by the significance of Bollywood in
the former U.S.S.R. and throughout the Arabic-speaking world, not only
among migrants. Japanese animation studios have now spread throughout
| 321 |
R
e
v
is
io
n
a
ry
F
ilm
|
Southeast Asia and furnish television screens with children’s adventures
worldwide, leading out from cinema toward computer games and toys like
Pokemon, tamagotchi, and neo-pets. The sequence early in Wong Kar-wai’s
Chunking Expresswhere Brigitte Lin’s character sets up a smuggling deal with
Indian cobblers indicates the rich interplay of Asian cultures. But for Once
Upon a Time in China,the final confrontation is intranational.
Wong Fei-hung’s grace lies in the perfection of the gesture with which
he completes a gymnastic stunt to settle like a landing bird, incarnate har-
mony, weight on one curled leg, one leg and arm balletically extended, and
one arm poised in a curve as gracious and relaxed as a heron’s neck over his
nonchalant and impassive face. The balance is inward, energy concentrated
in the absolute moment. His opponent Master Yim has his own character-
istic pose: a huge iron weight has slipped at speed into his spine, as he stands
like a circus strongman, obdurate and unflinching in accepting this punish-
ment, protected by the magic of his “pugilist armor.” There is the unmis-
takable confrontation between the upright man whose arts and skills are not
for sale, and the forthright man, whose are. It is scarcely a challenge to read
off from their interface a criticism of the neoliberal capitalism of Guang-
dong, now the largest and fastest growing urban conglomeration in the
world, already past a population of seventy million, already beginning to
stifle in its own pollution. Skill, invention, craft are devalued when they are
riven away from the ethic of honor.
Stripped of the rituals of religious observance and divorced from its
function as official ideology of the Mandarin bureaucracy, Wong Fei Hung’s
Confucianism strikes as a straightforward code of ethical behavior whose im-
petus is toward comfort without excess, decency without self-righteousness,
and satisfaction grounded in peaceable coexistence with others who will
wish no harm if they are decently fed, clothed, and housed. It is a gentle-
man’s code, one that will be ridiculed in other films of Tsui Hark’s, but which
serves well here as counterfoil to the self-seeking amoral Yim and his great-
est skill: the ability to take a beating.
Wonder and Dream
The struggles for modernity, historicity, identity, and nationhood enacted
in 1942, Honneamise,and Once Upon a Timecan draw on the immense well-
springs of tradition in India, Japan, and China. They also share the fact that
each boasts a large, mature film industry that has explored that history as
| 322 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
2
|
myth, as epic, and as legend. Aotearoa New Zealand, whose double naming
indicates its precarious balancing of two cultures, has neither. Something
more like the Western is required: a narrative of origin. In his 1989 film The
Navigator(figs. 12.5, 12.6),Vincent Ward imagined a visionary history rife
with ambiguity: an allegory without a key; a prophecy of the present folded
into its own betrayal. Cinema is surely a time machine. So, in Ward’s ver-
sion, is history: a device rediscovered in an abandoned mine, a technology
for burrowing through time. This tentative moment of imagining nation-
hood, in a young country that has still not abandoned its colonizer’s flag or
its sovereign’s face on its currency, is bounded in time. In the years since the
film’s release, Aotearoa has reoriented toward the Asia Pacific, recognizing
the triumph of geography. But the moment prior to that emerging con-
sciousness, the moment as it were of waking, is all the more fascinating for
its rarity and its ephemerality.
This film is an extended moment of realization, of firstness. As such it
is sunk in time like a stone in mud, or better still like the Wingèd Car of Ed
Dorn’s Gunslinger:“the space has nofront it’sAllrear” (Dorn 1975: np). It is
| 323 |
R
e
v
is
io
n
a
ry
F
ilm
|
| Figure 12.5 |
The Navigator:Griffin: figure-ground relation becomes figure-history relation.
a moment of wonder. Wonder is entirely bathed in time, in the instant of
“before.” The sublime stands above and beyond time, proposing good and
evil as equally ineffable and absolute—the nonnegotiable evil–sublime bina-
rism enacted in the television images of the September 11 events. Wonder,
on the other hand, is dialectical, and it is this dialectic that intrigues Ward’s
The Navigator.Wonder winks into existence only to eradicate itself, to insti-
gate the chain of understanding, and so to wipe out the first, marvelous
incomprehension with which we confront the world as familiar stranger.
Ward’s wonder, without a cause, emerges into the present without a past but,
unlike the sublime, equipped with a future in which its meaning will be
understood.
Understanding (if not the explanation) of the wonderful is always fu-
ture. In a remote medieval mining village in Cumbria, the young lad Grif-
fin has visions of a great church in a celestial city. Threatened by the advance
of the Black Death, the miners of the village follow the boy’s lead into aban-
doned workings, burrowing through the earth until they arrive, with no fur-
ther explanation, in twentieth-century Auckland. There they hoist a cross,
| 324 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
2
|
| Figure 12.6 |
The Navigator:the texture of history.
the “spike,” to the top of the cathedral, while the more bizarre elements of
the dreams become clear: an iron whale, a horse in a rowboat, a wind that
forces a man’s mouth into a voiceless scream... The boy’s eventual death
does not explain his vision, already miscellaneously (and wrongly) inter-
preted by his companions, but his miraculous sacrifice is braided in with
wonder’s dialectical other, monstrosity: the apparent betrayal of the village
to the plague. What makes this wonderful is its strange temporality, where
the greatest doubts settle on the existence of the modern city. Todorov sug-
gests that, confronted with an inexplicable event, we must choose between
deciding that the experience was illusory, or accepting its reality and there-
fore doubting the laws we assume to govern the world. “The fantastic oc-
cupies the duration of this uncertainty” (Todorov 1973: 25). Ward leaves
unclosed the duration of uncertainty, a condition proper to a country whose
not-yet existence makes it entirely wonderful.
Reading Bazin against himself, we might say film arrives at Being by
erasing history in order to confirm the contemporary world in its perpetual
present, as it appears in the eye of God. Cinema provides the technical as
well as metaphorical bases for the mosaic montage of events that constitutes
history as static residue, as standing-reserve: the exemplary medium for the
commodification of time. Though a cinema ticket buys only the right to a
seat for a specified duration, the experience on offer erases geography as
surely as it passes time. From R.W. Paul’s 1895 patent for a cinematic time
machine (Barnes 1976: 37–40; Chanan 1980: 226) to IMAX, film inaugu-
rates the placeless, timeless domain of accelerated modernity.
And yet cinema’s attraction for audiences rests on the provision of place
and duration. In varying ways total, realist, and classical film construct
formed and formal symmetries, closed and enclosing diegeses that please
through their difference from the anarchy of production, the chaos of ur-
banism, the drift of subjectivity and the shock of the new, constructing a ho-
listic experience out of the fragmented visions of everyday life and diurnal
fantasy. The Navigatordoes not offer a satisfying edifice of ordered coher-
ence, totality, or surface. It images the real as fantastic, as when the harsh
winter mountains of New Zealand’s South Island double for Cumbria in
stark black and white (Ward 1990: 159–161), rendering the world not as
presence but as a process trembling on the brink of becoming. This is not
totality but a relation to infinity, to possibilities branching out from any
moment of the present. Its time is not messianic, its potentiality not filled in
| 325 |
R
e
v
is
io
n
a
ry
F
ilm
|
by a single, defining, sublime, extrahistorical stroke. Rather The Navigator
opens history as secular futurity, bereft of certainty though guided by de-
terminations from the accumulations of the past. Chance has its role to play,
as it does in melodrama and surrealism. Coincidence, entirely proper to
Virilio’s age of the accident, is no more insubstantial than the vision that
guides or the knowledge that must be analyzed and critiqued if it is to retain
the status of knowledge—and which therefore must always be, like a vision,
partial, temporary, and local.
Unhappily deprived of past and future, the film investigates the dimen-
sionality of the present: as Hansen writes, drawing on Kracauer’s sense of
cinema as alternative public sphere, cinema “engaged the contradictions
ofmodernity at the level of the senses, the level at which the impact of mod-
ern technology on human experience was most palpable and irreversible”
(Hansen 2000: 342). Ward’s medievals are alienated, but their story is not
one of lost wholeness. Rather, wholeness is deferred, and they are alienated
not from their history or traditions but from their future, their unknown,
unnamed capabilities. This is how the boy, particularly, finds himself in the
dialectical previsionary state of remembering the future. Because he is me-
dieval, that memory incorporates not the unrememberable but in any case
contingent moment of dying, but instead the determined ritual time of bur-
ial, not the event but the sign of the event, a sign that, rather like Deleuze’s
crystalline description, “stands for its object, replaces it, both creates and
erases it” (Deleuze 1989: 126). In Griffin’s vision, the sign of death is future-
perfect: it will have happened. In this sense the boy shares God’s atemporal
view. But the vision is without meaning, its thirdness a blur, and the film’s
historical work will be to unravel the secondness, the system of objects and
events that will bring that meaning into existence, a cinematic task. Between
divine destiny and human work lies the wonder of a child blinking into vi-
sion or a nation into history.
The vision, a flashback that is also a flashforward, works at the level of
this schiz, opening a space at once of panic and contemplation in the char-
acters’ present. Here the threatened failure of interpretation—the mis-
recognition of the gauntlet that leads to the misidentification of the
sacrificial victim—belongs specifically to that present. But so does the vi-
sion of the coffin sinking into the lake. The boy’s vision includes a fragment
of posthumous futurity—the sole guarantee that what he sees is neither past
| 326 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
2
|
nor present. The unthinkable paradox that cinema can furnish beyond
words is this future vision whose subject is dead. Like the point of view shot
in Dreyer’s Vampyrseen from the perspective of a corpse (Nash 1976), this
drags us into an impossible, paralogical space within the timeless time and
placeless place of viewing. A further paradox, common to cinema, evolves
from the mismatched time of story and projection. We live in the charac-
ters’ future, and now even in the future of the modern foundry workers who
help the travelers on their quest (the panorama of the city antedates Auck-
land’s signature skyscraper, the Skytower). The coffin vision, then, exists
without any of the times available to an audience today, a purely cinematic
temporality betwixt and between Cumbria and Aotearoa. This death, far
from a total event closing off the narrative and its telling, is instead the ob-
jective through which pass into focus all the temporal rays of the filmic sit-
uation: a gateway.
Wonder is the shared and common form of amazement, and it arrives
in the communication of awe, not in its silenced adoration. Wonder arises
from an instinctive appreciation of the universe as awesome, an instinct that
in some ages is realized as spirituality or mysticism, and which even in a sec-
ular world refuses to be swept away. To some extent, the Hollywood sublime
is an example of the return of the repressed: an instinct turned down by left
and right secularists alike, which nonetheless returns in apparently unen-
durable intensity. It is this inexplicable intensity on which the Hollywood
sublime feeds. By contrast, Ward’s film explores the dynamic interplay of
impression and expression, as fascinated by the scamper of emotions over a
child’s face as in the sight that evokes them. This is communicable. Death,
the quintessential unspeakable that in Heidegger as in so much twentieth-
century thinking both sums communication and inaugurates it, is here
moved into another position in discourse. When discourse no longer cen-
ters on the verbal, death no longer concentrates existence as its emanation.
The recording angel of cinema does not respect finality, condensing pho-
tography’s ability to see beyond the grave (Gunning 1995a) and radio’s to
enquire into the haunting voices of the dead (Morales 1993; Sconce 2000).
Lefebvre’s (1991) contestation that space is always produced stands true
of time. The universe (and therefore film), the physicists tell us, is composed
of matter, energy, and information. But the constitution of the film as mean-
ingful involves a fourth dimension, that of communication, and it is in
| 327 |
R
e
v
is
io
n
a
ry
F
ilm
|
communication that time and space are constructed or produced. Homolo-
gies with the physical world are misleading: human regimes of communica-
tion are not informational in the physical sense. Their characteristic form is
fluid, and they are not homeostatic. Cinematic materiality appears null—
film appears immaterial—only because, like any abstraction, it is the result
of a collision of materials. The flicker of light reflecting on the depthless
sheet of the screen is matter in the state of equilibrium, the zero of random
movement that you can see by walking up to the screen during projection
(or examining a TV screen with a magnifying glass). It informs in the cut,
the inward organization of indefinite movement that unifies into objects.
Energy in the cinema is the production of signifiers, and it is here that the
dialectic of random equilibrium and unification is necessary, for from it
alone can come definite but infinite trajectories of meaning, the excess of
signifiers in which, like nature for the “savage mind,” the cinema excels for
the modern. Film operates, like all human communications, on a number of
timescales, from the near-instantaneity of celnet pict messaging to the slow
passage of shipborne trade, and slower still the passage of ideas from gener-
ations long dead in altered landscapes, pedigree beasts, technologized dead
labour. Film renders physical the processes of communication: giving them
dimensionality, structuring their energy as objects, informing their multiple
temporalities.
Genetic data, bits of biological information, are far slower to evolve
than ideas because they lacks the communicative function of betrayal. The
Navigatorbetrays its viewer by representing the narrative as a story told in
the mine; the boy Griffin is deceived by Conor, who has dissimulated his in-
fection to the village; the plague cheats Conor by passing him over with
nothing but scars; and the vision has tricked Griffin by taking him not once
but twice, at the cathedral and now, in the dawn in which the angel of death
was to have passed over, seizing him as the only victim of its passage. Most
of all, the vision betrays all those who participate in it by bringing a salva-
tion in which none has any faith. Darwin’s world has no option but to speak
truth. The human universe is a patchwork palimpsest of degradations, dog-
mas, fictions, lies, misunderstandings, coincidental signs, and random ges-
tures. The travelers’ first sight of Auckland is at once a vision of the City of
God and of Pandemonium,3a massive machinery of mutation and evolution.
Monsters and wonders are its ineluctable outcome.
| 328 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
2
|
Today, as the nation-state’s legitimations wither (Habermas 2001b),
one remaining role for the state is the construction of identity, a task explicit
in the constitution of the New Zealand Film Commission, the film’s cofunder.
As Huyssen (2000) argues, memory has become an affair of state, from the
musealization of culture to reconciliation tribunals, the “sorry” campaign in
Australia and the negotiations over the Treaty of Waitangi in Aotearoa New
Zealand. No longer monopolist of violence, the state is now sole agent of
legitimate rememoration. The normalization of language (Balibar and La-
porte 1974) and the role of print (Anderson 1983) disguise the contempo-
rary truth that spoken and written words fail to communicate across
intercultural divides. Cinema proposes not the visual but the process of
making, and making physical, as utopian alternative to linguistic exchange.
In one important scene, the time-travelers come to an Auckland foundry to
cast their copper. Although the audience understands both sides of the dis-
cussion, the dialogue makes it clear that the New Zealanders cannot com-
prehend the Cumbrian dialogue. But both crews understand the praxis of
smelting and pouring into moulds. The literate culture of the West has
clung for too long to the primacy of language, a universal in our models
of dialogue. Ward’s film intimates the utopian moment of intercultural
communication via another mediation: that of making. Making transcends
ostensible borderlines separating languages, cultures, times, and places,
challenging the universality of language with what Mignolo calls “diversal-
ity,” “the relentless practice of critical and dialogical cosmopolitanism rather
than a blueprint of a future and ideal society projected from a single point
of view” (Mignolo 2000: 744). The emphasis falls on “practice”: on the par-
ticulars of practical knowledge rather than the universals of abstraction.
The medieval word comes to the rescue: smithing was a “mystery,” a craft
guarded by the guild, whence its modern sense of secret knowledge, but first
of all it was a set of skills that permeated the boundaries between cultures
and made the making of a world possible and thinkable. The common,
shared work of making is the foundation of Ward’s utopia.
The journey to the future anterior is both escape and arrival. Equipped
with a medieval sense of wonder, the travelers marvel but are never thereby
either accommodated into the strange world they visit, nor shifted from
their own understanding of who, what, where, and when they are. Only how
they live is altered, but not by the arrival: rather by the vision and its betrayal.
| 329 |
R
e
v
is
io
n
a
ry
F
ilm
|
This twist in the construction of history as special effect is previsionary
rather than revisionary, and it plays on the impossible synchronicity of the
recorded image to identify the moment of viewing with wonder at the un-
heard of and the unforeseen. When the film shows us the boy as storyteller
completing the tale of the journey as though it had never happened, we are
in the presence of historiography. When we recognize the final fragment of
flashforward as foreknowledge, we understand the gap between vision and
dream. Vision is a wonder, catapulted from an otherwhere or otherwhen,
carrying the promise of a fulfillment that is always future. A dream is already
a sign, already heavy with meaning, already determined by the dreamer’s
communicative world.
The film’s final betrayal, when the image of the silver cross sinking be-
neath the black waters is identified as the boy’s coffin, betrays because it an-
chors the vision in a truth it possesses despite itself. History, in as much as
it is the vehicle that gives nationhood imaginative meaning, should always
be such: a history of the future more than a vision of the past. In the neo-
baroque and digital cinemas of destiny, we stand near the end of the jour-
ney; in revisionary and even more so in previsionary cinemas, we stand at
the beginning.
| 330 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
2
|
Audiencing
the junk merchant does not sell his product to the consumer, he sells
the consumer to his product
—William S. Burroughs1
Cosmopolis
It remains for us to watch for the signs of the next twist, the resolution of the
dialectical impasse that confronts the methodical ordering of reference with
the dematerialization of liberty, the pursuit of narcissism with the dis-
mantling of reality, the unhappy dialectic of peace and freedom with which
the superpowers faced each other in the last years of the Cold War, two
theses that were and are not only mutually but internally contradictory. Our
most powerful cinema confronts and enacts these themes, just as our most
popular raises them to soothe the ragged heart they lacerate. The BBC’s old
motto, “Let nation speak peace unto nation,” falls foul of this dialectic, and
once again, speech is the culprit.
Never has the need for intercultural dialogue been so necessary. Rarely
have the conditions for it happening seemed so remote. This final chapter
looks at some films that have tried to win a global audience, and which, in
the process, have had to invent as a special effect an address to the audience
that might constitute it as global. Is this a vain enterprise? Is it only enter-
prise, with no utopian content whatsoever? Isn’t the purpose of postideo-
logical film entirely changed from the days in which it might have been
possible, as it was for Griffith, to imagine cinema as universal language
(Hansen 1991)? After all, Luhmann argues that “It is certainly true to say
that entertainment is one component of modern leisure culture, charged
13
COSMOPOLITAN FILM
| |
with the function of destroying superfluous time” (Luhmann 2000: 51). In
the end, isn’t that all the attempts to formulate a global cinema comes down
to—a radical and sublime eradication of any time that is not otherwise de-
voted to the production of profit, a process in which human being is in-
creasingly irrelevant?
The audience is the last unquestioned zone of media theory. There is
the audience. Empirical market research gives us statistical data of more or
less, often less, reliability. Against all experience, it equates pleasure and
meaning with the purchase of tickets. There is little between the test audi-
ence for films shown ahead of release with a view to recutting or reshooting,
and the raw box-office statistics, open to all kinds of tricky recalculation since
the box-office gross is the final accounting mechanism on the back of which
all partners in a film get paid.
Nonetheless, media studies never doubts the existence of an audience.
Reconceptualized in the 1970s and 1980s by David Morley (1980, 1987),
audiences began to be understood academically in more sociological terms:
as people rather than statistics. Although this approach solved, for a time,
the problem of inferring audience responses from textual practices, it did
not get beyond challenging the practice of audience analysis. Changing the
method from large-scale but shallow market research to small-scale, depth
interactions revealed a great deal—much of it of use to advertisers and com-
mercial TV operators. But the object “audience” remained in place, and if
anything in an even stronger ideological position than it occupied before in
the rationalizations that began in the premise of “giving the people what
they want.” The problem lay in the hypostasis of “the people,” and the iden-
tification of the people with the audience.
John Hartley gives a powerful analysis of the proposition in the brief es-
say entitled “Public-ity” that introduces his book The Politics of Pictures.The
public, he argues, exists only as a discursive effect. Public life is conducted
so thoroughly in media forms, that
the audience for popular media is a discursive production too; an “invisible fic-
tion” produced and deployed by the institutions which have most to gain from
its existence. If the public and the audience are indeed discursive productions,
there’s not much point in barging into people’s living rooms to watch them
watching telly. Better to look at the discursive production of audienceship, and
to reconceptualize the activity people undertake in their homes as something
| 332 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
3
|
neither autonomous nor authentic but the end product of a discursive strategy
in which viewers are participants but not original sources. (Hartley 1992: 9–10)
Viewers exist only as viewers of.There is little point attempting to imag-
ine a person that exists prior to and outside the communicative webs of
contemporary mediation because there is no such person. Personage is, in
contemporary life, a function of mediation. So too of course is viewership,
audienceship. The entity “audience” exists as the object of an activity whose
purpose is in part simply to produce it. At the level of the nation, the level
at which modern politics still operates, television has been the privileged
medium, especially in countries like the U.K. where terrestrial channels still
serve a nationalizing purpose. This is why it is so typical that Aotearoa New
Zealand’s most impressive work of national mythology should have taken the
form of a television documentary (Perrott 2002). The cinema, however,
seeks its audiences by and large internationally, for commercial, ideological,
or cultural reasons. Hartley’s proposed methodology is therefore even more
applicable to contemporary cinema: “it is not a question of contrasting a real
public with the illusory media (almost vice versa, in fact)” (Hartley 1992: 2).
The audience for a particular movie is as much a construct as its author.
“Authorship” is never the property of an individual: it is an institutional and
discursive function. No one—not Renoir, not Peckinpah, not Ward—makes
a film alone. Nor does any film spring unheralded from the mind of a cre-
ator: it draws on myriad technologies and techniques to apply them to a cer-
tain, determinate film. Authorship may also be seen as a kind of legal and
bibliographic fiction, a way of organizing the vast array of texts into search-
able order (Foucault 1979) and of ascribing ownership in copyright (Gaines
1992; Coombe 1998). Likewise, no audience comes to a film ignorant of
cinema, or of their role in realizing it. The task of cinema is to deliver audi-
ences to films, and the task of audiences is to constitute films as objects of
consumption.
Undoubtedly the intersection of previous mediations constructs a spec-
trum of viewing positions (for example, Batman fans, Prince fans, people
who care little for either or both but caught the promotions or the word-of-
mouth [Bacon-Smith and Yarborough 1991: 90–91]). Buying the ticket and
entering the auditorium are acts of surrender to the economic and filmic
machinery of cinema. Watching (as opposed to necking or walking out) is
asurrender to the film itself. Ethnographic research on film, however, is
| 333 |
C
o
sm
op
o
l
it
an
F
i
lm
|
always after the fact, never conducted where spectatorship happens, in the
cinema itself where any attempt to elicit a response ruins the experience it
tries to capture. Cinema has its own uncertainty principle.
Acceptable behaviors in cinemas vary from place to place (and show-
time to showtime: children’s matinees, evening performances, midnight
screenings) but they are always shaped by acceptability, a correct way to
watch a film. To become audience, we have to submit to that discipline,
orknowingly transgress it. To paraphrase Marx, people make themselves
audiences, but not under conditions of their own choosing. A population
becomes an audience not so much by an act of will—the argument of free-
enterprise capitalism—nor by acts of negotiation—the culturalist ap-
proach—as in an agreement to be mediated, the cinema audience no less
than the television spectator. In the closed market for TV ratings in the
United States, argues Eileen Meehan, “advertisers, networks, and now cable
channels buy ratings from a ratings firm whose success rests on the ability
to serve continuities in demand, to manipulate discontinuities through
measurement practices, and to design measurement practice[s] as strategies
for market control. This means that ratings and the commodity audience
are manufactured in the strictest sense of the word” (1990: 132).
The AC Nielsen ratings system analyzed by Meehan derives its figures
from “people meters” installed exclusively in cabled homes, restricting the
sample to a grouping that shares nothing but its meterage, and lacking the
usual social-scientific backdrop of either random or representative sampling.
This exclusive audience forms the commodity for which advertisers pay and
networks compete—this audience that is truly commodified. Yet with ticket
sales as a guide, cinema audiences are more easily tracked in the mass,
though the statistics of box-office take do not distinguish premium priced
seats from cheaper suburban sales and are designed to exclude the vast au-
dience for Indian, Chinese, and other cinemas from competition with the
box-office gross numbers for U.S. product. Not least since ticket sales fig-
ures are heavily touted in promotional campaigns for film releases, to be-
come an audience is to become a commodity.
To become an audience is also to become mediated. Economic agency
is now cultural consumption in a system where audiences mediate between
brand image and point of sale. More, our personal media histories, the back-
ground of TV programs, comics, movies, and games that we bring to our
selection of things to watch and ways to enjoy them “mediates our present
| 334 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
3
|
day desires and gives the past an imaginary status that strips away closure,
opening it up to personal (although culturally-mediated) fantasies” (Spigel
and Jenkins 1991: 142). The proviso about culturally mediated fantasies
indicates a double mediation: memory of past shows mediates mediated fan-
tasies. The personal fantasy, the intimate moment in which we are suppos-
edly most ourselves, is an effect of the processes of mediation. If it is also
true that economic exchange is a mode of communication thoroughly me-
diated by systems of fiscal transaction, a third mediation constructs the
audience, who are then mediated again as statistical evidence of success,
artistic or financial. When it comes to the manufacture of audiences, there
is no distinction between commodification and mediation, for the com-
modity is the single most characteristic mediating form of capitalism, and
capitalism itself is a vast system for constructing communicative webs, al-
beit webs that persistently fail to communicate more than the glamour of
the commodity and the brutality of exclusion from it.
In the age of globalization, it is not surprising that film production
should aim at maximizing its audiences by developing product that might
appeal to an even more diverse, global population. The construction of such
projects as The Matrixand Crouching Tiger, Hidden Dragoninvolves the in-
vention of a new form of audience, the global audience. As used in television
discourse, the phrase denotes the aggregate number of viewers tuning in to
worldwide media events like the Olympics, a critical number for example
inCoca Cola’s sponsorship for the company’s hometown Atlanta games.
Capital, “that most aggressively universalizing of categories” (Pollock et al.
2000: 586), globalizes by expanding the commodity relation into the man-
agement of planetary communication. Such management requires a media
formation of its own, the burgeoning discourse of management communi-
cation. This universally applicable map of efficiency in issuing commands,
recruiting creativity, and monitoring action is only one example of the cos-
mopolitanism of contemporary capital.
Commonly, “cosmopolitan” describes someone who is at home with
every cuisine, with all protocols of etiquette, who is at home in the world
and with its citizens. It was an élite formation, specific to the diplomat for a
hundred or two hundred years, the object of Kipling’s and Forster’s moral
fables on how to live correctly in India, the enviable suavity of James Bond.
The cosmopolite, whatever his or her origins, always knew a little place
around the corner. That special knowledge, however, could not survive the
| 335 |
C
o
sm
op
o
l
it
an
F
i
lm
|
expansion of capital into its own management, and cosmopolitanism has be-
come, over recent decades, a commodity, sold through travel guides, con-
sumed as hybrid cooking, branded and attached to cigarettes, soft drinks,
alcohol, and perfumes, hotel chains and news networks, and used to entice
an increasingly peripatetic managerial class. The consumer of this lifestyle
option, to use the marketing cant, was neighbor to the consumer of art-
house cinema, the refined, urbane inhabitant of other cultures, the incarna-
tion of neoliberalism’s pluralist multiculturalism. From the politics of
recognition (Taylor 1992) to the politics of inclusion (Habermas 1998), cos-
mopolitan intellectuals sought a peaceful, conflict-free assimilation of dif-
ference to the universal truths of the West, the forgiving embrace of the
commodity.
On the one hand, there is the drive to produce a class of global managers
with a cultural repertoire adequate to the needs of the system. On the other,
there is the imperial expansion of capital. The latter, which drives the film
business like any other, drives the construction of a cosmopolitan audience
for, especially, Hollywood film. Hollywood is not alone in this—offerings
from Hong Kong (The One, fig. 13.1)and India (Asoka) have attempted to
penetrate the highly protected U.S. internal market—but Hollywood is most
often a partner in such operations, backing cosmopolitanism both ways. The
cosmopolitan film commodity aims to achieve, in its pluralist way, the proj-
ect Wyndham Lewis once ascribed to Nietzsche: the popularization of aris-
tocratic attitudes (Lewis 1968: 114). The construction of cosmopolitan
audiences as a privileged, commodified mediation of spectatorship involves
the democratization of elitism.
Inseparable from the concept of globalization, informationalization de-
scribes the way in which communication has changed during the course of
the twentieth century, and its likely trajectories in the early twenty-first.
Mediated as it always is by material process, human communication has a
history. The mode of communication changes as its mediations alter. Since
the emergence of a world economy in the sixteenth century (Braudel 1984;
Wallerstein 1991), the dominant medium of human communication has
been money. During the last seventy years or so, that centrality has begun
to be displaced by information, understood here in its technical definition,
a structured pattern of data. Informationalization is the process through
which economic domination becomes information domination.
| 336 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
3
|
For example, as electronically traded, money itself is now a structured
pattern of data. So are demographics, data on earthquakes, the latest Holly-
wood blockbuster, a CD of Lata Mangeshkar, and this word-processed text.
The cosmopolitan commodity is not entirely mediated by money: money it-
self has become a commodity to be traded as data set, and the structure of
commodification has thus altered internally. The cosmopolitan lives in the
world as data set and is no longer afraid to recognize that fact, at least since
Gordon Gecko’s “Greed is good” speech in Wall Streetwon Michael Douglas
his Oscar. The politics of inclusion and the self-reflexive acceptance of me-
diation as data combine in the postmodern ironies of The Matrix, but they
also produce bizarre variants on the neobaroque in their quest for a magic
formula that will construct once and for all a global moviegoing public.
Commodification and mediation of audiences combine in cosmopolitan in-
formationalization: audience as data set.
Cosmopolitanism corresponds to informationalization because it oper-
ates in only one direction. The cosmopolitan is at home in the culture of the
| 337 |
C
o
sm
op
o
l
it
an
F
i
lm
|
| Figure 13.1 |
The One:afterThe Matrixstole martial arts for the blockbuster, Hong Kong steals sci-fieffects
for the martial arts film. Courtesy BFI Stills, Posters, and Designs.
other, but he does not offer the other the hospitality of his own home. To
the extent that cosmopolitanism arises as a cultural option in the era of im-
migration control, it is antiethical, in the sense proposed by Derrida, for
whom (drawing on the Greek meaning of the word ethos,home) “Insofar as
it has to do with the ethos, that is, the residence, one’s home, the familiar
place of dwelling, inasmuch as it is a manner of being there, the manner in
which we relate to ourselves and to others, to others as our own or foreign-
ers, ethics is hospitality” (2001: 16–17).
By abandoning the ethical commitment to hospitality, the cosmopoli-
tan abandons the ethics of the face-to-face, the ethics of communication.
The other becomes a data set, an object to be managed. But for this to be ac-
complished, the cosmopolitan manager must sacrifice his own place in com-
municative networks, must sacrifice what it is to be human. And in this way
the manager becomes the data stream and is more thoroughly mediated
than those to whom his media formation ascribes object status. Faced with
the invisible and inhuman task of identifying wholly with the managed
dataflows, this lonely solipsist takes on the formal tragedy of a secular age.
This is the figure who is so frequently preordained to the supreme sacrifice:
to become the secret savior of the world.
The Proletarianization of Consumption
Deleuze remembers a lecture of Maurice L’Herbier: “space and time be-
coming more and more expensive in the modern world, art had to make it-
self international industrial art, that is, cinema, in order to buyspace and
time” (Deleuze 1989: 78). For Deleuze, this is a first intimation of the emer-
gence of the time-image, the direct image of time unmediated by movement
he associates with the avant-garde cinemas of Antonioni, Resnais, and others.
Where time is money, money is a measure of time. In the informationaliza-
tion of the global economy, information is money, and money is a dataflow
whose value depends on its approximation to instantaneity. Deleuze be-
lieves that the direct time-image liberates cinema from the sensory-motor
bonds of the movement image, but as the time image approaches asymptot-
ically toward stillness, as in Syberberg, it approaches equally the condition
of the sublime. In Deleuze’s analysis, this approach connotes the achieve-
ment of a liberation from time in the films he prizes. On the other hand, if
it is the case, as previous chapters have argued, that the sublime has become
a trope in the commercial cinema in which historical process is annihilated,
| 338 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
3
|
then we should read the achievement of the time-image as merely paving the
way for the cinematic institutionalization of the sublime end of history.
Sublimity comes as the end, the absent center of communication.
Mirroring both poststructural constitutive absence and Heideggerian being-
toward-death, the sublime reconforms both the concept and the phenome-
non of experience to its own singularity. Experience may have been founded
historically in the embodied face-to-face encounter. Today, although med-
iation remains material, experience is increasingly abstracted from the
physical danger that obtains in any face-to-face situation (the Hegelian
master-slave dialectic, Levinas’s ethics as first philosophy). The Hollywood
sublime is offered neither as a means nor as a practical moment of the me-
diation process, but as an instantaneous, apparently unmediated and riskless
affect enjoyed not for its communicative intent but first for itself, and more
recently as the invisible core of a virtual diegesis designed to sublate the be-
coming of spectators into itself.
The global audience is dimensionless. To the extent that it succumbs to
the global media product, and more specifically to the extent that it is a func-
tion of information flows displacing even money (or reconfiguring money
and the commodity form as information), the sublime effect deprives the
global audience of space and time. The audience, as commodity, becomes
that full void of the commodity fetish that, as secret core, goal, and medium
of informational capital, it must be.
At the extreme of subsumption to the diegetic is subsumption to the
singularity of the sublime. The construction of binarism is mere paradox:
evil disappears into the anethical absolution of difference that is the sub-
lime. Evil at the moment of global audience, that evil so utterly abjected in
the blockbuster cosmology, turns out to be only an aspect of the informe,
only the unspeakably vile as the sublime is the unspeakably lofty. Sublime
and evil are lifted into infinite unity in the “unspeakable,” the extraction
from communication that also extracts from history.
Since what we occupy is space-time, the global audience is also banished
from geography. The partition of the world into a cartographic grid of time
zones, currency zones, zip and postal codes, informational spaces (Curry
1998) deprives location of its “thereness,” at least in the information econ-
omy. The more data fuses with money, the less locality bears on consump-
tion, save only as a numerical parameter of consumption. As space sheds its
sensuous particularity—its use value—in exchange for information value,
| 339 |
C
o
sm
op
o
l
it
an
F
i
lm
|
it loses its dimensionality to become the entirely communicable object of
strategic market planning. To that extent, space ceases to be produced, as it
still was when Lefebvre wrote (1991), and begins instead to be consumed,
not so much by its inhabitants, but by those whose charge it is to extract its
surplus value. That value is now attached not, again, to production but to
consumption, the privileged site of profit. Insofar as the audience is global,
it is removed from space. Insofar as it is audience, it is removed from time.
Insofar as they are global, differences are assimilated into the democratized
elitism of the cosmopolitan, and insofar as it is removed from space and
time, the cosmopolitan is ineffable.
Film history acts out the transition from production economies to
consumer economies, from the object commodity to the information com-
modity, and from the trade in objects to the trade in audiences. In the nine-
teenth century labor became proletarianized. The factory became the type
of work discipline, the worker became an alienated object, a cog in the ma-
chine, at once the feared and despised tool of the factory (the “hand”) and
the archetype of a newly socialized humanity (Wollen 1988). At the heart
ofthe alienation that Lukacs (1971) understood as the core experience of
proletarianization lay work discipline (Marx 1976: 544–553). But work dis-
cipline would not remain unique to the factories. It enters the office trades
in the late nineteenth and the retail trades in the mid-twentieth centuries
with the mechanization of data entry, record keeping, and arithmetic, stock-
keeping and telling, the computerization of barcodes and electronic point-
of-sale technologies. It remains associated with the intensive gendering of
employment, with the division of labor, with deskilling (the transformation
of living labor skills into dead labor, fixed capital, technology), with man-
agerialism and with New Age–inspired variants on human resource man-
agement (Ross 1991).
In the twentieth century, consumption became proletarianized. The
origins of the process can be traced back to the last decade of the nineteenth
century and the rise of the department store, the invention of the female
flâneur, the impact of cheap colonial materials on the fashion industry, and
the rise of advertising (Peiss 1986; Rappaport 1995; Richards 1990; Wil-
liams 1982; Wilson 1985). These entrepreneurial innovations became eco-
nomic doctrine in the wake of the Great Depression of the early 1930s,
when Keynesianism in its various forms descried the priority of market de-
velopment if capital were to survive. Unsurprisingly, the first industries to
| 340 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
3
|
be hit by this reorganization of capital toward a market-driven model were
the emergent broadcasting industries. In the United States of the 1930s, then
the leading industrial economy, radio broadcasting was the first business to
be shaped by a new paradigm: the sale of consumers. At the beginning of the
new century, few countries retained advertising-free, government-run
channels. All others were operated on the basic principle of delivering audi-
ences to advertisers.
Just as the proletarianization of the workforce demanded work disci-
pline, the proletarianization of consumption demands consumer discipline.
For early broadcasters and still today for comparable industries such as do-
mestic energy, consumer discipline need only be organized in the mass.
Early consumer discipline did not require that individual consumers govern
their activities to match the temporal and spatial organization of produc-
tion, at least not in the way that the factory worker had to internalize the dis-
cipline imposed by the rhythms of the machinery. Consumption as a mass
activity followed only the broad outlines laid down by the media, such as
attending during prime time. But with the advancing division of consump-
tion, especially since the Reaganomic and Thatcherite era of savage deregu-
lation, into specialized zones, times, channels, and media, the mass audience
no longer serves the needs of capital. Consumption must be organized. The
proliferation of channels, and later of media (cable, satellite, video, DVD,
remote control, computer games, internet, and “convergent media”), struc-
tures the consuming day according to constructions of consumers as demo-
graphic classes or, in the more polite and apolitical language of the 1990s,
lifestyle groups. The advertising industry, which treats each publication as
a distinct medium, thus structures campaigns according to the success of a
radio channel, a newspaper, a magazine, or a TV program in attracting the
attention of a definable audience type.
The consumer is charged with three disciplinary tasks: recognizing
which type of consumer she is, unearthing the correct media for her lifestyle
group, and attending to the correct media in the correct ways. During the
1980s, research demonstrated the minimal attention paid by viewers to tele-
vision (Cumberbatch and Howitt 1989). In these circumstances, merely
being in the domestic space with the television turned on was no longer
adequate to attract advertising spend. The new commodity was no longer
absolute numbers, nor even shares of a specific lifestyle group, but levels of
attention. Now that attention is clearly the commodity exchanged in the
| 341 |
C
o
sm
op
o
l
it
an
F
i
lm
|
advertising business, the job of consumers has become more demanding:
they must not only note the existence of media designed for them, but also
give them appropriate degrees of attention according to the exchange value
they attract.
Some groups are poorly disciplined. Early adopters are notoriously hard
to attract and even harder to keep. They will latch onto a program, for ex-
ample, before its exchange value has been fixed, guaranteeing that its price
rises. However, once the exchange value has been determined on the basis
that it brings with it the valuable attention of early adopters, they have
moved on, bored, or, under the influence of an elite conception of their own
cultural capital, decrying the now expensive medium as popularized.
Other groups are simply not valuable. Those that devote the most at-
tention to advertising media—the unemployed, the elderly, the poor—de-
value their attention by overexerting it. Their lack of consumer discipline,
like their supposed lack of work discipline, discriminates against their ex-
change value in ways even more significant than their cultural kudos. Other
undisciplined consumption, such as aspirational viewing or slumming, like-
wise stirs rumblings, and even precipitates radical actions like the Chanel
No. 5 campaign designed to lose the product’s new downmarket buyers to
retain the cachet of exclusivity on which its fortunes were founded. This is
an exemplary form of disciplinary action against the abuse of consumption
by consumers.
An immediate consequence of informationalization is then that the
means of production no longer holds pole position in mediated formations.
Attempts to seize control of the means of production are unable to alter the
fundamental logic of consumerism: that the highest value is the rapt atten-
tion of the target audience. Work of excellence in television, for example,
can only either more successfully target a lifestyle group, or best of all serve
to identify a previously unknown and distinctive lifestyle cluster on behalf
of the trade in attention. The media industries, narrowly defined, were only
the first to recognize that the customer base is a tradable asset, now a truism
of business mergers and acquisitions. They were the first to reveal the cen-
trality of distribution and its preeminence over production. Distribution
companies trade in structured knowledge about suppliers and consumers
and the ability to assemble that knowledge into strategic spatiotemporal or-
ganizations. These organizations convert products into media and con-
sumers into audiences.
| 342 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
3
|
The globalization process that proceeds hand in hand with informa-
tionalization looks after the global export of consumer discipline as it did
over the global export of work discipline. An immediate effect has been the
proletarianization of family as the unit of consumption in Keynesianism.
Charged with both disciplining consumption and reproducing the social
consumer force, the family is increasingly prone to intergenerational dys-
function and divorce. In developing economies, the size of extended fami-
lies and their functionality comes under extreme pressure, falling to struggles
over the distinctions between tradition and modernity, the former charac-
terized by its conformity to older, production-era work discipline, the lat-
ter by its adjustment to contemporary consumer discipline. Expressed as
antonymy rather than dialectic, there can be no resolution in choosing be-
tween clinging to an outmoded local media formation, or adapting to the
demands of global informationalized consumerism.
Contradictions arise instead at the level of the failure of capital to fulfill
the desires it creates. Consumer discipline demands the division of con-
sumption between members of a family by age and gender, while demand-
ing that the family respond as a unit to the culturally specific disciplines we
know as tradition. So tradition itself is becoming a consumer discipline, as
in the use of Bombay movies in the subcontinental diaspora, where the tra-
dition loses its specificity, while acting as a contradictory demand on the
gender and age discipline otherwise binding on family consumption. At this
juncture, the proletarianization of consumption comes into contact with the
hyperindividualizing process, in the ideological formation of “it’s up to you
to discover your place in the world.” This is both an ideological demand
(know what you are supposed to consume and what kind of attention to pay
to it) and a philosophical statement concerning the nature of existence in
mediated formations. Each person has a destiny, which takes the form of a
task they must perform to secure happiness. That task is their fate and is
written into their lives.
The position of cinema in this process is anomalous. Cinema, a
nineteenth-century medium, emerges from the work-discipline model. It
is thus open to Pierre Bourdieu’s (1986) critique of cultural capital. Capital
accrues through the selection of a film to attend, and especially the generic
action of going out to see it, or even of checking it out from a video store,
an act that defines itself differentially, for example, as “not watching televi-
sion.” However, cinema in the twenty-first century is no longer exempt
| 343 |
C
o
sm
op
o
l
it
an
F
i
lm
|
from consumer disciplines that have encroached on the older elite forms.
The bourgeois model of cultural capital still operates among the bour-
geoisie, but the proletarianization of consumption removes the cultural ca-
chet from genre pictures. Although cultural capital was strong enough to
rescue from obscurity films whose genre was textually based (Western, film
noir, gangster), it is unable to resurrect for its uses those new, high-concept
genres in which the audience defines the film: chick flick, date movie, action
pic, slasher. Cinema release today is only a key moment in the marketing of
a lifestyle campaign embracing making-of documentaries, awards cere-
monies, junk food, stickers, and television spinoffs. In this sense, cinema
release organizes the problem of early adoption. Early adopters can be tar-
geted by their hunger for cultural capital, paying premium prices for early
access, functioning as word-of-mouth ambassadors, their resistance to con-
sumer discipline turned into a tool of consumption’s proletarianization of
the attention commodity.
These processes are caught in Jonathan Beller’s observation that “the
moving image represents an intermediate state, a synthesis between money
and other commodities. This synthetic space is the scene for the valorization
of capital through the realization of surplus value. Money-Commodity-
Money becomes Money-Image-Money as capital seeks a new armature to
administer the extraction of surplus value” (1998: 196; see also Beller 1995).
Discussing the transition from manufacture to factory labor, Marx notes that
“Along with the tool, the skill of the worker in handling it passes over to the
machine” (Marx 1976: 545); “Machinery is misused in order to transform the
worker, from his very childhood, into a part of a specialized machine” (ibid.:
547); “In handicrafts and manufacture, the worker makes use of a tool; in the
factory, the machine makes use of him” (ibid.: 548). Marx distinguishes be-
tween work—the specific human practices of making—and labor—its so-
cialized form that a worker sells to a capitalist. Work and communicating are
indistinguishable and intrinsic to human life. But the labor of mediation oc-
curs under specific historical conditions that transform it, in the global audi-
ence, into the salable commodity form of attention. This is Beller’s “new
armature” for the extraction of surplus value, and it involves the subordina-
tion of communication to the division of consumption proper to global me-
dia. The ability to create, to voice, to interpret, passes over from work to the
“specialized machine” of the media industry, the fixed capital in which the
sum of human communication is ossified into technique and technology, and
| 344 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
3
|
which finally makes use of the audience far more than the audience can make
use of the media.
The pure discipline of consumption is learned in the cinema as the
archetypal thief of time. That idleness which fired Pissarro’s utopian imag-
ination, that distraction which terrified the guardians of morality and civi-
lization in the 1890s, has become the central tool of the anaesthetics of
globalization. Under its wing, in the suspended time of audiencing, there is
no communication. It is a moot point as to whether globalization ever suc-
ceeds so completely, or ever does for more than a moment, or that it can re-
produce itself in the same way in different places and at different times. But
to the extent that it succeeds in realizing itself, there are no different times
and places, nor any differences within the global audience, which is pre-
cisely dedifferentiated in its construction as global, its differences assimi-
lated as otherness, a masala, into the indifferent sublime. The whole point
of global media product is to open itself up to multiple pleasures, to provide
not for polysemy—because its goal is insignificance—but polymorphous
and polyvalent delights.
So the global audience can, indeed must, draw on multiple and differ-
entiated media memories in all their mediation, to achieve their dedifferen-
tiation in the mechanized rememoration of the cinematic event. Like the
private sphere, private intellectual property, which in any case became cor-
porate property during the course of the twentieth century, is no longer ten-
able as a system of ownership and reward, either ethically or practically.
Almost every new medium of the later twentieth century has been both a
recording and a transmitting device: fax, tape cassette, video, computer. The
culture that has arisen, from Warhol’s silkscreens to DVD burners, treats
existing media as content for new media (Bolter and Grusin’s 1999 remedi-
ation thesis). A carefully constructed text like Casablancabecomes anitem of
vocabulary for a metadiscourse—such as this one, or a comic parody (Gum-
shoe), or an elaborate pastiche (Play It Again, Sam), or an homage (Barb Wire).
Despite technological attempts (DVD regional encoding and copyright
protection software) and legal wars (the U.S. government’s threatened em-
bargo on Chinese involvement in WTO until they agreed to action against
copy factories), the gray economy and the cultural practice of appropria-
tion, pastiche and mosaic remain typical of our era. The erosion of privacy,
private property, and private intellectual rights all coincide with attempts to
restrict and hoard the flow of communication in the informationalization
| 345 |
C
o
sm
op
o
l
it
an
F
i
lm
|
process. They involve a new configuration of the private individual, no
longer as citizen-producer, but as proletarian-consumer.
The old literary category of genre is an attempt to capture this effect of
mediated rememoration, but when we ask of The Matrixwhat genre it be-
longs to, we have to be ready to say “American film” as readily as “science
fiction,” “fight film” as quickly as “blockbuster,” “live-action anime” as swiftly
as “star vehicle.” Even the star comes freighting multiculturalism, a single
body embodying the multiple strands of North American “ethnicity” as
carefully selected for the global melting pot as the first crew of the U.S.S.
Enterprise (Feng 2001). There are pleasures in recognizing Alice in Wonder-
land, Jean Baudrillard, or the cityscapes of Sydney, the signature wirework
of Yuen Wo Ping and the comic book art of Geoff Durrow. Some of these
multiple pleasures compile together in complex harmonies, some are threads
worked through the textile of the film. Each is in the process subordinated
to the film and thence to its consumption on a global scale. The goal is in-
significance: the semantic corollary of instantaneity. Lacking dimension,
there is neither time nor space for meaning that can only take place, take
time. The significant other, however, is a key component of the insignificant
cosmopolitan, as difference is constitutive of indifference. The commer-
cialization of democracy, like the Nietzschean democratization of aristoc-
racy before it, is built not on extending elite privileges to wider and wider
populations but on the devaluation of experiences under regimens of com-
modification from exchange value to information value, a process in which
commodity status passes from objects to agents.
Esse est percipi: in Merleau-Ponty’s (1968) reading, to see is to be in-
scribed in the field of the visual. As a consequence of informationalization,
being changes alongside the mode of perception. When that perception be-
comes informational, that is, when the subject is the object for a perception
that is wholly or even partially informational, then being is also an informa-
tional phenomenon. When perception is no longer dominated by vision, as
a consequence of globalization (I am perceived as a customer by those who
are not geographically close enough to see me), the consequences of my ac-
tions are likewise invisible to me (taking place in some other part of the
world), and the aggregate of my actions with those of all the others acting
simultaneously deprives my actions, as far as they are dependent on my per-
ception of them, of their being in any ethical or aesthetic sense. And just as
my actions are deprived of consequences save as a moment of the aggregate
| 346 |
C
h
ap
te
r
1
3
|
of large-scale movements within the mediated formation, so my existence
becomes a matter of statistical probability.
In the fullest extension to date of cosmopolitan media, this is what an
audience does when it audiences: it erases itself from locality and historic-
ity. The dimensionlessness of informational existence alters the conditions
under which it is possible to be perceived. Becoming, which is integral to
communication, is arrested in the moment of being, a moment at which au-
diencing loses its dimensionality.
Neo Geo
In this as in so many ways, informationalization destabilizes the causality on
which Western modernity was founded. Anchors in the temporal dimen-
sion, which placed effects after their causes, are lost in the virtual instanta-
neity of the global media event. There is no instantaneous communication,
but by acting as if there were, the global audience severs the causal chains of
Western reason. In their place, we have the imagined spatial perception of
the hero, the chih of Li Mu Bai (Chow Yun Fat) in Crouching Tiger, Hidden
Dragon,of Neo (Keanu Reeves) in The Matrix.The prescient martial artist
occupies space rather than time, and that space is indistinguishable from any
other, a global geometry of arcs, lines, and trajectories in absolute space.
The reassertion of geography that Soja (1989) argued for has swung beyond
historico-geographical synthesis, space attaining the explanatory centrality
once proper to history, but only by shedding in the process geography’s
claim to local knowledge. Just as the auditorium disappears into placeless
darkness, the hypersenses of the hero flood into the abstract space of the
screen world. Likewise the diegesis has thoroughly absorbed the time of
narrative into a spatialized database of events whose preordained end always
guides the unfolding story into an ending that preexists it, as script, as rep-
etition, and as destiny. That abstract space already contains all the events
that will occur in it, which is how the hero can occupy it so totally, and in do-
ing so indicate to audiences how perfectly immersion in the medium of cin-
ema can be achieved.
This is one source of the ironic peculiarity of The Matrix(figs. 13.2,
13.3),a film that delivers a theory of ideology as cosmopolitan spectacle. As
Peter Lunenfeld (1999) noted in a post to |